diff options
Diffstat (limited to 'subnaturefn.otx')
-rw-r--r-- | subnaturefn.otx | 151 |
1 files changed, 0 insertions, 151 deletions
diff --git a/subnaturefn.otx b/subnaturefn.otx deleted file mode 100644 index 590baa5..0000000 --- a/subnaturefn.otx +++ /dev/null @@ -1,151 +0,0 @@ -FOOTNOTES - - - - - - - - - - -10 Ilya Prigogine, \et{Unity of Physical Laws and Levels of Description} in -M. Grene (editor) \jt{Interpretations of Life and Mind} (N.Y., Humanities -Press, 1971) and Ilya Prigogine and others \et{Thermodynamics of Evolution} in \jt{Physics Today} Vol. 25 #1, 1972, - -11 See John and Nancy Jack Todd, \bt{Tomorrow Is Our Permanent Address} (N.Y., Harper \& Row, 1980), p. 48. - -12 See Magoran Maruyama, \et{The Cybernetics: Deviation-Amplifying -Mutual Causal Processes} in \jt{American Scientist} \#51, 1963, and G. -Nicolis and I. Prigogine., \bt{Self-Organization in Non-Equilibrium Systems} - N.Y., Wiley Interscience, 1977). - -13 Lancelot L. Whyte, \et{Towards a Science of Form} in \jt{Hudson Review} -Vol 23 \#4, Winter 1970--71, reminds us of the sense in which the -natural world is a perceptually present world of spatial units from -molecules, crystals, organisms to solar systems and spiral nebul\ae. -How thesee spatial forms are generated---how these units and hierarchies -of units arise in nature---is the project of a morphic science. - -14 H.H. Pattee, \et{Complementarity vs. Reduction as Explanation of -Biological Complexity} in \jt{American Journal of Physiology} Vol. 236 -\#5, May 1979 where he argues: - -\Q{As a consequence of this property of information none of the rules -or constraints of information-processing systems can be reduced to -rate-dependent equations (to the structural laws of nature T.S.), and -therefore their descriptions cannot be integrated in time, as are rate -equations, to give the trajectory or behavior of the system. Such -informational constraints that have rate-independent alternative -structures are called nonintegrable\ld\ constraints. I would define -biological function as activity that is controlled or measured by -nonintegrable constraints.} -\Qs{(p. R244)} - -Both the explanatory laws of physics and the cybernetics of nonintegrable -constraints are essential for an account of biological organization. - -15 Bateson, \e{op. cit.}, p. 460. - -16 Ilya Prigogine, \bt{From Being to Becomuing: Time and Complexity in the -Phystcal Sciences} (San Francisco, WH. Freeman \& Co., 1980). - -17 G. Nicolis and I. Prigogine, \bt{Self-Organization inn Nonequilibrium -Systems: From Dissipative Structures to Order Through Fluctuations} -(N.Y., John Wiley \& Sons, 1977). - -18 See Marjorie Grene's \bt{Approaches to a Philosophical Biology} (N.Y., -Basic Books, 1965) for a discussion of Portmann's thinking in contrast -to other biological theorists who reject the Galileian primary qualities -as fundamental for organic life. For a brief introduction to Portmann -in English, see \et{Beyond Darwinism}in \jt{Commentary} XL (1965), pp. -31--41. - -19 This argument is developed below in Section 1V. - -20 J E. Lovelock, \bt{Gaia: A New Look at Life on Earth} (N.Y., Oxford -University Press, 1980) - -21 As indeed it has: See W. Ford Doolittle's review of Lovelock's book in -\jt{Co-Evolution Quarterly} \#29, Spring 1981, pp. 58ff. where the charge -that the feedback loops of Gaia are either created by natural selection -or, more likely to Doolittle, occur by chance. In response, we can return -to Prigogine's theory of dissipative structures: -\Q{We here propose an alternative description of prebiotic evolution. -The main idea is the possibility that a prebiological system may -evolve through a whole succession of transitions leading to a hierarchy -of more and more complex and organized states\ld\ As a -result, if the system is to be able to evolve through successive -instabilities, a mechanism must be developed whereby each new -transition favors further evolution by increasing the nonlinearity -and the distance from equilibrium. One obvious mechanism is that -each transition enables the system to increase the entropy production\ld} -\Qs{in \et{Thermodynamics of Evolution.} op. cit.} -However other reviewers of the book find the hypothesis tenable: See -K. Mellanby, \ht{New Scientist}, Oct 4, 1979; René Dubos, \jt{Nature}, Nov. 8, -1979; P Morrison, \jt{Scientific American}, March 1980. - -22 Erns Mayr, \et{Teleological and Teleonomic: A New Analysis} in \jt{Boston -Studies in the Philosophy of Science} 14 (1974), pp. 91--117. - -23 See EM. Lappe and J. Collins, \bt{Food First: The Myth of Scarcity} -(Ballantine Press, 1978). Also see \bt{The New International Division of -Labor} by F. Frobel, J. Heinrichs, D. Kreye (Cambridge University Press, -1980). - -24 See Gerald O. Barney, \bt{The Global 2000 Report to the President of -the U.S.: Vol. I The Summary Report} (NY., Pergamon Press, 1980). - -25 See Klaus Myer-Abich, \e{op. cit.} - -26 See Nicholas Georgesev-Roegen, \et{Inequality, Limits and Growth -from a Bio-Economic Viewpoint} in \jt{Review of Social Economy} V. 35, -Dec. 1977. - -26 See Serge Moscovici, \et{The Re-Enchantment of the World} in Norman -Birnbaum, \bt{Beyond the Crisis} (N.Y., Oxford University Press, -1977) for an analysis to which this paper is indebted. - -28 Raymond Dasmann, \et{Eco-Development} in the \jt{Planet Drum Review} -Vol. 1 \#2, Winter 1981. - -29 The term \dq{re-inhabitation} is taken from one of many local journals -which are now advocating the watershed as the natural eco-development -unit. The strategy is the use of a combination of oral history and local -ecological research as a place identification approach. See Paul Ryan's -\bt{Talking Wood: Living in the Passaic Watershed}, 1980 (Talking Wood, -PO.Box 364, Pompton Lakes, N.J. 07442). (But the original use of the -term was by Peter Berg in an article on \et{Re-Inhabitation of California} -in \jt{The Ecologist} in the early 1970's.) - -30 See Ivan Illich, \bt{Shadow Work} (Boston, Marion Boyers, 1981). - -31 For the notion of communicative rationalization, see Jurgen Habermas' -\et{Science and Technology as Ideology} in \bt{Toward a Rational Society} -(Boston, Beacon, 1970). However, this paper represents a critique of -Habermas' instrumental concept of natural science as well as his -orientation toward core nation-states of the West. For an account of -his notion of critical theory, see my \bt{The Critique of Domination} -(Boston, Beacon, 1974). - -32 Yet there is a sense in which the anarchist position's notion that theory -and practice is ultimately unified art the level of action which changes -reality cannot be faulted. Especially in the American context, there is -an affinity of anarcho-libertarianism and the historical symbols of -independence, self-determination, and self-reliance which are, at least -in origin, not reducible to possessive individualist idealizations of -self-interested production for gain. These American practices were -socially and ethically mediated by the ever-present American quest for -\dq{community.} An anarchist practice still permeates the American -movements for decentralization, ecology and approprate technology, -feminism, etc. There is also a unique amalgam of Old World utopian -surplus and contemporary anarchist, neo-primitivist, and nativist symbols - that simply mystifies Marxists---especially theoreticans who expect -social relations to dance according to their notion of reason. - -33 Russell Means, \et{For the World to Live, \sq{Europe} Must Die} in -\jr{Mother Jones}, Dec. 1980. - -34 Wendell Berry, \bt{The Unsettling of America: Culture and Agriculture} -(San Francisco, Sierra Club Books, 1977). - |