1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
|
% chapter i
\defpnote{0.1}{A.N. Whitehead, \bt{Process and Reality}
(New York: The Macmillan Company, 1941), p. 63.}
\defpnote{0,2}{W.H. Walsh,
\et{Plato and the Philosophy of History: History and Theory in the Republic,}
\jt{History and Theory}
(The Hague: Mouton \& Co., 1962), II, 1, pp. 1--16.}
\defpnote{0.3}{K.R. Popper,
\bt{The Open Society and its Enemies}
(2 vols.; 2\tss{nd} ed. rev.; London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1952).}
\defpnote{0.4}{Walsh, op. cit., p. 6.}
\defpnote{0.5}{See, for example. R.L. Nettleship,
\bt{Lectures on the Republic of Plato }
(New York: The Macmillan Company,
1955), and E. Barker,
\bt{Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle}
(New York: Dover Publications, Imnc., 1959).
Both of these authors make slight reference to the \bt{Timaeus} while discussing Plato's \dq{Political Philosophy.}}
\defpnote{0.6}{R.G. Bury,
\et{Plato and History,}
\jt{Classical Quarterly,}
New Series, 1--2, pp. 86--94.}
\defpnote{0.7}{Edward MacKinnon, S.J.,
\et{Time in Contemporary Physics,}
\jt{International Philosophical Quarterly,}
II, 3, (September, 1962), p. 429.}
\defpnote{0.8}{Hermann Gauss,
\bt{Philosophischer Handkommentar zu den Dialogen Platos},
vol. III part 2 (Bern: Herbart Lang, 1961)}
\defpnote{0.9}{Bertrand Russell,
\bt{Mysticism and Logic}
(Garden City, New York: Doubleday \& Co., 1917). }
\defpnote{0.10}{Whitehead, loc, cit.}
\defpnote{0.11}{Werner Heisenberg,
\bt{Physics and Philosophy}
(New York: Harper \& Brothers, 1955), ch. 4.}
\defpnote{0.12}{See, for example. F.M. Cornford,
\bt{From Religion to Philosophy}
(New York: Harper \& Brothers, 1957).}
\defpnote{0.13}{F.M. Cornford,
\bt{Plato's Cosmology},
(London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, Ltd., 1937), p. 8.}
\defpnote{0.14}{Carl G. Hempel,
\et{Fundamentals of Concept Formation in Empirical Science,}
\bt{International Encyclopaedia of Unified Science},
vols. I and IT;
\ul{Foundations of the Unity of Science}
vol. II, no. 7 (University of Chicago Press, 1952)}
\defpnote{0.15}{Hans Meyerhoff, ed.,
\bt{The Philosophy of History in Our Time}
(New York: Doubleday \& Co., 1959),
which contains a valuable anthology of the important authors in this field and some of their most representative views.}
% chapter ii
\defpnote{1.1}{A.E. Taylor,
\bt{Commentary on Plato's Timaeus}
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1928), p. 4.}
\defpnote{1.2}{F.M. Cornford,
\bt{Plato's Cosmology},
p. viii.}
\defpnote{1.3}{Werner Jaeger,
\bt{Paideia: The Ideals of Greek Culture}
(3 vols.; New York: Oxford University Press, 1943), II, pp. 77--78. }
\defpnote{1.4}{Ibid., p. 78.}
\defpnote{1.5}{Ibid., p. 79.}
\defpnote{1.6}{C.F. Hermann,
\bt{Geschichte und System der Platonischen Philosophie}
(Heidelberg: 1839), in Jaeger,
op. cit., p. 79}
\defpnote{1.7}{Jaeger, op. cit., p. 79.}
\defpnote{1.8}{Ibid., p. 80.}
\defpnote{1.9}{Theodor Gompers,
\bt{Greek Thinkers},
trans. G.G. Berry
(London: John Murray, 1905).}
\defpnote{1.10}{Ibid., p. 275.}
\defpnote{1.11}{Ibid., p. 278.}
\defpnote{1.12}{Ibid.}
\defpnote{1.13}{Ibid., pp. 279, 283.}
\defpnote{1.14}{Ibid., p. 284.}
\defpnote{1.15}{Ibid., p. 285.}
\defpnote{1.16}{Ibid.}
\defpnote{1.17}{Ibid., p. 286.}
\defpnote{1.18}{Ibid., p. 287.}
\defpnote{1.19}{Jaeger, loc. cit.}
\defpnote{1.20}{L. Campbell,
\et{Plato,}
\bt{Encyclopaedia Britannica,}
11\tss{th} ed., Vol. XXI, pp. 808--824.}
\defpnote{1.21}{Ibid., p. 810.}
\defpnote{1.22}{Ibid.}
\defpnote{1.23}{Ibid.}
\defpnote{1.24}{U.V. Wilamowitz-Moellendorff,
\bt{Platon}, I,
(2\tss{nd} ed.;
Berlin: Weidman, 1920), in Jaeger, op. cit., p. 80.}
\defpnote{1.25}{Jaeger, op. cit., p. 84.}
\defpnote{1.26}{A.E. Taylor,
\et{Plato,}
\bt{Encyclopaedia Britannica},
XVIII (Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc., 1957),
p. 49.}
\defpnote{1.27}{Ibid.}
\defpnote{1.28}{A.E. Taylor, \bt{Commentary}, p. 4.}
\defpnote{1.29}{A.E. Taylor,
\bt{Plato: The Man and His Work}
(6\tss{th} ed.; 5\tss{th} print.; New York: Meridian Books, Inc., 1959),
p. 346}
\defpnote{1.30}{A.E. Taylor, \bt{Commentary}, p. 4.}
\defpnote{1.31}{Constantin Ritter,
\bt{The Essence of Plato's Philosophy},
trans. Adam Alles (London: George Allen \& Unwin, Ltd., 1933).}
\defpnote{1.32}{W. Lutoslawski,
\bt{Origin and Growth of Plato's Logic}
(New York: Longmans, 1928.)}
\defpnote{1.33}{John Burnet,
\bt{Greek Philosophy}
(London: Macmillan \& Co., Ltd., 1914), Part I, p. 212.}
\defpnote{1.34}{Cornford, op, cit.}
\defpnote{1.35}{Wilamowitz, \bt{Platon}, I, p. 591, in Jaeger,
op. cit., p. 8O.}
\defpnote{1.36}{Constantin Ritter,
\bt{Neue Untersuchungen uber Platon}
(Munich: 1910), p. 181.}
\defpnote{1.37}{Ritter, \bt{The Essence of Plato's Philosophy}, p. 9.}
\defpnote{1.38}{Ibid., p. 27.}
\defpnote{1.39}{Ibid., pp. 29--30.}
\defpnote{1.40}{G.C. Field, \bt{Plato and His Contemporaries: A Study in Fourth-Century Life and Thought} (London: Methuen \& Co., Ltd., 1930), p. 68.}
\defpnote{1.41}{Ross has summarized these results in tabular
form: see Appendix A.}
\defpnote{1.42}{A.E. Taylor, \et{Plato,} \bt{Encyclopaedia Britannica},
pp. 48--64.}
\defpnote{1.43}{Field, op. cit., p. 4.}
\defpnote{1.44}{According to Field, Plato's benefactor was
Archytas (Field, op. cit., p. 16), but according to
Gompers it was Anniceria (Gompers, op. cit., p. 261).}
\defpnote{1.45}{Field, op. cit., p. 18.}
\defpnote{1.46}{Gompers, op, cit., p. 261.}
\defpnote{1.47}{Ritter,
\bt{The Essence of Plato's Philosophy},
pp. 21--22.}
\defpnote{1.48}{Ibid., p. 22.}
\defpnote{1.49}{Ibid., p. 23.}
\defpnote{1.50}{Ibid.}
\defpnote{1.51}{Ibid., p. 24.}
\defpnote{1.52}{Ibid., p. 25.}
\defpnote{1.53}{Ibid., pe 26.}
\defpnote{1.54}{Ibid., p. 27.}
\defpnote{1.55}{Ritter op. cit., pp. 329 ff.;
\bt{Untersuchungen uber Platon}
(Stutheeres 1888), pp. 88 ff.}
\defpnote{1.56}{J. Harward, \bt{The Platonic Epistles} (Cambridge:
The University Press, 1932).}
\defpnote{1.57}{Harward, op, cit., p. 60.}
\defpnote{1.58}{B. Jowett,
\bt{The Dialogues of Plato}
(3\tss{rd} ed.; New York: Scribner, Armstrong, \& Co., 1878) preface.}
\defpnote{1.59}{H.T. Karsten,
\bt{De Epistolis quae feruntur Platonicis}
(Utrecht: 1864), in Harward, op, cit., p. 61.}
\defpnote{1.60}{Harward, op. cit., pp. 71--72.}
\defpnote{1.61}{Field, op. cit., p. 16.}
\defpnote{1.62}{Harward, op. cit., p. 76.}
\defpnote{1.63}{Ibid., pp. 86--96.}
\defpnote{1.64}{Ibid., p. 86.}
\defpnote{1.65}{Ritter,
\bt{Neue Untersuchungen uber Platon}, p. 408.}
\defpnote{1.66}{\bt{Tusc, Disp.} V, 35, in Harward, op. cit., p. 189.}
\defpnote{1.67}{Harward, op. cit., p. 192.}
\defpnote{1.68}{Not \e{learned.} Plato is talking about the
communication of philosophy, not the stating of it, nor
the acquisition of it, but the process in which, so to
speak, philosophy happens.}
\defpnote{1.69}{See the Cave Allegory of the \bt{Republic} 507.}
\defpnote{1.70}{i.e., it is in all probability not a posthumous
edition.}
% ch iii
% ch iv
\defpnote{2.1}{A.E. Taylor, \bt{Plato: The Man and His Work}, p. 2.}
\defpnote{2.2}{Cornford, \bt{Plato's Cosmology}, p. 2.}
\defpnote{2.3}{Gauss, \bt{Philosophischer Handkommentar zu den Dialogen Platos}, p. 157}
\defpnote{2.4}{Cornford, op. cit., appendix, p. 365.}
\defpnote{2.5}{P. Frutiger, \bt{Les Myths de Platon}, (Paris: 1930), pp. 244 ff.}
\defpnote{2.6}{Cornford, op. cit., p. 14.}
\defpnote{2.7}{Q. Lauer, S.J., \et{The Being of Non-Being in Plato's Sophist} (unpublished manuscript; New York: Fordham University).}
\defpnote{2.8}{Cornford, op. cit., p. 8.}
\defpnote{2.9}{A.E. Taylor, \bt{Plato: The Man and His Work}, p. 440.}
\defpnote{2.10}{Cf., V.J. Gioscia, \et{A Perspective for Role Theory,} \jt{The American Catholic Sociological Review,} XXII, 2 (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1961), pp. 143 ff.}
\defpnote{2.11}{Cornford, op. cit., p. 24.}
\defpnote{2.12}{Ibid., p. 28.}
\defpnote{2.13}{Ibid., p. 30.}
\defpnote{2.14}{Ibid., pp. 31--32.}
\defpnote{2.15}{R.D. Archer-Hind, \bt{Commentary on the Timaeus}, (London: The Macmillan Company, 1888), p. 86, n, 14.}
\defpnote{2.16}{T.T. Taylor, \bt{The Timaeus and Critias of Plato},
(Washington: Pantheon Books Inc., 1952), p. 112. }
\defpnote{2.17}{Ibid., p. 17.}
\defpnote{2.18}{Bury, \bt{Plato and History},\ednote{book or essay?} p. 5.}
\defpnote{2.19}{A.E. Taylor, \bt{Commentary}, p. 73.}
\defpnote{2.20}{Ibid.}
\defpnote{2.21}{Ibid., p. 74.}
\defpnote{2.22}{Ibid.}
\defpnote{2.23}{Ibid., p. 19.}
\defpnote{2.24}{Cornford, op. cit., p. x.}
\defpnote{2.25}{Ibid., pp. 11--12.}
% ch 5
\defpnote{3.1}{Cornford, \bt{Plato's Cosmology}, p. 31.}
\defpnote{3.2}{One is tempted to restore the hiatus which Cornford habitually tries to remove as \dq{intolerable.} Then the passage would read, \dq{he desired that all things should come as near as possible to being, like himself.}}
\defpnote{3.3}{A.E. Taylor, \bt{Commentary}, p. 37.}
\defpnote{3.4}{Ibid., p. 78.}
\defpnote{3.5}{T.T. Taylor,
\bt{The Timaeus and Critias of Plato}, pp. 29 ff.}
\defpnote{3.6}{e.g., Alexandre Koyre, \bt{From the Closed World to the
Infinite Universe}, (New York: Harper \& Brothers, 1958).}
\defpnote{3.7}{E.R. Dodds, \bt{The Greeks and the Irrational}
(Boston: Beacon Press, 1957).}
\defpnote{3.8}{George S. Claghorn, \bt{Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's
\sq{Timaeus}} (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1954), p. 87.}
\defpnote{3.9}{Cornford, op, cit., p. 59.}
\defpnote{3.10}{Ibid., p. 61.}
\defpnote{3.11}{A.E. Taylor, \bt{Commentary}, p. 128.}
\defpnote{3.12}{Cornford, loc. cit., "Kinds" is a peculiar expression which is repeated here only to assure an accurate representation of Cornford's view.}
\defpnote{3.13}{T.T. Taylor, op. cit., \et{Introduction.}}
\defpnote{3.14}{According to T.T. Taylor, loc. cit.}
\defpnote{3.15}{A.E. Taylor, \bt{Commentary}, Appendix.}
\defpnote{3.16}{Heisenberg, \bt{Physics and Philosophy}, ch. 4. See
also MacKinnon, \bt{Time in Contemporary Physics}, pp. 428--457.}
\defpnote{3.17}{Dodds, op. cit.}
\defpnote{3.18}{A.E. Taylor, \bt{Commentary}, p. 113.}
\defpnote{3.19}{A.E. Taylor, Cornford, Archer-Hind, Bury.}
\defpnote{3.20}{Cornford has \dq{So.}}
\defpnote{3.21}{Cornford, op. cit.}
\defpnote{3.22}{They do not really wander; see \bt{Laws} 822a.}
\defpnote{3.23}{Cornford has \dq{circuits.}}
% ch6
{4.1}{For example, in his chapter on the doctrine of the
Timaeus, Ross (W.D. Ross, \bt{Plato's Theory of Ideas}
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1951).) discusses the role of
Time not at all.}
{4.2}{Gauss, \bt{Philosophischer Handkommentar zu den
Dialogen Platos}, p. 157.}
{4.3}{Jowett, \bt{The Dialogues of Plato}, II, pp. 456--7.}
{4.4}{Bury, \et{Plato and History,}\ednote{essay or book?} p. 5.}
{4.5}{Walsh, \bt{Plato and the Philosophy of History}. See
also Barker, \bt{Political thought of Plato and Aristotle},
Nettleship, \bt{Lectures on the Republic of Plato},
Popper, \bt{The Open Society and its Enemies}, and numerous
anthologies which present Plato's \bt{Republic} but seldom if
ever present the \bt{Timaeus}.}
{4.6}{A.E. Taylor, \bt{Commentary}, pp. 689 ff.}
{4.7}{J.F. Callahan, \bt{Four Views of Time in Ancient
Philosophy} (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1948),
rightly says that A.E. Taylor errs here because of his
adoption of Aristotle's notion of Time.}
{4.8}{There are several aspects of Plato's discussion
of Time and Society which bear a marked resemblance to
some aspects of the philosophy of Anaximander, but a
discription of these similarities and differences would
require a lengthy discussion which would take us into
the origin of Plato's doctrines, whereas it is only our
purpose here to present and examine Plato's doctrine.
For example, while it would be instructive to investigate
the extent of Plato's indebtedness to Anaximander's
dark saying about the reparation which things offer in
Time for their injustices, (see, for example, John
Burnet, \bt{Early Greek Philosophy} (4\tss{th} ed.; London: Adam
and Charles Black; New York: Tne Macmillan Co., 1930),
pp. 52--53.) it would necessitate more comment than
we have room to present here.}
% appendix
{A.1}{W.D. Ross, \bt{Plato's Theory of Ideas} (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1951), p. 2.}
|