1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
1001
1002
1003
1004
1005
1006
1007
1008
1009
1010
1011
1012
1013
1014
1015
1016
1017
1018
1019
1020
1021
1022
1023
1024
1025
1026
1027
1028
1029
1030
1031
1032
1033
1034
1035
1036
1037
1038
1039
1040
1041
1042
1043
1044
1045
1046
1047
1048
1049
1050
1051
1052
1053
1054
1055
1056
1057
1058
1059
1060
1061
1062
1063
1064
1065
1066
1067
1068
1069
1070
1071
1072
1073
1074
1075
1076
1077
1078
1079
1080
1081
1082
1083
1084
1085
1086
1087
1088
1089
1090
1091
1092
1093
1094
1095
1096
1097
1098
1099
1100
1101
1102
1103
1104
1105
1106
1107
1108
1109
1110
1111
1112
1113
1114
1115
1116
1117
1118
1119
1120
1121
1122
1123
1124
1125
1126
1127
1128
1129
1130
1131
1132
1133
1134
1135
1136
1137
1138
1139
1140
1141
1142
1143
1144
1145
1146
1147
1148
1149
1150
1151
1152
1153
1154
1155
1156
1157
1158
1159
1160
1161
1162
1163
1164
1165
1166
1167
1168
1169
1170
1171
1172
1173
1174
1175
1176
1177
1178
1179
1180
1181
1182
1183
1184
1185
1186
1187
1188
1189
1190
1191
1192
1193
1194
1195
1196
1197
1198
1199
1200
1201
1202
1203
1204
1205
1206
1207
1208
1209
1210
|
\chapter{Philosophy Proper (\enquote{Version 3,} 1961)}
\subsection*{Chapter 1: Introduction (Revised, 1973)}
This monograph defines philosophy as such---philosophy proper---to be
an inquiry as to which beliefs are "true," or right. The right beliefs are
tentatively defined to be the beliefs one does not deceive oneself by holding.
Although beliefs will be regarded as mental acts, they will be identified by
their propositional formulations. Provisionally, beliefs may be taken as
corresponding to non-tautologous propositions.
Philosophy proper is an ultimate activity in the sense that no belief or
supposed knowledge is conceded to be above philosophical examination. It is
also an unavoidable activity in the sense that the notion of a belief, and the
notion of judging the truth of a belief, are intrinsic to common sense and the
natural language. Philosophers may not have achieved convincing results in
philosophy proper; but the question of which beliefs are right is
continuously posed for us even if we do not respect the way in which
philosophers have dealt with it.
All of the obstacles to philosophy proper arise because beliefs are
normally held in order to satisfy non-cognitive needs. It will be heipful to
examine this situation at some length. However, nothing can be done here
beyond examining the situation. It is already clear that the interest of this
monograph in beliefs is cognitive. It would be inappropriate to try to gain
approval for philosophy proper by appealing to the values of those who hold
beliefs in order to satisfy non-cognitive needs.
it is implicit in beliefs that they correspond to cognitive claims, that
they are subject to being judged true or false, and that their value rests on
their truth. Nevertheless, beliefs can and do satisfy non-cognitive needs,
quite apart from whether they are true. In order for a belief to satisfy some
non-cognitive need, it is not necessary for the belief to be true; it merely has
to be held. Concern with the ultimate philosophical validity of beliefs is rare.
Concern with beliefs is normally concern with their ability to satisfy
non-cognitive needs.
To be specific, the literature of credulity contains remarks such as "I
could not stand to live if I did not believe so-and-so," or "Even if so-and-so is
true I don't want to know it." These remarks manifest the needs with which
we are concerned. To take note of these remarks is already to uncover a level
of self-deception. It is important to realize that this self-deception is explicit
and self-admitted. To recognize it has nothing to do with imputing
subconscious motives to behavior, as is done in psychoanalysis. Further, to
recognize it is by no means to advance a theory of the ultimate origin of
beliefs, a theory which would presuppose a judgment as to the philosophical
validity of the beliefs. To theorize that the ultimate origin of beliefs lies in
the denial of frustrating experiences, or in primal anxieties which are
alleviated by mythological inventions, would be inappropriate when we have
not even begun our properly philosophical inquiry. The only self-deceptions
being considered here are admitted self-deceptions.
A partial classification of the circumstances in which beliefs are held for
non-cognitive reasons follows.
\begin{enumerate}
\item Beliefs may be directly tied to one's morale. "I couldn't stand to live if I didn't believe in God." "If President Nixon is guilty I don't want to know it."
\item One may believe for reasons of conformity. The conversion of Jews to Catholicism in late medieval Spain was an extreme example.
\item The American philosopher Santayana said that he believed in Catholicism for esthetic reasons.
\item Moral doctrines are sometimes justified on the grounds of their efficacy in maintaining public order, rather than their philosophical validity.
\item A more complicated and more interesting situation arises when one
who claims to be engaged in a cognitive inquiry somehow circumscribes the
inquiry so as to ensure in advance that it will yield certain preferred results.
Such a circumscribed inquiry will be called "theologizing," in recognition of
the archetypal activity in this category.
When we raise the question of whether the natural sciences are
instances of theologizing, it becomes apparent that the issue of non-cognitive
motives for beliefs is no light matter. According to writers on the scientific
method such as A. d'Abro, the scientist is compelled to operate as if he
believed in the "real existence of a real absolute objective universe---a
common objective world, one existing independently of the observer who
discovers it bit by bit." The scientist holds this belief, even though it is a
commonplace of college philosophy courses that it is unprovable, because he
must do so in order to get on to the sort of results he considers desirable.
The scientist claims to be engaged in a cognitive inquiry; yet the inquiry
begins with an act of faith which it is impermissible to scrutinize. It follows
that science is an instance of theologizing. If scientists cannot welcome a
demonstration that their "metaphysical" presuppositions are invalid, then
their interest in science cannot be cognitive.
The scientist's non-cognitive motive for believing differs from the
non-cognitive motives described earlier in one notable respect. Each of the
non-cognitive needs described earlier required a given belief, and could not
be satisfied by that belief's negation. But inside a science's circumscribed
area of inquiry, the scientist can welcome the establishment of either of two
contradictory propositions; in other words, his non-cognitive need can be
satisfied by either proposition. It is in this sense that he can impartially test
or decide between two propositions, or make new discoveries. On the other
hand, with regard to the metaphysical presuppositions of science, only a
single alternative is welcome.
\item Academicians will readily acknowledge that they are not interested
in scholarly work by unknown persons with no academic credentials. To
academic mathematicians and biologists, whether Galois and Mendel had
made valid discoveries was irrelevant. Thus, academicians as academicians
circumscribe their purported interest in the cognitive in two ways---once as
scientists; and once for reasons of personal gain and prestige.
\item The strangest instance of a non-cognitive need for a belief is
provided by the person who holds a fearful belief which is widely considered
to be superstitious, such as belief in Hell. As always, the test of whether the
motive for the belief is cognitive is the question of whether the person would
welcome a demonstration that the belief is invalid. There is reason to suspect
that persons who cling to fearful beliefs would not welcome such a
demonstration, perverse as their attitude may seem. After all, they take no
comfort in the widespread rejection of the belief as superstitious. Thus, it
seems that a masochistic need for fearful beliefs must be recognized.
\end{enumerate}
This examination of non-cognitive motives for beliefs is, to repeat,
limited to circumstances in which there is explicit self-deception, or
self-deception that can be demonstrated directly from internal evidence. The
examination cannot be carried further unless we become able to judge
whether the beliefs referred to are, after all, valid. Thus, we will now turn to
our properly philosophical inquiry, which will occupy the remainder of this
monograph.
\signoffnote{(Note: Chapters 2-7 were written in 1961, at a time when I used
unconventional syntax and punctuation. They are printed here without
change.)}
\section{The Linguistic Solution of Properly Philosophical Problems}
\subsection*{Chapter 2 : Preliminary Concepts}
In this part of the book I will be concerned to solve the problem of
philosophy proper, the problem of which beliefs are right, by discussing
language, certain linguistic expressions. To motivate what follows I might
tentatively say that I will consider beliefs as represented by statements,
formulations of them (for example, \formulation{Other persons have minds} as
representing the belief that other persons have minds), so that the problem
will be which statements are true. Actually, to solve this problem we will be
driven far beyond answers to the effect that given statements are true (or
false).
To make this book as engaging as possible, I would like to start right
into the solution of the problem, to begin with the material in the next
chapter. However, it effects, I think, a considerable clarification and
simplification of the presentation of the solution if I first introduce certain
concepts in an extended discussion. Then, when they enter into the solution
they won't have to be just suggested in a condensed explanation which has
to be repeated over and over. Thus, this chapter will be a properly
philosophically neutral introduction of the concepts, an introduction which
doesn't in itself say anything about the rightness of given beliefs (or the
truth of given statements). The chapter is as a result not so interesting as the
others, but I hope the reader will bear with me through it.
The first concept is a new one, that of "explication". Explication of a
familiar linguistic expression is what might traditionally be said to be finding
a definition of the expression; it amounts partly to determining what it is
wanted that the expression "mean". To explain: I will be discussing
philosophically important expressions, familiar to the reader, such that their
"meaning" needs clarifying, such that it is not clear to him how he wants to
use them. I will be concerned with the suggestion of expressions, of which
the "meanings", uses, are clear, which will be acceptable to the reader as
replacements for the expressions of which the uses are obscure; that is,
which have the uses that, it will turn out, the expressions of which the uses
are obscure are supposed to have. Since the expressions which are to be
replacements can be equivalent as expressions (sounds, bodies of marks) to
the expressions they are to replace, it can also be said that I will be
concerned with the suggestion of clear uses, of the expressions of which the
uses are obscure, which are, it will turn out, the uses the reader wants the
expressions to have. To be more specific about the conditions of
acceptability of such replacements, if the familiar expressions (expressions of
which the uses were obscure) were supposed to be names, have referents
(and non-referents), then the new: expressions must clearly have referents.
Further, the new expressions must deserve (by having appropriate referents
in the case of names) the principal connotations of the familiar expressions,
especially the distinctive, honorific connotations of the familiar expressions.
(I will not say here just how I use "connotation". What the connotations of
an expression are will be suggested by giving sentences about, in the case of a
supposed name for example, what the referents of the expression are
supposed to be like.) "Finding", or constructing, an expression (with its use)
supposed to be acceptable to oneself as.a replacement, of the kind described,
for an expression familiar to oneself, will be said to be "explicating" the
expression familiar to oneself. The expression to be replaced will be said to
be the "explicandum", and the suggested replacement, the "explication".
Incidentally, if clarification shows that the desired use of the explicandum is
inconsistent, then it can't have an explication at all acceptable, or what is the
same thing, any explication will be as good as any other.
I should mention that my use of "explication" is different from that of
Rudolph Carnap, from whom I have taken the word rather than use the very
problematic "definition". For him, explication is a scientist's, or philosopher
of science's, devising a new precise concept, useful in natural science,
suggested by a vague, unclear common concept (for example, that of
"work"); whereas for me it is in effect constructing (if possible) that precise,
clear concept which is the nearest equivalent to an unclear common concept.
Here is an example in the acceptability of explications. Suppose that an
expression is suggested, as an explication for "thing having a mind" (if
supposed to be a name, have referents), which has as referents precisely the
things which have certain facial expressions, or talk, or have certain other
"overt" behavior, or even certain brain electricity. Then I expect that this
expression will not be acceptable to the reader as an explication for "thing
having a mind", since "thing having a mind" presumably has the connotations
for the reader "that having a mind is not the same as, is very different from,
higher than, having certain facial expressions, talking, certain other overt
behaving, or having certain brain electricity---the mind is observable only by
the thing having it", and the explication doesn't deserve these connotations:
the connotations of the explicandum are exclusive of the referents of the
proposed explication. It doesn't make any difference if there's a causual
connection between having a mind and the other things, because the
expression 'thing having a mind' itself, and not the supposed effects of
having a mind, is what is under discussion.
As the reader can tell from the example, I will, in evaluating
expressions, have to speak of what I assume the connotations of words are
for the reader. If any of my assumptions are incorrect, the book will be
slightly less relevant to the reader's philosophical problems than it would be
otherwise. Even so, the reader should get from this part the method of
finding good explications, and its use in solving properly philosophical
problems.
Especially important in deciding whether an explication for a supposed
name is good is the check of the referents of the explication against the
connotations of the explicandum. Traditional philosophers, in the rare cases
when they have suggested explications for expressions in dealing with
philosophical problems, have suggested absurdly bad ones, which can quickly
be shown up by such a check. Examples which are typically horrible are the
explications for "thing having a mind" mentioned above.
The second concept I will discuss is that of true statement. As I will be
discussing the "truth" of formulations of beliefs, statements, in the next two
chapters, and as the concept of true statement is quite obscure (making it a
good example of one needing explication), it will be helpful for me to clarify
the concept beforehand, to give a partial explication for "true statement".
(Partial because the explication, although much clearer than the
explicandum, will itself have an unclear word in it.)
Well, what is a "statement"? How do what are usually said to be
"statements" state? Take a book and look through it, a book in a language
you don't read, so you won't assume that it's obvious what it means. What
does the book, the object, do? How does it work? Note that talking just
about the marks in the book, or what seem (!) to be the rules of their
arrangement, or the like, won't answer these questions. In fact, I expect that
when the reader really thinks about them, the questions won't seem easy
ones to answer. Now to begin answering them, one of the most important
connotations of "true statement", and, more generally, of "statement", as
traditionally and commonly used, is that a "statement" is an "assertion
which has truth value" (is true or false) (or "has content", as it is sometimes
said, rather misleadingly). That is, the "verbal" part of a statement is
supposed to be related in a certain way to something "non-verbal", or at
least not in the language the verbal part of the statement is in. Further, a
statement is supposed to be "true" or not because of something having to do
with the non-verbal thing to which the verbal part of the statement is
related. (The exceptions are the "statements" of formalist logic and
mathematics, which are not supposed to be assertions; they are thus
irrelevant to statements of the kind ordinary persons and philosophers are
interested in.) Thus, if "true statement" is to be explicated, "assertion having
truth value" and "is true" (and "has content" in a misleading use) have to be
explicated, as they are obscure, and as it must be clear that the explication
for "true statement" deserves the connotations which were suggested with
"assertion having truth value" and "is true". One important conclusion from
these observations is that although "sentences" (the bodies of sound or
bodes of marks such as "The man talks") are often said to be "statements",
would not be sufficient (to say the least) to explicate "statement" by simply
identifying it with "sentence" (in my sense); something must be said about
such matters as that of being an assertion having truth value. For the same
reason, it is not sufficient (to say the least) to simply identify "statement"
with "sentence", the latter being explicated in terms of the ("formal") rules
for the formation of (grammatical) sentences, as these rules have no
reference to such matters as that of being an assertion having truth value.
In explicating "true statement" I will use the most elegant approach, one
relevant to the interest in such matters as that of being an assertion having
truth value. This is to begin by describing a simple, if not the simplest, way
to make an assertion. As an example, I will describe the simplest way to
make the assertion that a thing is a table. The way is to "apply" \term{table} to
the thing. It is supposed that \term{table} has been "interpreted", that is, that it is
"determinate" to which, of all things, applications of \term{table} are (to be said
to be) "true". (It is good to realize that it is also supposed that it is
"determinate" which, of all things (events), are "occurrences of the word
"table", are expressions "equivalent to" "table".) The word "determinate" is
the intentionally ambiguous one in this explication; I don't want to commit
myself yet on how an expression becomes interpreted. As for 'apply', one
can "apply" the word to the thing by pointing out "first" the word and
"then" the thing. 'point out' is restricted to refer to "ostension", pointing
out things in one's presence, things one is perceiving, and not to "directing
attention to things not in one's presence" as well. The assertion is 'true', of
course, if and only if the thing to which 'table' is applied is one of the things
to which it is determinate that the application of 'table' is (to be said to be)
"true", otherwise "false". It should be clear that such a pointing out of a
"first" thing and a "second", the first being an interpreted expression, is an
assertion of a simple kind, does have truth value and so forth. Let me further
suggest 'interpreted expression' as an explication for 'name'; with respect to
this explication, the things to which equivalent names ("occurances of a
name") may be truthfully applied are the referents of the equivalent names,
other things being non-referents. (Incidentally, I could have started with the
concept of a name and its referents, and then said how to make a simple
assertion using a name.) Then what I have intentionally left ambiguous is
how a name has referents; I have not said, for example, whether the relation
between name and referents is an "objective, metaphysical entity", which
would be getting into philosophy proper.
The point of describing this simple way of making an assertion is that
what one wants to say are "statements", namely sentences used in the
context of certain conventions, can be regarded as assertions of the "simple"
kind; thus an explication for 'true statement' can be found. To do so, first
let us say that the "complex name" gotten by replacing a sentence's "main
verb" with the corresponding participle is the "associated name" of the
sentence. For example, the associated name of 'Boston is in Massachusetts' is
'Boston being in Massachusetts'. In the case of a sentence with coordinate
clauses there may be a choice with respect to what is to be taken as the main
verb, but this presents no significant difficulty. Example: sentence: \said{The
table in the room will have been black only if it had been pushed by one
man while the other man talked}; main verb: 'will have been' or 'had been
pushed'. Also, English may not have a participle to correspond to every verb,
but this is in theory no difficulty; the lacking participle could obviously be
invented. Now what we would like to say one does, in using a sentence to
make a statement, is to so to speak "assert" its associated name; this
"asserted name" being "true" if and only if it has a referent. However, one
doesn't assert names; names just have referents---it is statements that one
makes, "asserts", and that are "true" or "false". How, then, do we explicate
this "asserting" of a name? By construing it as that assertion, of the simple
kind, which is the application of 'having a referent' to the name. In other
words, from our theoretical point of view, to use a sentence to make a
statement, one begins with a name (the sentence's associated name), and
puts it into the sentence form, an act equivalent by convention to applying
'having a referent' to it. For example, the sentence 'Boston is in
Massachusetts' should be regarded as the simple assertion which is the
application of 'having a referent' to 'Boston being in Massachusetts'.
Now this approach may seem "unnatural" or incomplete to the reader
for several reasons. First there is the syntactical oddity: the sentence is
replaced by a statement "about" it (or to be precise its associated name).
Well, all I can say is that this oddity is the inevitable result of trying to
describe explicitly all that happens when one uses a sentence to make a
statement; I can assure the reader that the alternate approaches are even
more unnatural. Secondly, it may seem natural enough to speak of
interpreting "simple names" (Fries' Class 1 words), but not so natural to
speak of interpreting complex names (what could their referents be?). Of
course, this is because complex names are to be regarded as formed from
simpler names by specified methods; that is, their interpretations (and thus
referents) are in specified relations to those of the simple names from which
they are formed. The relations are indicated by the words, in the complex
names, which are not names, and by the order of the words in the complex
names. An example worth a comment is associated names containing such
words as 'the'; in making statements, these names have to be in the context
of additional conventions, understandings, to have significance. It will be
clear that what these relations (and referents) are, the explication of these
relations, is not important for my purposes. Thirdly, I have not said anything
about what the "meaning" (intension), as opposed to the referents (and
non-referents), of a name is. (I might say that a thing can't have an intension
unless it has referents or non-referents.) This matter is also not important for
my purposes (and gets into philosophy proper). Finally, my approach tells
the reader no more than he already knew about whether a given statement is
true. Quite so, and I said that the discussion would be properly
philosophically neutral. In fact, it is so precisely because of the ambiguous
word 'determinate', because I haven't said anything about how names get
referents. Even so, we have come a long way from blank wonder about how
one (sounds, marks) could ever state anything, a long way towards
explicating how asserting works. (And to the philosopher of language with
formalist prejudices, the discussion has been a needed reminder that if
language is to be assertional, say something, then names and referring in
some form must have the central role in it.)
"Statements", then, can be regarded as assertions of the 'simple' kind
which are made in the special, conventional way, involving sentences, I have
described. I could thus explicate 'true statement' as referring to those true
"simple" assertions made in the special way, and it should be clear that this
would be a good explication. However, as the connotations of 'true
statement' having to do with the method of apptying the first member to the
second are, I expect, of secondary importance compared to those having to
do with such matters as being an assertion having truth value, it ts more
elegant to explicate 'true statement' as referring to all true assertions of the
"simple" kind. For the purposes of this book it is not important which of
the two explications the reader prefers.
So much for the preliminaries.
\subsection*{Chapter 3 : "Experience"}
I will introduce in this chapter some basic terminology, as the main step
in taking the reader from ordinary English and traditional philosophical
language to a language with which my philosophy can be exposited. This
terminology is important because one of the main difficulties in expositing
my philosophy (or any new philosophy) is that current language is based on
precisely some of the assumptions, beliefs, I intend to question. It will, I
think, be immediately clear to the reader at all familiar with modern
philosophy that the problems of terminology I am going to discuss are
relevant to the problem of which beliefs are right.
First, consider the term 'non-experience'. Although the concept of a
non-experience is intrinsically far more "difficult" than the concept of
"experience" which I will be discussing presently, it is, I suppose,
presupposed in all "natural languages" and throughout philosophy, is so
taken for granted that it is rarely discussed in itself. Thus, the reader should
have no difficulty understanding it. Examples of non-experiences are
perceivable objects---for example, a table (as opposed to one's perceptions of
it), existing external to oneself, persisting when one is not perceiving it; the
future (future events); the past; space (or better, the distantness of objects
from oneself); minds other than one's own; causal relationships as ordinarily
understood; referental relationships (the relationships between names and
their referents as ordinarily understood; what I avoided discussing in the
second chapter); unperceivable "things" (microscopic objects (of course,
viewing them through microscopes does not count as perceiving them),
essences, Being); in short, most of the things one is normally concerned with,
normally thinks about, as well as the objects of uncommon knowledge. (To
simplify the explanation of the concept, make it easier on the reader, I am
speaking as if I believed that there are non-experiences, that is, introducing
the concept in the context of the beliefs usually associated with it.)
Non-experiences are precisely what one has beliefs about. One believes that
there are microscopic living organisms, or that there are none (or that one
can not know whether there are any---this is not a non-belief but a complex
belief about the relation of the realm where non-experiences could be to the
mind). Incidentally, that other minds, for example, are non-experiences is
presumably a connotation of 'other minds' for the reader, as explained in the
second chapter.
In the history of philosophy, the concept of non-experience comes first.
Then philosophers begin to develop theories of how one knows about
non-experiences (epistemological theories). The concept of a perception, or
experience of something, is introduced into philosophy. The theory is that
one knows about non-experiences by perceiving, having experiences of, some
of them. For example, one knows that there is a table before one's eyes
(assuming that there is) by having a visual perception or experience of it, by
having a "visual-table-experience". The theory goes on to say that these
perceptions are in the mind. Then, if one has a visual-table-experience in
one's mind when there is no table, one is hallucinated. And so forth. Now
there are two sources of confusion in all this for the naive reader. First,
saying that perceptions of objects are in one's mind is not saying that they
are, for example, visualizations, imaginings, such as one's visualization of a
table with one's eyes closed. Perceptions of objects do not seem "mental".
The theory that they are in the mind is a belief. This point leads directly to
the second source of confusion. Does the English word 'table', as ordinarily
used to refer to a table when one is looking at it, refer to the table, an entity
external to one's perceptions which persists when not perceived, or to one's
perception of it, to the visual-table-experience? If distinguishing between
the two, and the notion that the table-experience is in his mind, seem silly to
the reader, then he probably uses 'table', 'perceived table', and
'table-experience' as equivalent some of the time. The distinction, however,
is not just silly; anyone who believes that there are tables when he is not
perceiving them must accept it to be consistent. At any rate there is this
confusion, that it is not always clear whether English object-names are being
used to refer to perceived non-experiences or to experiences, the
perceptions.
Now let us ignore for a moment the connotations that experiences are
experiences, perceptions, of non-experiences, and are in the mind. The term
'experience' is important here because with it philosophers finally made a
start at inventing a term for the things one knows directly, unquestionabiy
knows, or, better, which one just has, or are just there (whether they are
experiences, perceptions, of non-experiences or not). A traditional
philosopher would say that if one is having a table-experience, one may not
know whether it's a true perception of a table, whether there's an objective
table there; or whether it's an hallucination; but one unquestionably knows,
has, the table-experience. And of course, with respect to one's experiences
not supposed to be perceptions of anything, such as visualizations, one
unquestionably knows, has them too. A better way of putting it is that there
is no question as to whether one has one's experiences or what they are like.
One doesn't believe (that one has) one's experiences; to try to do so would
be rather like trying to polish air. In fact, "thinking" that one doesn't have
one's experiences, if this is possible, is a belief, a wrong one (as will be
shown, although it should already be obvious if the reader has the slightest
idea of what I am talking about), and in fact a perfectly insane one. Now the
reader must not think that because I say experiences are unquestionably
known I am talking about tautologies, or about beliefs which some
philosophers say can be known by intuition even though unprovable, or say
cannot really be doubted without losing one's sanity (for example, some
philosophers say this about the belief that other persons have minds). In
speaking of experiences I am not trying to trick the reader into accepting a
lot of beliefs I am not prepared to justify, as many philosophers do by
appealing to intuition or sanity or what not, a reprehensible hyprocrisy
which shows that they are not the least interested in philosophy proper. One
does not have other-persons'-having-minds-experiences (nor are the objective
tables one supposedly perceives table-experiences); one believes that other
persons have minds (or that there is an objective table corresponding to one's
table-experience), and this belief could very well be wrong (in fact, it is, as
will be shown).
I have explained the current use of the term 'experience'. Now I want
to propose a new use for the term, which, except where otherwise noted,
will be that of the rest of this book. (Thus whereas in discussing
'non-experience' I was merely explaining and accepting the current use of
the term, in the case of 'experience' I am going to suggest a new use for the
term.) As I explained, the concept of non-experience preceded that of
experience, and the latter was developed to explain how one knows the
former. What I am interested in, however, is not 'experience' as it implies.
'perceptions, of non-experiences, and in the mind', but as it refers to that
which one unquestionably knows, is immediate, is just there, is not
something one believes exists. I am going to use 'experience' to refer, as it
already does, to that immediate "world", but without the implication that
experience is perception of non-experience, and in the mind: the same
referents but without the old connotations. In other words, in my use
'experience' is completely neutral with respect to relationships to
non-experiences, is not an antonym for 'non-experience' as conventionally
used, does not presuppose a metaphysic. The reader is being asked to take a
leap of understanding here, because there is all the difference in philosophy
between 'experience' as implying, connoting, relatedness to non-experiences
or in particular the realm where they could be, and 'experience' without
these connotations.
Viewing this discussion of terminology in retrospect, it should be
obvious that although my term 'experience' was introduced last, it is
intrinsically, logically, the simplest, most immediate, most inevitable of the
terms, and should be the easiest to understand. In contrast, the notions I
discussed in reaching it may seem a little arbitrary. As a matter of fact, I
have used the perspective of the Western philsophical tradition to explain my
term, but this doesn't mean that it is relevant only to that tradition or,
especially, the theory of knowing about non-experiences. Even if the reader's
conceptual background does not involve the concept of non-experience, and
especially the modern Western theory of knowing about non-experiences, he
ought to be able to understand, and realize the "orimacy" of, my term
'experience'. The term should be supra-cultural.
I have gone to some length to explain my use of the term 'experience'.
As I have said, it is "intrinsically" the simplest term, but I can not define it
by just equating it to some English expression because all English, including
the traditional term 'experience', the antonym of 'non-experience', is based
on metaphysical assumptions, does have implications about non-experience,
in short, is formulations of beliefs. These implications are different for
different philosophers according as their metaphysics (or, as is sometimes
(incorrectly) said, "ontologies") differ. Even such a sentence as "The table is
black" implies the formulation \formulation{Material objects are real} (to the materialist),
or \formulation{So-called objects are ideas in the mind} (to the idealist), or \formulation{Substances
and attributes are real}, and so forth, traditionally. As a result, in order to
explain the new term I have had to use English in a very special way,
ultimately turning it against itself, so as to enable the reader to guess how I
use the term. That is, although there is nothing problematic about my use of
\term{experience}, about its referents, there is about my English, for example
when I say that the connotation of relatedness to non-experience is to be
dropped from \term{experience}. There can be this new term, the philosopher is
not irrevocably tied to English or other natural language and its implied
philosophy, as some philosophers claim; because a term is able to be a name,
to be used to make assertions, not by being a part of conventional English or
other natural language, but by having referents.
As I suggested at the beginning of this chapter, I need to introduce my
\term{experience} because without it I cannot question all beliefs, everything
about non-experiences, since in English there is always the implication that
there could be non-experiences. The term is a radical innovation; one of the
most important in this book. The fact that although it is the "simplest" and
least questionable term, it is a radical innovation and is difficult to explain
using English, shows how philosophically inadequate English and the
philosophies it implies are. Now if the reader has not understood my
\term{experience} he is likely to precisely mis-understand the rest of the book as
an attempt to show that there are no non-experiences. (It's good that this
isn't what I'm trying to show, because it is self-contradictory: for there to be
no non-experiences there would have to be a realm empty of them, and this
realm would have to be a non-experience.) If he is lucky he will just find the
book incomprehensible, or possibly even come to understand the term from
the rest of what I say, using it. But if he does understand the term, then he is
past the greatest difficulty in understanding the book; in fact, he may
already realize what I'm going to say.
\subsection*{Chapter 4 : The Linguistic Solution}
Now that I have explained the key terminology for this part of the
book, I can give the solution to properly philosophical problems, the
problems of which beliefs are right, in the form of conclusions about the
language in which the beliefs are formulated. My concern here is to present
the solution as soon as possible, so as to make it clear to the reader that my
work contains important results, is an important contribution to philosophy,
and not just admirable sentiments or the formulation of an attitude or a
philosophically neutral analysis of concepts or the like. For this reason I will
not be too concerned to make the solution seem natural, or intuitive, or to
explore all its implications; that will come later.
However, in the hope that it will make the main "argument" of this
chapter easier to understand, I will precede it with a short, non-rigorous
version of it, which should give the "intuitive insight" behind the main
argument. Consider the question of whether one can know if a given belief is
true. Now a given belief is cognitively arbitrary in that it cannot be justified
from the standpoint of having no beliefs, cannot be justified without
appealing to other beliefs. Thus the answer must be skepticism: one cannot
know if a given belief is true. However, this skepticism is a belief---a
contradiction. The ultimate conclusion is that to escape inconsistency, to be
right, one must, at the linguistic level, reject all talk of beliefs, of knowing if
they are true, reject all formulations of beliefs. The "necessity", but
inconsistency, of skepticism "shows" my conclusion in an intuitively
understandable way.
To get on to the definitive version of my "argument". I will say that
one name "depends" on another if and only if it has the logical relation to
that other that \name{black table} has to \name{table}: a referent of the former is
necessarily a referent of the latter (one of the relations between names
mentioned in the second chapter). Now the associated name of any
statement, or formulation, of a belief of necessity depends on
'non-experience', since non-experiences are what beliefs are about. For
example, \name{Other persons having minds}, the associated name of the
formulation \formulation{Other persons have minds}, certainly depends on
\term{non-experience}. Thus, anything true of \term{non-experience} will be true of the
associated name of any formulation of a belief.
In the last chapter I introduced, explained the concepts of
non-experience and experience (in the traditional sense, as the antonym of
\term{non-experience}), showed the connotations of the expressions
\term{non-experience} and \term{experience} (traditional). What I did not go on to
show, left for this chapter, is that if one continues to analyze these concepts,
one comes on crucial implications which result in contradictions. What
follows is perhaps the most concentrated passage in this book, so that the
reader must be willing to read it slowly and thoughtfully. Consider one's
experience (used in my, "neutral", sense unless I say otherwise). Could there
be something in one's experience, a part of one's experience, which was
awareness of whether it's experience (traditional), of whether it's related to
non-experience, of whether there is non-experience, awareness of
non-experience? No, as should be obvious from the connotations shown in
the last chapter. (Compare this with the point that one cannot (cognitively)
justify a belief from the standpoint of having no beliefs, cannot justify it
without appealing to other beliefs). If there could be, if such awareness were
just an experience, the distinctness of experience from experience
(traditional) and so forth would disappear. The concepts of experience
(traditional) and so forth would be superfluous, in fact, one couldn't have
them: experience (traditional) and so forth would just be absorbed into
experience. One concludes that there cannot be anything in one's experience
which is awareness of whether it's experience (traditional), of whether there
is non-experience. But then this awareness, which is in part about experience
(traditional) and non-experience and thus involves awareness of them, is in
one's experience---a contradiction. In fact, the same holds for the awareness
which is "understanding the concepts" of non-experience and the rest as
they are supposed to be understood. And for "understanding"
\term{non-experience} (and the rest) as it is supposed to be, being aware of its
referents (and non-referents); since to name non-experience, it must be an
experience (traditional). And even for being aware of the referents (and
non-referents) of "non-experience", which to name an experience
(traditional) must be one. One mustn't assume that one understands
'non-experience' --- and "non-experience" --- and \triquote{non-experience}; but here
one is, using "non-experience" and \triquote{non-experience} to say so (which
certainly implies that one assumes one understands them). It is impossible
for there to be non-experiences. When one begins to examine closely the
concept of non-experience, it collapses.
(A final point for the expert. This
tangle of contradictions is intrinsic in the concept of non-experience; it does
not result because I have introduced a violation of the law that names cannot
name themselves. This should be absolutely clear from the two sentences
about names, which show contradictions --- that one must not assume that
one understands certain expressions, but that one uses the expressions to say
so (does assume it) --- with explicit stratification.)
My exposition has broken down in a tangle of contradictions. Now
what is important is that it has done so precisely because I have talked about
experience (traditional), non-experience, and the rest, because I have spoken
as if there could be non-experiences, because I have used 'experience'
(traditional), 'non-experience', and the rest. Thus, even though what I have
said is a tangle of contradictions, it is not by any means valueless. Since it is
a tangle of contradictions precisely because it involves 'experience'
(traditional), 'non-experience', and the rest, it shows that one who "accepts"
the expressions, supposes that they are valid language, has inconsistent
desires with respect to how they are to be used. The expressions can have no
explications at all acceptable to him. He cannot consistently use the
expressions (the way they're supposed to be). The expressions, and,
remembering the paragraph before last, any formulation of a belief, are
completely discredited. (What is not discredited is language referring to
experiences (my use). If it happens that an expression I have said is a
formulation of a belief does have a good explication for the reader, then it is
not a formulation of a belief for him but refers to experiences.) Now there is
an important point about method which should be brought out. If all
"non-experiential language", "belief language", is inconsistent, how can I
show this and yet avoid falling into contradiction when I say it? The answer
is that I don't have to avoid falling into contradiction; that I fall into
contradiction precisely because I use formulations of beliefs shows what I
want to show. This, then, is the linguistic solution; as I said we would, we
have been driven far beyond any such conclusion as 'all formulations of
beliefs are false'.
Now what do these conclusions about formulations of beliefs, about
belief language, say about beliefs themselves, about whether a given belief is
right? Well, to the extent that a belief is tied up with its formulation, since
the formulation is discredited, the belief is, must be wrong. After all, if a
belief were right, its formulation would necessarily have an acceptable
explication which was true; in short, the belief would have a true
formulation (to see this, note that the contrary assertion is itself a
formulation of a belief---leading to a contradiction). Incidentally, this point
answers those who would say, that the inconsistency of their statements of
belief taken literally does not discredit their beliefs, as the statements are not
to be taken literally, are metaphorical or symbolic truths. To continue, one
who because of having a belief took its formulation seriously, expected that
it could have an acceptable explication for him, could not turn out to be an
expression he could not properly use, must be deceiving himself in some
way. Now there is another important point about "method" to be made.
The question will probably continually recur to the critical reader how one
can "know", be aware that any given belief is wrong, without having beliefs.
The answer is that one way one can be aware of it is simply to be aware of
the inconsistency of belief language, which awareness is not a belief.
(Whether belief language is inconsistent is not a matter of belief but of the
way one wants expressions used; being aware of the inconsistency is like
being aware with respect to a table, "that in my language, this is to be said to
be a "table"".) Incidentally, to wrap things up, the common belief as to how
a name has referents is that there is a relation between the name and its
referents which is an objective, metaphysical entity, a non-experience; this
belief is wrong. How, in what sense a name can have referents will not be
discussed here.
The unsophisticated reader may react to all of this with a lot of 'Yes,
but...' thoughts. If he doesn't more or less identify beliefs with their
formulations, and doesn't have an intuitive appreciation of the force of
linguistic arguments, he my tend to regard my result as a mere (if
embarrassing) curiosity. (Of course, it isn't, but I am concerned with how
well the reader understands that.) And there does remain a lot to be said
about beliefs themselves (as mental acts), and where the self-deception is in
them; it is not even clear yet just what the relation of a belief to its
formulation is. Then the reader might ask whether there aren't beliefs whose
rejection as wrong would conflict with experience, or which it would be
impossible or dangerous not to have. I now turn to the discussion of these
matters.
\clearpage
2/22/1963
Tony Conrad and Henry Flynt demonstrate
against Lincoln Center, February 22,
1963
(photo by Jack Smith)
\clearpage
\section{Completion of the Treatment of Properly Philosophical Problems}
\subsection*{Chapter 5 : Beliefs as Mental Acts}
In this chapter I will solve the problems of philosophy proper by
discussing believing itself, as a ("conscious") mental act. Although I will be
talking about mental acts and experience, it must be clear that this part of
the book, like the fast part, is not epistemology or phenomenology. I will
not try to talk about "perception" or the like, in a mere attempt to justify
"common-sense" beliefs or what not. Of course, both parts are incidentally
relevant to epistemology and phenomenology, since in discussing beliefs I
discuss the beliefs which constitute those subjects.
I should say immediately that 'belief', in its traditional use as supposed
to refer to "mental acts, often unconscious, connected with the realm of
non-experience", has no explication at all satisfactory, has been discredited.
This point is important, as it means that one does not want to say that one
does or does not "have beliefs", in the sense important to those having
beliefs, that beliefs (in my sense) will not do as referents for "belief" in the
use important to those having beliefs; helping to fill out the conclusion of
the last part. Now when I speak of a "belief" I will be speaking of an
experience, what might be said to be "an act of consciously believing, of
consciously having a belief", of what is "in one's head" when one says that
one "believes a certain thing". Further, I will, for convenience in
distinguishing beliefs, speak of belief "that others have minds", for example,
or in general of belief "that there are non-experiences" (with quotation
marks), but I must not be taken as implying that beliefs manage to be
"about non-experiences". (Thus, what I say about beliefs will be entirely
about experiences; I will not be trying to talk "about the realm of
non-experience, or the relation of beliefs to it".) I expect that it is already
fairly clear to the reader what his acts of consciously believing are (if he has
any); I will be more concerned with pointing out to him some features of his
"beliefs" (believing) than with the explication of 'act of consciously
believing', although I will need to make a few comments about that too.
What I am trying to do is to get the reader to accept a useful, possibly new,
use of a word ('belief') salvaged from the unexplicatible use of the word,
rather than rejecting the word altogether.
There is a further point about terminology. The reader should
remember from the third chapter that quite apart from the theory "that
perceptions are in the mind", one can make a distinction between mental
and non-mental experiences, between, for example, visualizing a table with
one's eyes closed, and a "seen" table, a visual-table-experience. Now I am
going to say that visualizations and the like are "imagined-experiences". For
example, a visualization of a table will be said to be an
"imagined-visual-table-experience". The reader should not suppose that by
"imagined" I mean that the experiences are "hallucinations", are "unreal". I
use "imagined" because saying 'mental-table-experience" is too much like
saying "table in the mind" and because just using 'visualization' leaves no way
of speaking of mental experiences which are not visualizations. Speaking of
an "imagined-table-experience" seems to be the best way of saying that it is
a mental experience, and then distinguishing it from other mental
experiences by the conventional method of saying that it is an imagining "of
a (non-mental) table-experience" (better thought of as meaning an imagining
like a (non-mental) table-experience). In other words, an
imagined-x-experience (to generalize) is a "valid" experience, all right, but it
is not a non-mental x-experience; it is a mental experience which is like a
(non-mental) x-experience in a certain way. Incidentally, an "imagined-imagined-experience" is impossible by definition; or is no different from an
imagined-experience, whichever way you want to look at it. If this
terminology is a little confusing, it is not my fault but that of the
conventional method of distinguishing different mental experiences by
saying that they are imaginings "of one or another non-mental experiences".
I can at last ask what one does when one believes "that there is a table,
not perceived by oneself, behind one now", or anything else. Well, in the
first place, one takes note of, gives one's attention to, an
imagined-experience, such as an imagined-table-experience or a visualization
of oneself with one's back to a table; or to a linguistic expression, a supposed
statement, such as \lexpression{There is a table behind me}. This is not all one does,
however; if it were, what one does would not in the least deserve to be said
to be a "belief" (a point about the explication of my 'belief'). The
additional, "essential" component of a belief is a self-deceiving "attitude"
toward the experience. What this attitude is will be described below. Observe
that one does not want to say that the additional component is a belief
about the experience because of the logical absurdity of doing so, or, in
other words, because it suggests that there is an infinite regress of mental
action. Now the claim that the attitude is "self-deceiving" is not, could not
be, at all like the claim "that a belief as a whole, or its formulation, fails to
correspond in a certain way to non-experience, to reality, or is false". The
question of "what is going on in the realm of non-experience" does not arise
here. Rather, my claim is entirely about an experience; it is that the attitude,
the experience not itself a belief but part of the experience of believing, is
"consciously, deliberately" self-deceiving, is a "self-deception experience". I
don't have to "prove that the attitude is self-deceiving by reference to what
is going on in the realm of non-experience"; when I have described the
attitude and the reader is aware of it, he will presumably find it a good
explication, unhesitatingly want, to say that it is "self-deceiving".
I will now say, as well as can be, what the attitude is. In believing, one
is attentive primarily to the imagined-experience or linguistic expression as
mentioned above. The attitude is "peripheral", is a matter of the way one is
atttentive. Saying that the attitude is "conscious, deliberate", is a little
strong if it seems to imply that it is cynical self-brainwashing; what I am
trying to say is that it is not an "objective" or "subconscious" self-deception
such as traditional philosophers speak of, one impossible to be aware of. This
is about as much as I can say about the attitude directly, because of the
inadequacy of the English descriptive vocabulary for mental experiences;
with respect to English the attitude is a "vague, elusive" thing, very difficult
to describe. I will be able to say more about what it is only by suggestion, by
saying that it is the attitude "that such and such" (the reader must not think
I mean the belief "that such and such"). If the experience to which the
attention is primarily given in believing is an imagined-x-experience, then the
self-deceiving attitude is the attitude "that the imagined-x-experience is a
(non-mental) x-experience". As an example, consider the belief "that there is
a table behind one". If one's attention in believing is not on a linguistic
expression, it will be on an imagined-experience such as an
imagined-table-experience or a visualization of a person representing oneself
(to be accurate) with his back to a table, and one will have the self-deceiving
attitude "that the imagined-experience is a table or oneself with one's back
to a table". Of course, if one is asked whether one's imagined-x-experience is
a (non-mental) x-experience, one will say that it is not, that it is admittedly
an imagined-experience but "corresponds to a non-experience". This is not
inconsistent with what I have said: first, I don't say that one believes "that
one's imagined-x-experience is an x-experience"; secondly, when one is asked
the question, one stops believing "that there is a table behind one" and starts
believing "that one's imagined-experience corresponds in a certain way to a
non-experience", a different matter (different belief).
lf one's attention in believing is primarily on a linguistic expression
(which if a sentence, will be pretty much regarded as its associated name),
the self-deceiving attitude is the attitude "that the expression has a
referent". With respect to the belief "that there is a table behind one", one's
attention in believing would be primarily on the expression \expression{There is a table
behind me}, pretty much regarded as 'There being a table behind me', and
one would have the self-deceiving attitude "that this name has a referent".
Unexplicatible expressions, then, function as principal components of
beliefs.
\inlineaside{This paragraph is complicated and inessential; if it begins to confuse
the reader it can be skipped.} I will now describe the relation between the
version, of a belief, involving language and the version not involving
language. In the version not involving language, the attention is on an
imagined-x-experience which is "regarded" as an x-experience, whereas in
the version involving language, the attention is on something which is
"regarded" as having as referent "something" (the attitude is vague here).
For the latter version, the idea is "that the reality is at one remove", and
correspondingly, one whose "language" consists of formulations of beliefs
doesn't desire to have as experiences, or perceive, or even be able to imagine,
referents of expressions---which, for the more critical person, may make
believing easier. Thus, just as one takes note of the imagined-x-experience in
the version of the belief not involving language, has something which
functions as the thing the belief is about, so in the version involving language
one has the attitude that the expression has a referent. Further, just as one
has the attitude that the imagined-x-experience is an x-experience in the
version not involving language, does not recognize that what functions as the
thing believed in is a mere imagined-experience, so in the version involving
"language" one takes note of an 'expression' not having a referent, since a
referent could only be a (mere) experience. One who expects an expression,
which is the principal component of a belief, to have a good explication does
so on the basis of the self-deceiving attitude one has towards it in having the
belief. In trying to explicate the expression, one finds inconsistent desires
with respect to what its referents must be. These desires correspond to the
way the expression functions in the belief: the desire that it be possible for
awareness of the referent to be part of one's experience corresponds to the
attitude, in believing, that the expression has a referent; and the desire that it
not be possible for awareness of the referent to be (merely) part of one's
experience corresponds to the expression's not having a referent in believing.
Pointing out that the expression is unexplicable discredits the belief of which
it is the principal component, just as pointing out that a belief not involving
language consists of being attentive to an imagined-experience and having the
attitude that it is not an imagined-experience, discredits that belief.
Such, then, is what one does when one believes. If the reader is rather
unconvinced by my description, especially because of my speaking of
"attitudes", then let him consider the following summary: there must be
something more to a mental act than just taking note of an experience for it
to be a "belief"; this something is "peripheral and elusive", so that I am
calling the something an "attitude", the most appropriate way in English to
speak of it; the attitude, an experience not itself a belief but part of the
experience which is the belief, is thus isolated; the attitude is
"self-deceiving", is a "(conscious) self-deception experience", because when
aware of it the reader will presumably want to say that it is. The attitude just
about has to be a ("conscious") self-deception experience to transform mere
taking note of an experience into something remotely deserving to be said to
be a "belief". The decision as to whether the attitude is to be said to be
"self-deceiving" is to be made without trying to think "about the relation of
the belief as a whole to the realm of non-experience", to do which would be
to slip into having beliefs, other than the one under consideration, which
would be irrelevant to our concern here. Ultimately, the important thing is
to observe what one does in believing, and particularly the attitude, more
than to say that the attitude is "self-deceiving".
In order for my description of believing to be complete, I must mention
some things often associated with believing but not "essential" to it. First,
one may take note of non-mental and imagined-experiences other than the
one to which attention is primarily given. If one has a table-experience and
believes "that it is a table-perception corresponding to an objectively existing
table', one may give much of his attention to the table-experience in so
believing, associate the table-experience strongly with the belief. One may in
believing give attention to non-mental experiences supposed to be 'evidence
for, confirmation of, one's belief" (more will be said about confirmation
shortly). If one's attention in believing is primarily on the linguistic
expression 'x', one may give attention to a referent of
'imagined-x(-experience)', an "imagined-referent" of 'x'; or to
imagined-y-experiences such that y-experiences are supposed, said, to be
"analogous to the referent of 'x'". In the latter case the y-experiences will be
mutually exclusive, and less importance will be given to them than would be
to imagined-referents. An example of imagined-referents in believing is
visualizing oneself with one's back to a table, as the imagined-referent of
'There being a table behind one'. An example of imagined-y-experiences
(such that y-experiences are mutually exclusive) which are said to be
"analogous to referents", in believing, is the visualizations associated with
beliefs "about entities wholly other than, transcending, experience, such as
Being".
Secondly, there are associated with beliefs logical "justifications",
"arguments", for them, "defenses" of them. I will not bother to explicate
the different kinds of justifications because it is so easy to say what is wrong
with all of them. There are two points to be made. First, explication would
show that the matter of justifications for beliefs is just a matter of language
and beliefs of the kind already discussed. Secondly, as I have suggested
before, whether a statement or belief is right is not dependent on what the
justifications, arguments for it are. (If this seems to fail for inductive
justification, the kind invoiving the citing of experience supposed to be
evidence for, confirmation of, the belief, it is because the metaphysical
assumptions on which induction is based are rarely stated. Without them
inductive justifications are just non sequiturs. An example: this table has
four legs; therefore ("it is more probable that") any other table has four
legs.) Justification of a statement or belief does nothing but conjoin to it
superfluous statements or beliefs, if anything. The claim that a justification,
argument can show that a belief is not arbitrary, gratuitous, in that it can
show that to be consistent, one must have the belief if one has a Sesser,
weaker belief, is simply self-contradictory. If a justification induces one to
believe what one apparently did not believe before hearing the justification,
then one already had the belief "implicitly" (it was a conjunct of a belief
one already had), or one has accepted superfluous beliefs conjoined with it.
I will conclude this chapter first with a list of philosophical positions
my position is not. Although I have already suggested some of this material,
I repeat it because it is so important that the reader not misconstrue my
position as some position which is no more like mine than its negation is,
and which I show to be wrong. My position is not disbelief. (Incidentally, it
is ironic that 'disbeliever', without qualification, has been used by believers
as a term of abuse, since, as disbelief is belief which is the negation of some
belief, any belief is disbelief.) In particular, I am not concerned to deny "the
existence of non-experience", to "cause non-experiences to vanish", so to
speak, to change or cause to vanish some of the reader's non-mental
experiences, "perceived objects". My position is not skepticism of any kind,
is not, for example, the belief "that there is a realm where there could either
be or not be certain entities not experiences, but our means of knowing are
inadequate for finding which is the case." My position is not a mere
"decision to ignore non-experiences, or beliefs". The philosopher who denies
"the existence of non-experiences", or denies any belief, or who is skeptical
of any belief, or who merely "decides to ignore non-experiences, or beliefs",
has some of the very beliefs I am concerned to discredit.
What I have been concerned to do is to discredit formulations of
beliefs, and beliefs as mental acts, by pointing out some features of them. In
the first part of the book I showed the inconsistency of linguistic expressions
dependent on 'non-experience', and pointed out that those who expect them
to have explications at all acceptable are deceiving themselves; discrediting
the beliefs of which the expressions are formulations. In this chapter, I have
described the mental act of believing, calling the reader's attention to the
self-deception experience involved in it, and thus showing that it is wrong.
To conclude, in discrediting beliefs I have shown what the right
philosophical position is: it is not having beliefs (and realizing, for any belief
one happens to think of, that it is wrong (which doesn't involve having beliefs)).
\subsection*{Chapter 6 : Discussion of Some Basic Beliefs}
In the preceding chapters I have been concerned, in discrediting any
given belief, to show what the right philosophical position is. In this chapter
I will turn to particular beliefs, supposed knowledge, to make it clear just
what, specifically, have been discredited. Now if the reader will consider the
entire "history of world thought", the fantastic proliferation of activities at
least partly "systems of knowledge" which constitute it, Platonism,
psychoanalysis, Tibetian mysticism, physics, Bantu witchcraft,
phenomenology, mathematical logic, Konko Kyo, Marxism, alchemy,
comparative linguistics, Orgonomy, Thomism, and so on indefinitely, each
with its own kind of conclusions, method of justifying them, applications,
associated valuations, and the like, he will quickly realize that I could not
hope to analyze even a fraction of them to show just how "non-experiential
language", and beliefs, are involved in them. And I should say that it is not
always obvious whether the concepts of non-experiential language, and
belief, are relevant to them. Zen is an obvious example (although as a matter
of fact is unquestionably does involve beliefs, is not for example an
anticipation of my position). Further, many quasi-systems-of-knowledge are
difficult to discuss because the expositions of them which are what one has
to work with, are badly written, in particular, fail to state the insights behind
what is presented, the real reasons why it can be taken seriously, and are
incomplete and confused.
What I will do, then, to specifically illustrate my results, is to discuss a
few particular beliefs which are found in almost all systems of "knowledge";
have been given especial attention in modern Western philosophy and are
thus especially relevant to the immediate audience for this book; and are so
"basic" (accounting for their ubiquity) that they are either just assumed, as
too trivially factual to be worthy the attention of a profound thinker, or if
they are explicit are said to be so basic that persons cannot do without them.
The discussion will make it specifically clear that it is not necessary to have
these beliefs, that not having them is not "inconsistent" with one's
experience; and is thus important for the reader who is astonished at the idea
of rejecting any given belief, the idea of any given belief's being wrong and
of not having it.
Consider beliefs to the effect "that the world is ordered", beliefs
formulated in "natural laws", beliefs "about substance", and the like.
Rejection of them may seem to lead to a problem. After all, one's "perceived
world" is not "chaotic", is it? The reader should observe that in rejecting
beliefs "that the world is ordered" I do not say that his "perceived world" is
("subjectively") chaotic (that is, extremely unfamiliar, strange). The
non-strange character of one's "perceived world" is associated with beliefs
"about substance" and beliefs formulated in natural laws, but it is not "the
world being ordered"; and taking note of the non-strange character of one's
"perceived world" is not part of what is "essential" in these beliefs.
Rejection of "spatio-temporal" beliefs may seem to lead to a problem.
After all, cannot one watch oneself wave one's hand towards and away from
oneself? Of course one can "watch oneself wave one's hand" (in a non-strict
sense---and if the reader uses the expression in this sense it will not be a
formulation of a belief for him). However, that one can "watch oneself wave
one's hand" (in the non-strict sense) does not imply "that there are spatially
distant, and past and future events"; and although experiences such as a
visual---"moving"---hand experience are associated with spatio-temporal
beliefs, taking note of them is not part of what is essential in those beliefs.
Rejection of beliefs "about the objectivity of linguistic referring" may
seem to lead to a problem. After all, when one says that a table is a "table",
doesn't one do so unhesitatingly, with a feeling of satisfaction, a feeling that
things are less mysterious, strange, when one has done so, and without the
slightest intention of saying that it is a "non-table"? The reader should
observe that I do not deny this. These experiences are associated with beliefs
"about the objectivity of referring", but they are not "objective referring";
and taking note of them is not part of what is essential in those beliefs.
Rejection of the belief "that other humans (better, things) than oneself
have minds" my seem to lead to a problem. After all, "perceived other
humans" talk and so forth, do they not? The reader should observe that in
rejecting the belief "that others have minds" I do not deny that "perceived
other humans" talk and so forth. Other humans' talking and so forth is
associated with the belief "that others have minds", but it is not "other
humans having minds"; and taking note of others talking and so forth is not
part of what is essential in believing "that others have minds", points I
anticipated in the second chapter.
Finally, many philosophers will violently object to rejection of
temporal beliefs of a certain kind, namely beliefs of the form "If \x, then \y\
will follow in the future", especially if \y\ is something one wants, and \x\ is
something one can do. (After all, doesn't it happen that one throws the
switch, and the light goes on?) They object so strongly because they fear
"that one cannot live unless one has and uses such knowledge". They say,
for example, "that one had better know that one must drink water to live,
and drink water, or one won't live". Now "one's throwing the switch and the
light's coming on" (in a non-strict sense) is like the experiences associated
with other temporal beliefs; that one can do it (in the non-strict sense) does
not imply "that there are past or future events", and taking note of it is not
part of what is essential in the belief "that if one throws the switch, then the
light will come on". As for what the philosophers say, fear, believe "about
the necessity of such knowledge for survival", it is just more beliefs of the
same kind, so that rejection of it is similarly unproblematic. If this abrupt
dismissal of the fears as wrong is terrifying to the reader, then it just shows
how badly he is in need of being straightened out philosophically.
Incidentally, all this should make it clear that it is futile to try to "save"
beliefs (render them justifiable) by construing them as predictions.
By now the reader has probably observed that the beliefs, and their
formulations, which I have been discussing, the ones he is presumably most
suspicious of rejecting, are all strongly (but not essentially) associated with
non-mental experiences of his. The reader may no longer seriously have the
beliefs, but have problems in connection with them, get involved in
defending them, and be suspicious of rejecting them, merely because he
continues to use the formulations of the beliefs, but to refer to the
experiences associated with them (as there's no other way in English to do
so), and confusedly supposes that to reject the beliefs and formulations is to
deny that he has the experiences. Now I am not denying that he has the
experiences. As I said in the last chapter, I am not trying to convince the
reader that he doesn't have experiences he has, but to point out to him the
self-deception experiences involved in his beliefs. The reader should be wary
of thinking, however, on reading this, that maybe he doesn't have any beliefs
after all, just uses the belief language he does to refer to experiences. It
sometimes happens that people who have beliefs and as a result use belief
language excuse themselves on the basis that they are just using the language
to refer to experiences, an hypocrisy. If one uses belief formulations, it's
usually because one has beliefs.
The point that the language which one may use to describe experiences
is formulations of beliefs, is true generally. As I said in the third chapter, all
English sentences are, traditionally anyway, formulations of beliefs. As a
result, those who want to talk about experiences (my use) and still use
English are forced to use formulations of beliefs to refer to strongly
associated experiences, and this seems to be happening more and more; often
among quasi-empiricists who naively suppose that the formulations have
always been used that way, except by a few "metaphysicians". I have had to
so use belief language throughout this book, the most notable example being
the introduction of my use of "experience" in the third chapter. Thus, some
of what I say may imply belief formulations for the reader when it doesn't
for me, and be philosophically problematic for him; he must understand the
book to some extent in spite of the language, as I suggested in the third
chapter. I have tried to make this relatively easy by choosing, to refer to
experiences, language with which they are very strongly associated and
which is only weakly associated with beliefs, and, the important thing, by
announcing when the language is used for that purpose.
It is time, though, that I admit, so as not to be guilty of the hypocricy I
was exposing earlier, that most of the sentences in this book will be
understood as formulations of beliefs, that, in other words, I have presented
my philosophy to the reader by getting him to have a series of beliefs. This
does not invalidate my position, because the beliefs are not part of it. They
are for the heuristic purpose of getting the reader to appreciate my position,
which is not having beliefs (and realizing, for any belief one happens to think
of, that it is wrong (which doesn't involve believing)); and they may well not
be held when they have accomplished that purpose. I hope I will eventually
get around to writing a version of this book which presents my position by
suggesting to the reader a series of imaginings (and no more), rather than
beliefs; developing a new language to do so. The reason I stick with English
in this book is of course (!) that readers are too "unmotivated" (lazy!) to
learn a language of an entirely new kind to read a book, having
unconventional conclusions, in philosophy proper.
\subsection*{Chapter 7 : Summary}
The most important step in understanding my work is to realize that I
am trying neither to get one to adopt a system of beliefs, nor to just ignore
beliefs or the matter of whether they are right. Once the reader does so, he
will find that my position is quite simple. The reader has probably tended to
construe the body of the book, the second through the sixth chapters, as a
formulation of a system of beliefs; or as a proposal that he ignore beliefs or
the matter of whether they are right. Even if he has, a careful reading of
them will, I hope, have prepared him for a statement of my position which is
supposed to make it clear that the position is simple and right. This
statement is a summary, and thus cannot be understood except in
connection with the second through the sixth chapters. First, I reiterate that
my position is not a system of beliefs, supported by a long, plausible
argument. This means, incidentally, that it is absurd to "remain
unconvinced" of the rightness of my position, or to "doubt, question" it, or
to take a long time to decide whether it is right: one can "question" (not
believe) disbelief, but not unbelief. (Not to mention that it is a wrong belief
to be "skeptical" of my position in the sense of believing "that although the
position may subjectively seem right, there is always the possibility that it is
objectively wrong".) I am trying, not to get one to adopt new beliefs but to
reject those one already has, not to make one more credulous but less
credulous. If one "questions my position" then one is misconstruing it as a
belief for which I try to give a long, plausible argument, and is trying to
decide which is more plausible, my argument that all beliefs are false, say, or
the arguments that beliefs are true. It may well take one a long time to
understand my position, but if one is taking a long time to decide whether it
is right then one is wasting one's time thinking about a position I show to be
wrong. Secondly, my position is not a proposal that one ignore beliefs or the
matter of whether they are right. Thus, it is absurd to conclude that my
position is irrefutable but trivial, that one who has beliefs can also be right.
Now for the statement of the position. Imagine yourself without
beliefs. One certainly is without beliefs when one is not thinking, for
example (although not only then). This being without beliefs is my position.
Now this position can't be wrong inasmuch as you aren't doing anything to
be "true or false", to be self-deceiving. Now imagine that someone asks you
to believe something, for example, to believe "that there is a table behind
you". Then if you are going to do what he asks, and believe (as opposed to
continuing not to think; or only imagining---for example, "visualizing
yourself with your back to a table"), you are going to have to have the
attitude that you are in effect perceiving what you don't perceive, that is,
deceive yourself. (What else could he be asking you to do?) You are going
to have to be wrong. That's all there is to it.
As for my language here, it is primarily intended to be suggestive,
intended, at best, to suggest imaginings to you which will enable you to
realize what the right philosophical position is (as in the last paragraph). The
important thing is not whether the sentences in this book correspond to true
statements in your language (although I expect the key ones will, the
expressions in them being construed as referring to the experiences
associated with them); it is for you to realize, observe what you do when
you don't have beliefs and when you do. You are not so much to study my
language as to begin to ask what one who asks you to believe wants you to
do, anyway. The language isn't sufficiently flawless to absolutely force the
complete realization of what the right position is on you (it doesn't have to
be flawless to unquestionably discredit "non-experiential language"); if you
don't want to realize where the self-deception is in believing you can just
ignore the book, and "justify" your doing so on the basis of what I have said
about language such as I have used. The point is that the book is not
therefore valueless.
So much for what the right philosophical position is. From having
beliefs to not having them is not a trivial step; it is a complete
transformation of one's cognitive orientation. Yet astonishing as the latter
position is when first encountered, does it not become, in retrospect,
"obvious"? What other position could be the resolution of the fantastic
proliferation of conflicting beliefs, and of the "profound" philosophical
problems (for example, "Could an omnipotent god do the literally
impossible?", "Are statements about what I did in the past while alone
capable of intersubjective verification?") arising from them? And again, one
begins to ask, when one is asked to believe something, what it is that one is
wanted to do, anyway; and one's reaction to the request comes to be "Why
bother? Cognitively, what is the value of doing so? I'd just be deceiving
myself". Also, how much simpler my position is than that of the believer.
And although in a way the believer's position is the more natural, since one
"naturally" tends to deceive oneself if there's any advantage in doing so
(that is, being right tends not to be valued), in another way my position is,
since it is simple, and since the non-believer isn't worried by the doubts
which arise for one who tries to keep himself deceived.
|