1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
|
\chapter{Subjective Propositional Vibration (Work in Progress)}
Up until the present, the scientific study of language has treated
language as if it were reducible to the mechanical manipulation of counters
on a board. Scientists have avoided recognizing that language has a mental
aspect, especially an aspect such as the 'understood meaning" of a linguistic
expression. This paper, on the other hand, will present linguistic constructs
which inescapably involve a mental aspect that is objectifiable and can be
subjected to precise analysis in terms of perceptual psychology. These
constructs are not derivable from the models of the existing linguistic
sciences. In fact, the existing linguistic sciences overlook the possibility of
such constructs.
Consider the ambiguous schema '$A\supset B\&C$', expressed in words as '$C$ and
$B$ if $A$'. An example is
\begin{equation}
\label{firstvib}
\parbox{4in}{Jack will soon leave and Bill will laugh if Don speaks.}
\end{equation}
In order to get sense out of this utterance, the reader has to supply it with a
comma. That is, in the jargon of logic, he has to supply it with grouping. Let
us make the convention that in order to read the utterance, you must
mentally supply grouping to it, or "bracket" it. If you construe the schema
as '$A\supset (B\&C)$', you will be said to bracket the conjunction. If you construe
the schema as '$(A\supset B)\&C$', you will be said to bracket the conditional. There
is an immediate syntactical issue. If you are asked to copy \ref{firstvib}, do you write
"Jack will soon leave and Bill will laugh if Don speaks"; or do you write
"Jack will soon leave, and Bill will laugh if Don speaks" if that is the way
you are reading \ref{firstvib} at the moment? A distinction has to be made between
reading the proposition, which involves bracketing; and viewing the
proposition, which involves reacting to the ink-marks solely as a pattern.
Thus, any statement about an ambiguous grouping proposition must specify
whether the reference is to the proposition as read or as viewed.
Some additional conventions are necessary. With respect to \ref{firstvib}, we
distinguish two possibilities: you are reading it, or you are not looking at it
(or are only viewing it). Thus, a "single reading" of \ref{firstvib} refers to an event
which separates two consecutive periods of not looking at \ref{firstvib} (or only
viewing it). During a single reading, you may switch between bracketing the
conjunction and bracketing the conditional. These switches demarcate a
series of "states" of the reading, which alternately correspond to "Jack will
soon leave, and Bill will laugh if Don speaks" or "Jack will soon leave and Bill
will laugh, if Don speaks". Note that a state is like a complete proposition.
We stipulate that inasmuch as \ref{firstvib} is read at all, it is the present meaning or
state that counts---if you are asked what the proposition says, whether it is
true, \etc
Another convention is that the logical status of
\begin{quotation}
(Jack will soon leave and Bill will laugh if Don speaks) if and only if (Jack
will soon leave and Bill will laugh if Don speaks)
\end{quotation}
is not that of a normal tautology, even though the biconditional when
viewed has the form '$A\equiv A$'. The two ambiguous components will not
necessarily be bracketed the same way in a state.
We now turn to an example which is more substantial than \ref{firstvib}.
Consider
\begin{quotation}
Your mother is a whore and you are now bracketing the conditional in (2) if
you are now bracketing the conjunction in (2). (2)
\end{quotation}
If you read this proposition, then depending on how you bracket it, the
reading will either be internally false or else will call your mother a whore. In
general, ambiguous grouping propositions are constructs in which the mental
aspect plays a fairly explicit role in the language. We have included (2) to
show that the contents of these propositions can provide more complications
than would be suggested by \ref{firstvib}.
There is another way of bringing out the mental aspect of language,
however, which is incomparably more powerful than ambiguous grouping.
We will turn to this approach immediately, and will devote the rest of the
paper to it. The cubical frame \cubeframe\ is a simple reversible perspective figure
which can either be seen oriented upward like \cubeup\ or oriented downward
like \cubedown. Both positions are implicit in the same ink-on-paper image; it is
the subjective psychological response of the perceiver which differentiates
the positions. The perceiver can deliberately cause the perspective to reverse,
or he can allow the perspective to reverse without resisting. The perspective
can also reverse against his will. Thus, there are three possibilities: deliberate,
indifferent, and involuntary reversal.
Suppose that each of the positions is assigned a different meaning, and
the figure is used as a notation. We will adopt the following definitions
because they are convenient for our purposes at the moment.
$$ \cubeframe \left\{\parbox{4in}{for '3' if it appears to be oriented like \cubeup \linebreak
for '0' if it appears to be oriented like \cubedown}\right\} $$
We may now write
\begin{equation}
\label{cubefour}
1+\cubeframe = 4
\end{equation}
We must further agree that \ref{cubefour}, or any proposition containing such
notation, is to be read to mean just what it seems to mean at any given
instant. If, at the moment you read the proposition, the cube seems to be
up, then the proposition means $1+3=4$; but if the cube seems to be down,
the proposition means $1+O=4$. The proposition has an unambiguous
meaning for the reader at any given instant, but the meaning may change in
the next instant due to a subjective psychological change in the reader. The
reader is to accept the proposition for what it is at any instant. The result is
subjectively triggered propositional vibration, or SPV for short. The
distinction between reading and viewing a proposition, which we already
made in the case of ambiguous grouping, is even more important in the case
of SPV. Reading now occurs only when perspective is imputed. In reading
\ref{cubefour} you don't think about the ink graph any more than you think about the
type face.
in a definition such as that of '\cubeframe', '3' and 'O' will be called the
assignments. A single reading is defined as before. During a single reading, \ref{cubefour}
will vibrate some number of times. The series of states of the reading, which
alternately correspond to '$1+3=4$' or '$1+O=4$', are demarcated by
these vibrations. The portion of a state which can change when vibration
occurs will be called a partial. It is the partials in a reading that correspond
directly to the assignments in the definition.
Additional conventions are necessary. Most of the cases we are
concerned with can be covered by two extremely important rules. First, the
ordinary theory of properties which have to do with the form of expressions
as viewed is not applicable when SPV notation is present. Not only is a
biconditional not a tautology just because its components are the same when
viewed; it cannot be considered an ordinary tautology even if the one
component's states have the same truth value, as in the case of '$1+\cubeframe\neq2$'.
Secondly, and even more important, SPV notation has to be present
explicitly or it is not present at all. SPV is not the idea of an expression with
two meanings, which is commonplace in English; SPV is a double meaning
which comes about by a perceptual experience and thus has very special
properties. Thus, if a quantifier should be used in a proposition containing
SPV notation, the "range" of the "variable" will be that of conventional
logic. You cannot write '\cubeframe' for '$x$' in the statement matrix
'$x=\cubeframe$'.
We must now elucidate at considerable length the uniqué properties of
SPV. When the reader sees an SPV figure, past perceptual training will cause
him to impute one or the other orientation to it. This phenomenon is not a
mere convention in the sense in which new terminology is a convention.
There are already two clear-cut possibilities. Their reality is entirely mental;
the external, ink-on-paper aspect does not change in any manner whatever.
The change that can occur is completely and inherently subjective and
mental. By mental effort, the reader can consciously control the orientation.
If he does, involuntary vibrations will occur because of neural noise or
attention lapses. The reader can also refrain from control and accept
whatever appears. In this case, when the figure is used as a notation,
vibrations may occur because of a preference for one meaning over the
other. Thus, a deliberate vibration, an involuntary vibration, and an
indifferent vibration are three distinct possibilities.
What we have done is to give meanings to the two pre-existing
perceptual possibilities. In order to read a proposition containing an SPV
notation at all, one has to see the ink-on-paper figure, impute perspective to
it, and recall the meaning of that perspective; rather than just seeing the
figure and recalling its meaning. The imputation of perspective, which will
happen anyway because of pre-existing perceptual training, has a function in
the language we are developing analogous to the function of a letter of the
alphabet in ordinary language. The imputation of perspective is an aspect of
the notation, but it is entirely mental. Our language uses not only
graphemes, but "psychemes" or "mentemes". One consequence is that the
time structure of the vibration series has a distinct character; different in
principle from external, mechanical randomization, or even changes which
the reader would produce by pressing a button. Another consequence is that
ambiguous notation in general is not equivalent to SPV. There can be mental
changes of meaning with respect to any ambiguous notation, but in general
there is no psycheme, no mental change of notation. It is the clear-cut,
mental, involuntary change of notation which is the essence of SPV. Without
psychemes, there can be no truly involuntary mental changes of meaning.
In order to illustrate the preceding remarks, we will use an SPV
notation defined as follows.
\begin{equation*}
\cubeframe \left\{\parbox{4in}{is an affirmative, read "definitely," if it appears to be oriented
like \cubeup\linebreak
is a negative, read "not," if it appears to be oriented like \cubedown}\right\}
\end{equation*}
The proposition which follows refers to the immediate past, not to all past
time; that is, it refers to the preceding vibration.
\begin{quotation}
You have \cubeframe deliberately vibrated (4). (4)
\end{quotation}
This proposition refers to itself, and its truth depends on an aspect of the
reader's subjectivity which accompanies the act of reading. However, the
same can be said for the next proposition.
\begin{quotation}
The bat is made of wood, and you have just decided that the second
word in (5) refers to a flying mammal. (5)
\end{quotation}
Further, the same can be said for (2). We must compare (5), (2), and (4) in
order to establish that (4) represents an order of language entirely different
from that represented by (5) and (2). (5) is a grammatical English sentence
as it stands, although an abnormal one. The invariable, all-ink notation 'bat'
has an equivocal referental structure: it may have either of two mutually
exclusive denotations. In reading, the native speaker of English has to choose
one denotation or the other; contexts in which the choice is difficult rarely
occur. (2) is not automatically grammatical, because it lacks a comma. We
have agreed on a conventional process by which the reader mentally supplies
the comma. Thus, the proposition lacks an element and the reader must
supply it by a deliberate act of thought. The comma is not, strictly speaking,
a notation, because it is entirely voluntary. The reader might as well be
supplying a denotation io an equivocal expression: (5) and (2) can be
reduced to the same principle. As for (4), it cannot be mistaken for ordinary
English. It has an equivocal "proto-notation," '\cubeframe'. You automatically
impute perspective to the proto-notation before you react to it as language.
Thus, a notation with a mental component comes into being involuntarily.
This notation has an unequivocal denotation. However, deliberate,
inditferent, and most important of all, involuntary mental changes in
notation can occur.
We now suggest that the reader actually read (5), (2), and (4), in that
order. We expect that (5) can be read without noticeable effort, and that a
fixed result will be arrived at (unless the reader switches in an attempt to
find a true state). The reading of (2) involves mentally supplying the comma,
which is easy, and comprehending the logical compound which . results,
which is not as easy. Again, we expect that a fixed result will be arrived at
(unless the reader vacillates between the insult and the internally false state).
In order to read (4), center your sight on the SPV notation, with your
peripheral vision taking in the rest of the sentence. A single reading should
last at least half a minute. If the reader will seriously read (4), we expect that
he will find the reading to be an experience of a totally different order from
the reading of (5) and (2). It is like looking at certain confusing visual
patterns, but with an entire dimension added by the incorporation of the
pattern into language. The essence of the experience, as we have indicated, is
that the original imputation of perspective is involuntary, and that the reader
has to contend with involuntary changes in notation for which his own mind
is responsible. We are relying on this experience to convince the reader
empirically that (4) represents a new order of language to an extent to which
(5) and (2) do not.
To make our point even clearer, let us introduce an operation, called
"collapsing," which may be applied to propositions containing SPV
proto-notation. The operation consists in redefining the SPV figure in a given
proposition so that its assignments are the states of the original proposition.
Let us collapse (4). We redefine
\begin{equation*}
\cubeframe \left\{\parbox{4in}{for 'You have deliberately vibrated (4)' if it appears to be oriented
like \cubeup\linebreak
for 'You have not deliberately vibrated (4)' if it appears to be oriented
like \cubedown}\right\}
\end{equation*}
(4) now becomes
\begin{quotation}
\cubeframe (4)
\end{quotation}
We emphasize that the reader must actually read (4), for the effect is
indescribable. The reader should learn the assignments with flash cards if
necessary.
The claim we want to make for (4) is probably that it is the most
clear-cut case yet constructed in which thought becomes an object for itself.
Just looking at a reversible perspective figure which is not a linguistic
utterance---an approach which perceptual psychologists have already
tried---does not yield results which are significant with respect to "thought."
In order to obtain a significant case, the apparent orientation or imputed
perspective must be a proposition; it must be true or false. Then, (5) and (2)
are not highly significant, because the mental act of supplying the missing
element of the proposition is all a matter of your volition; and because the
element supplied is essentially an "understood meaning." We already have an
abundance of understood meanings, but scientists have been able to ignore
them because they are not "objectifiable." In short, reversible perspective by
itself is not "thought"; equivocation by itself has no mental aspect which is
objectifiable. Only in reading (4) do we experience an "objectifiable aspect
of thought." We have invented an instance of thought (as opposed to
perception) which can be accomodated in the ontology of the perceptual
psychologist.
|