summaryrefslogtreecommitdiffstats
path: root/essays
diff options
context:
space:
mode:
Diffstat (limited to 'essays')
-rw-r--r--essays/flaws_underlying_beliefs.tex126
-rw-r--r--essays/flyntian_modality.tex21
-rw-r--r--essays/introduction.tex255
-rw-r--r--essays/philosophical_reflections.tex188
-rw-r--r--essays/philosophy_proper.tex1210
-rw-r--r--essays/some_objections.tex159
-rw-r--r--essays/walking_through_walls.tex156
7 files changed, 2115 insertions, 0 deletions
diff --git a/essays/flaws_underlying_beliefs.tex b/essays/flaws_underlying_beliefs.tex
new file mode 100644
index 0000000..0eda09e
--- /dev/null
+++ b/essays/flaws_underlying_beliefs.tex
@@ -0,0 +1,126 @@
+\chapter{The Flaws Underlying Beliefs}
+
+
+We begin with the question of whether there is a realm beyond my
+"immediate experience." Does the Empire State Building continue to exist
+even when I am not looking at it? If either of these questions can be asked,
+then there must indeed be a realm beyond my experience. If I can ask
+whether there is a realm beyond my experience, then the answer must be
+yes. The reason is that there has to be a realm beyond my experience in
+order for the phrase "a realm beyond my experience" to have any meaning.
+Russell's theory of descriptions will not work here; it cannot jump the gap
+between my experience and the realm beyond my experience. The assertion
+\speech{There is a realm beyond my experience} is true if it is meaningful, and that
+is precisely what is wrong with it. There are rules implicit in the natural
+language as to what is semantically legitimate. Without a rule that a
+statement and its negation cannot simultaneously be true, for example, the
+natural language would be in such chaos that nothing could be done with it.
+Aristotle's \booktitle{Organon} was the first attempt to explicate this structure formally,
+and Supplement D of Carnap's \booktitle{Meaning and Necessity} shows that hypotheses
+about the implicit rules of a natural language are well-defined and testable.
+An example of implicit semantics is the aphorism that \enquote{saying a thing is so
+doesn't make it so.} This aphorism has been carried over into the semantics
+of the physical sciences: its import is that there is no such thing as a
+substantive assertion which is true merely because it is meaningful. If a
+statement is true merely because it is meaningful, then it is too true. It must
+be some kind of definitional trick which doesn't say anything. And this is
+our conclusion about the assertion that there is a realm beyond my
+experience. Since it would be true if it were meaningful, it cannot be a
+substantive assertion.
+
+The methodology of this paper requires special comment. Because we
+are considering ultimate questions, it is pointless to try to support our
+argument on some more basic, generally accepted account of logic, language,
+and cognition. After all, such accounts are being called into question here.
+The only possible pproach for this paper is an internal critique of common
+sense and the natural language, one which judges them by reference to
+aspects of themselves.
+
+As an example of the application of our initial result to specific
+questions of belief, consider the question of whether the Empire State
+Building continues to exist when I am not looking at it. If this question is
+even meaningful, then there has to be a realm in which the nonexperienced
+Empire State Building does or does not exist. This realm is precisely the
+realm beyond my experience. The question of whether the Empire State
+Building continues to exist when I am not Jooking at it depends on the very
+assertion, about the existence of a realm beyond my experience, which we
+found to be nonsubstantive. Thus, the assertion that the Empire State
+Building continues to exist when I am not looking at it must also be
+considered as nonsubstantive or meaningless, as a special case of a
+definitional trick.
+
+We start by taking questions of belief seriously as substantive questions,
+which is the way they should be taken according to the semantics implicit in
+the natural language. The assertion that God exists, for example, has
+traditionally been taken as substantive; when American theists and Russian
+atheists disagree about its truth, they are not supposed to be disagreeing
+aboui nothing. We find, however, that by using the rules implicit in the
+natural language to criticize the natural language itself, we can show that
+belief-assertions are not substantive.
+
+Parallel to our analysis of belief-assertions or the realm beyond my
+experience, we can make an analysis of beliefs as mental acts. (We
+understand a belief to be an assertion referring to the realm beyond my
+experience, or to be the mental act of which the assertion is the verbal
+formulation.) Introspectively, what do I do when I believe that the Empire
+State Building exists even though I am not looking at it? I imagine the
+Empire State Building, and I have the attitude toward this mental picture
+that it is a perception rather than a mental picture. Let us bring out a
+distinction we are making here. Suppose I see a table. I have a so-called
+perception of a table, a visual table-experience. On the other hand, I may
+close my eyes and imagine a table. Independently of any consideration of
+"reality," two different types of experiences can be distinguished,
+non-mental experiences and mental experiences. A belief as a mental act
+consists of having the attitude toward a mental experience that it is a
+non-mental experience. The "attitude" which is involved is not a
+proposition. There are no words to describe it in greater detail; only
+introspection can provide examples of it. The attitude is a self-deceiving
+psychological trick which corresponds to the definitional trick in the
+belief-assertion.
+
+The entire analysis up until now can be carried a step farther. So far as
+the formal characteristics of the problem are concerned, we find that
+although the problem originally seems to center on "nonexperience," it
+turns out to center on "language." Philosophical problems exist only if there
+is language in which to formulate them. The flaw which we have found in
+belief-assertions has the following structure. A statement asserts the
+existence of something of a trans-experiential nature, and it turns out that
+the statement must be true if it is merely meaningful. The language which
+refers to nonexperience can be meaningful only if there is a realm beyond
+experience. The entire area of beliefs reduces to one question: are linguistic
+expressions which refer to nonexperience meaningful? We remark
+parenthetically that practically all language is supposed to refer to
+nonexperiences. Even the prosaic word "table" is supposed to denote an
+object, a stable entity which continues to exist when I am not looking at it.
+Taking this into account, we can reformulate our fundamental question as
+follows. Is language meaningful? Is there a structure in which symbols that
+we experience (sounds or marks) are systematically connected to objects, to
+entities which extend beyond our experience, to nonexperiences? In other
+words, is there language? (To say that there is language is to say that half of
+all belief-assertions are true. That is, given any belief-assertion, either it is
+true or its negation is true.) Thus, the only question we need to consider is
+whether language itself exists. But we see immediately, much more
+immediately than in the case of "nonexperience," that this question is
+caught in a trap of its own making. The question ought to be substantive. (Is
+there a systematic relation between marks and objects, between marks and
+nonexperiences? Is there an expression, "Empire State Building," which is
+related to an object outside one's experience, the Empire State Building, and
+which therefore has the same meaning whether one is looking at the Empire
+State Building or not? ) However, it is quite obvious that if one can even ask
+whether there is language, then the answer must be affirmative. Further, the
+distinction of language levels which is made in formal languages will not help
+here. Before you can construct formal languages, you have to know the
+natural language. The natural language is the infinite level, the container of
+the formal languages. If the container goes, everything goes. And this
+container, this infinite level language, must include its own semantics. There
+is no way to "go back before the natural language." As we mentioned
+before, the aphorism that "saying a thing is so doesn't make it so" is an
+example of the natural language's semantics in the natural language.
+
+in summary, the crucial assertion is the assertion that there is language,
+made in the natural language. This assertion is true if it is meaningful. It is
+too true; it must be a definitional trick. Beliefs stand or fall on the question
+of whether there is language. There is no way to get outside the definitional
+trick and ask this question in a way that would be substantive. The question
+simply collapses.
+
diff --git a/essays/flyntian_modality.tex b/essays/flyntian_modality.tex
new file mode 100644
index 0000000..a153ec1
--- /dev/null
+++ b/essays/flyntian_modality.tex
@@ -0,0 +1,21 @@
+\chapter{Instructions for the Flyntian Modality}
+
+\begin{enumerate}
+
+\item \textsc{ Stop all \enquote{gross believing,} such as belief in other minds, causality, and the phantom entities of science (atoms, electrons, \etc).}
+
+\item \textsc{Stop thinking in propositional language.}
+
+\item \textsc{Stop all scientific hypothesizing. Do not consider your "sightings" of the empire state building as confirmations that it is there when you are not looking at it --- or for that matter, as confirmations that it is there when you \emph{are} looking at it.}
+
+\item \textsc{Stop organizing visual experiences and tactile experiences into object-gestalts. Stop organizing so-called "different spatial orientations or different touched surfaces of objects" into object-gestalts. That is, stop having perceptions of objects.}
+
+\item \textsc{Stop believing in past and future time. That is, live out of time. Stop feeling longing, dread, or regret.}
+
+\item \textsc{Stop believing that you can move your body.}
+
+\item \textsc{Stop believing that these instructions have any objective meaning.}
+
+\item \textsc{You are now free to walk through walls (if you can find them).}
+\end{enumerate}
+
diff --git a/essays/introduction.tex b/essays/introduction.tex
new file mode 100644
index 0000000..130b2ce
--- /dev/null
+++ b/essays/introduction.tex
@@ -0,0 +1,255 @@
+\chapter{Introduction}
+
+
+This essay is the third in a series on the rationale of my career. It
+summarizes the results of my activities, the consistent outlook on a whole
+range of questions which I have developed. The first essay,
+\essaytitle{On Social Recognition}, noted that the official social philosophy of practically every
+regime in the world says that the individual has a duty to serve society to the
+best of his abilities. Social recognition is supposed to be the reward which
+indicates that the individual is indeed serving society. Now it happens that
+the most important tasks the individual can undertake are tasks (intellectual,
+political, and otherwise) posed by society. However, when the individual
+undertakes such tasks, society's actual response is almost always persecution
+(Galileo) or indifference (Mendel). Thus, the doctrine that the'individual has
+a duty to serve society is a hypocritical fraud. I reject every social
+philosophy which contains this doctrine. The rational individual will obtain
+the means of subsistence by the most efficient swindle he can find. Beyond
+this, he will undertake the most important tasks posed by society for his
+own private gratification. He will not attempt to benefit society, or to gain
+the recognition which would necessarily result if society were to utilize his
+achievements.
+
+The second essay, \essaytitle{Creep}, discussed the practices of isolating oneself;
+carefully controlling one's intake of ideas and influences from outside; and
+playing as a child does. I originally saw these practices as the effects of
+certain personality problems. However, it now seems that they are actually
+needed for the intellectual approach which I have developed. They may be
+desirable in themselves, rather than being mere effects of personality
+problems.
+
+I chose fundamental philosophy as my primary subject of investigation.
+Society presses me to accept all sorts of beliefs. At one time it would have
+pressed me to believe that the earth was flat; then it reversed itself and
+demanded that I believe the earth is round. The majority of Americans still
+consider it "necessary" to believe in God; but the Soviet government has
+managed to function for decades with an atheistic philosophy. Thus, which
+beliefs should I accept? My analysis is presented in writings entitled
+\essaytitle{Philosophy Proper}, \essaytitle{The Flaws Underlying Beliefs}, and
+\essaytitle{Philosophical Aspects of Walking Through Walls}.
+The question of whether a given belief is valid
+depends on the issue of whether there is a realm beyond my "immediate
+experience." Does the Empire State Building continue to exist even when I
+am not looking at it? If such a question can be asked, there must indeed be
+a realm beyond my experience, because otherwise the phrase 'a realm
+beyond my experience' could not have any meaning. (Russell's theory of
+descriptions does not apply in this case.) But if the assertion that there is a
+realm beyond my experience is true merely because it is meaningful, it
+cannot be substantive; it must be a definitional trick. In general, beliefs
+depend on the assertion of the existence of a realm beyond my experience,
+an assertion which is nonsubstantive. Thus, beliefs are nonsubstantive or
+meaningless; they are definitional tricks. Psychologically, when I believe that
+the Empire State Building exists even though I am not looking at it, I
+imagine the Empire State Building, and I have the attitude toward this
+mental picture that it is a perception rather than a mental picture. The
+attitude involved is a self-deceiving psychological trick which corresponds to
+the definitional trick in the belief assertion. The conclusion is that all beliefs
+are inconsistent or self-deceiving. It would be beside the point to doubt
+beliefs, because whatever their connotations may be, logically beliefs are
+nonsense, and their negations are nonsense also.
+
+The important consequence of my philosophy is the rejection of truth
+as an intellectual modality. I conclude that an intellectual activity's claim to
+have objective value should not depend on whether it is true; and also that
+an activity may perfectly weil employ false statements and still have
+objective value. I have developed activities which use mental capabilities that
+are excluded by a truth-oriented approach: descriptions of imaginary
+phenomena, the deliberate adoption of false expectations, the thinking of
+contradictions, and meanings which are reversed by the reader's mental
+reactions; as well as illusions, the deliberate suspension of normal beliefs, and
+phrases whose meaning is stipulated to be the associations they evoke. It
+must be clear that these activities are not in any way whatever a return to
+pre-scientific trrationalism. My philosophy demolishes astrology even more
+than it does astronomy. The irrationalist is out to deceive you; he wants you
+to believe that his superstitions are truths. My activities, on the other hand,
+explicitly state that they are using non-true material. My intent is not to get
+you to believe that superstitions are truths, but to exploit non-true material
+for rational purposes.
+
+The other initial subject of investigation I chose was art. The art which
+claims to have cognitive value is already demolished by my philosophical
+results. However, art at its most distinctive does not need to claim cognitive
+value; its value is claimed to be entertainmental or amusemental. What about
+art whose justification is simply that people like it? Consider things which
+are just liked, or whose value is purely subjective. I point out that each
+individual already has experiences, prior to art, whose value is purely
+subjective. (Call these experiences "brend.") The difference between brend
+and art is that in art, the thing valued is separated from the valuing of it and
+turned into an object which is urged on other people. Individuals tend to
+overlook their brend, and they do so because of the same factors which
+perpetuate art. These factors include the relation between the socialization
+of the individual and the need for an escape from work. The conditioning
+which causes one to venerate "great art" is also a conditioning to dismiss
+one's own brend. If one can become aware of one's brend without the
+distortion produced by this conditioning, one finds that one's brend is
+superior to any art, because it has a level of personalization and originality
+which completely transcends art.
+
+Thus, I reject art as an intellectual or cultural modality. In rejecting
+truth, I advocated in its place intellectual activities which have an objective
+value independent of truth. In rejecting art, I do not propose that it be
+replaced with any objective activity at all. Rather, I advocate that the
+individual become aware of his just-likings for what they are, and allow them
+to come out. If I succeed in getting the individual to recognize his own
+just-likings, then I will have given him infinitely more than any artist ever
+can.
+
+We are not finished with art, however. Ever since art began to
+disintegrate as an institution, modern art has become more and more of a
+repository for activities which represent pure waste, but which counterfeit
+innovation and objective value. A two-way process is involved here. On the
+one hand, the modern artist, faced with the increasing gratuitousness of his
+profession, desperately incorporates superficial references to science in his
+products in the hope of intimidating his audience. On the other hand, art
+itself has become an institution which invests waste with legitimacy and even
+prestige; and it offers instant rewards to people who wish to play the game.
+What is innovation in modern art? You take a poem by Shelly, cut it up into
+little pieces, shake the pieces up in a box, then draw them out and write
+down whatever is on them in the order in which they are drawn. If you call
+the result a "modern poem," people will suddenly be awed by it, whereas
+they would not have been awed otherwise. This sort of innovation is utterly
+mechanical and superficial. When artists incorporate scientific references in
+their products, the process is similarly a mechanical, superficial
+amalgamation of routine artistic material with current gadgets.
+
+Now there may be some confusion as to what the difference is between
+the products which result from this attempt to "save" art, and activities in
+the intellectual modality which I favor. There may be a tendency to confuse
+activities which are neither science nor art, but have objective value, with art
+products which are claimed to be "scientific" and therefore objectively
+valuable. To dispel this confusion, the following questions may be asked
+about art products.
+\begin{enumerate}
+\item If the product were not called art, would it immediately be seen to be
+worthless? Does the product rely on artistic institutions to "carry" it?
+
+\item Suppose that the artist claims that his product embodies major scientific
+discoveries, as in the case of a ballet dancer who claims to be working in the
+field of antigravity ballet. If the dancer really has an antigravity device,
+why can it only work in a ballet theater? Why can it
+only be used to make dancers jump higher? Why do you have to be able to
+perform "Swan Lake" in order to do antigravity experiments?
+\end{enumerate}
+To use a phrase from medical research, I contend that a real scientist would seek to
+isolate the active principle---not to obscure it with non-functional mumbo-jumbo.
+
+Both of these sets of questions make the same point, from somewhat
+different perspectives. Given an individual with a product to offer, does he
+actively seek out the lady art reporters, the public relations contracts, the
+museum officials, or does he actively dissociate himself from them? Does he
+seek artistic legitimation of his product, or does he reject it? The objective
+activities which I have developed stand on their own feet. They are not art,
+and to construe them as art would make it impossible to comprehend them.
+
+A definition of the intellectual modality which I favor is now in order.
+Until now, this modality has involved the construction of ideas such that the
+very possibility of thinking these ideas is a significant phenomenon. In other
+words, the modality has consisted of the invention of mental abilities. The
+ideas involve physical language, that is, language which occurs in beliefs
+about the physical world. Such language is philosophically meaningless, but
+it has connotations provided by the psychological trick involved in believing.
+The connotations are what are utilized; factual truth is irrelevant. Then, the
+ideas cannot be reduced to the mechanical manipulation of marks or
+counters---unlike ordinary mathematics. Also, logical truth, which happens to
+be discredited by my philosophical results, is irrelevant to the ideas.
+
+But the defining requirement of the modality is that each activity in it
+must have objective value. The activity must provide one with something
+which is useful irrespective of whether one likes it; that is, which is useful
+independently of whether it produces emotional gratification.
+
+We can now consider the following principle. "spontaneously and
+without any prompting to sweep human culture aside and to carry out
+elaborate, completely self-justifying activities." Relative to the social context
+of the individual's activities, this principle is absurd. We have no reason to
+respect the eccentric hobbyist, or the person who engages in arbitrary
+antisocial acts. If an action is to have more than merely personal significance,
+it must have a social justification, as is explained in On Social Recognition.
+In the light of The Flaws Underlying Beliefs and the brend theory, however,
+the principle mentioned above does become valid when it is interpreted
+correctly, because it becomes necessary to invent ends as well as means. The
+activity must provide an objective value, but this value will no longer be
+standardized.
+
+The modality I favor is best exemplified by \essaytitle{Energy Cube Organism},
+\essaytitle{Concept Art}, and the \essaytitle{Perception-Dissociator Model}.
+\essaytitle{Energy Cube Organism} is a perfect example of ideas such that the very
+possibility of thinking them is a significant phenomenon. It is also a perfect example of an
+activity which is useful irrespective of whether it provides emotional
+gratification. It combines the description of imaginary physical phenomena
+with the thinking of contradictions. It led to \essaytitle{Studies in Constructed
+Memories}, which in turn led to \essaytitle{The Logic of Admissible Contradictions}.
+With this last writing, it becomes obvious that the activity has applications
+outside itself.
+
+\essaytitle{Concept Art}\footnote{published in An Anthology ed. LaMonte Young, 1963}
+uses linguistic expressions which are changed by the reader's mental
+reactions. It led to \essaytitle{Post-Formalism in Constructed Memories}, and this led
+in turn to \essaytitle{Subjective Propositional Vibration}.
+
+The \essaytitle{Perception-Dissociator Model}\footnote{published in I-KON, Vol. 1, No. 5}
+was intended to exploit the realization that humans are the most
+advanced machines (or technology) that we have. I wanted to build a model
+of a machine out of humans, using a minimum of non-human props. Further,
+the machine modelled was to have capabilities which are physically
+impossible according to present-day science. I still think that the task as I
+have defined it is an excellent one; but the model does not yet completely
+accomplish the objective. The present model uses the deliberate suspension
+of normal beliefs to produce its effects.
+
+\essaytitle{Post-Formalism in Constructed Memories} and \essaytitle{Studies in
+Constructed Memories} together make up \booktitle{Mathematical Studies} (1966). In
+this monograph, the emphasis was on extending the idea of mathematics as
+formalistic games to games involving subjectivity and contradiction. In two
+subsequent monographs, the material was developed so as to bring out its
+potential applications in conjunction with science.
+\essaytitle{Subjective Propositional Vibration} investigates the logical
+possibilities of expressions which are changed by the reader's mental responses.
+\essaytitle{The Logic of Admissible Contradictions} starts with the experiences
+of the logically impossible which
+we have when we suffer certain perceptual illusions. These illusions enable us
+to imagine certain logical impossibilities just as clearly as we imagine the
+logically possible. The monograph models the content of these illusions to
+obtain a system of logic in which some (but not all) contradictions are
+"admissible." The theory investigates the implications of admitting some
+contradictions for the admissibility of other contradictions. A theory of
+many-valued numbers is also presented.
+
+The \essaytitle{Perception-Dissociator Model} led to
+\essaytitle{The Perception-Dissociation of Physics.} Again, here is an essay whose
+significance lies in the very possibility of thinking the ideas at all. The essay
+defines a change in the pattern of experience which would make it
+impossibie for physicists to "construct the object from experience." Finally,
+\essaytitle{Mock Risk Games} is the activity which involves the deliberate adoption of
+false expectations. It is on the borderline of the intellectual modality which I
+favor, because it seems to me to have objective value, and yet has not
+generated a series of applications as the other activities have.
+
+To summarize my general outlook, truth and art are discredited. They
+are replaced by an intellectual modality consisting of non-true activities
+having objective value, together with cach individual's brend. Consider the
+individual who wishes to go into my intellectual modality. What is the
+significance to him of the academic world, professional occupations, and the
+business of scholarships, fellowships, and grants? From the perspective of
+the most socially important tasks, these institutions have always rewarded
+the wrong things, as I argued in \essaytitle{On Social Recognition}. But in addition, the
+institutions as now organized are obstacles specifically to my intellectual
+modality. In fact, society in general has the effect of a vast conspiracy to
+prevent one from achieving the kind of consequential intellectual play which
+I advocate. The categories of thought which are obligatory in the official
+intellectual world and the media are categories in which my outlook cannot
+be conceived. And here is where the creep practices mentioned at the
+beginning of this essay become important. Isolation from society is
+presumably not inherent in my intelectual modality; but under present
+social conditions isolation is a prerequisite for its existence.
+
diff --git a/essays/philosophical_reflections.tex b/essays/philosophical_reflections.tex
new file mode 100644
index 0000000..7abca34
--- /dev/null
+++ b/essays/philosophical_reflections.tex
@@ -0,0 +1,188 @@
+\chapter{Philosophical Reflections I}
+
+\begin{enumerate} % TODO letters, sub numbers
+\item If language is nonsense, why do we seem to have it? How do these
+intricate pseudo-significant structures arise? If beliefs are self-deceiving, why
+are they there? Why are we so skilled in the self-deceptive reflex that I find
+in language and belief? Why are we so fluent in thinking in self-vitiating
+concepts? Granting that language and belief are mistakes, are mistakes of
+this degree of complexity made for nothing? Is not the very ability to
+concoct an apparently significant, self-vitiating and self-deceiving structure a
+transcendent ability, one that points to something non-immediate? Do not
+these conceptual gymnastics, even if self-vitiating, make us superior to the
+mindless animals?
+
+Such questions tempt one to engage in a sort of philosophical
+anthropology, using in part the method of introspection. Beliefs could be
+explained as arising in an attempt to deal with experienced frustrations by
+denying them in thought. The origin of Christian Science and magic would
+thereby be explained. Further, we could postulate a primal anxiety-reaction
+to raw experience. This anxiety would be lessened by mythologies and
+explanatory beliefs. The frustration and the anxiety-reaction would be
+primal non-cognitive needs for beliefs.
+
+Going even farther, we could suppose that a being which could
+apprehend the whole universe through direct experience would have no need
+of beliefs. Beliefs would be a rickety method of coping with the limited
+range of our perception, a method by which our imperfect brains cope with
+the world. There would be an analogy with the physicist's use of phantom
+models to make experimental observations easier to comprehend.
+
+However, there are two overwhelming objections to this philosophical
+anthropology. First, it purports to study the human mind as a derivative
+phenomenon, to study it from a God-like perspective. The philosophical
+anthropology thus consists of beliefs which are subject to the same
+objections as any other beliefs. It is on a par with any other beliefs; it has no
+privileged position. Specifically, it is in competition not only with my
+philosophy but with other accounts of the mind-reality relation, such as
+behaviorism, Platonism, and Thomism. And my philosophy provides me with
+no basis to defend my philosophical anthropology against their philosophical
+anthropologies. My philosophy doesn't even provide me with a basis to
+defend my philosophical anthropology against its own negation.
+
+In short, the paradoxes which my philosophy uncovers must remain
+unexplained and unresolved.
+
+The other objection to my philosophical anthropology is that its
+implications are unnecessarily conservative. An explanation of why people
+do something wrong can become an assertion that it is necessary to do wrong
+and finally a justification for doing wrong. But just because I tend, for
+example, to construe my perceptions as confirmations of propositions about
+phenomena beyond my experience does not mean that I must think in this
+way. To explain the modern cognitive orientation by philosophical
+anthropology tends to absolutize it and to conceal its dispensability.
+
+\item There are more legitimate tasks for the introspective "anthropology"
+of beliefs than trying to find primal non-cognitive needs for beliefs.
+Presupposing the analysis of beliefs as mental acts and self-deception which I
+have made elsewhere, we need to examine closely the boundary line between
+beliefs and non-credulous mental activity.
+
+Is my fear of jumping out of the window a belief? Strictly speaking,
+no. In psychological terms, a conditioned reflex does not require
+propositional thought.
+
+Is my identification of an object in different spatial orientations
+(relative to my field of vision) as "the same object" a belief? Apparently,
+but this is very ambiguous.
+
+Is my identification of tactile and visual "pencil-perceptions" as aspects
+of a single object (identity of the object as it is experienced through
+different senses) a belief? Yes.
+
+It is possible to subjectively classify bodily movements according to
+whether they are intentional, because drunken awkwardness, adolescent
+awkwardness, and movements under ESB are clearly unintentional. Then
+does intentional movement of my hand require a belief that I can move my
+hand? Definitely not, although in rare cases some belief will accompany or
+precede the movement of my hand. But believing itself will not get the hand
+moved!
+
+Is there any belief involved in identifying my leg, but not the leg of the
+table at which I am sitting, as part of my body? Maybe---another ambiguous
+case.
+
+Are my emotions of longing and dread beliefs in future time? Is my
+emotion of regret belief in past time? Philosophical anthropology: these
+temporal feelings precede and give rise to temporal beliefs. (?)
+
+How can I introspectively analyze my dread as dread of future injury if
+my belief in the existence of the future is invalid to begin with? Easily---the
+object of the fear is a belief or has a belief associated with it.
+
+\gap
+
+\item At one point Alten claimed that his dialectical approach does not
+take any evidence as being more immediate, more primary, than any other
+evidence. Our "immediate experience" is mediated; it is a derived
+phenomenon which only subsists in an objective reality that is outside our
+subjective standpoint.
+
+\begin{enumerate}
+
+\item But Alten does not seriously defend the claim that he does not
+distinguish between immediate and non-immediate. The claim that there is
+no distinction would be regarded as demented in every human culture. Every
+culture supposes that I may be tricked or cheated: there is a realm, the
+non-immediate or non-experienced, which provides an arena for surreptitious
+hostility to me. Every culture supposes that it is easier for me to tell what I
+am thinking than what you are thinking. Every culture supposes that I will
+hear things which I should not accept before I go and see for myself. Alten is
+simply not iconoclastic enough to reject these commonplaces. What he
+apparently does is, like the perceptual psychologist, to accept the distinction
+between immediate and non-immediate, and to accept the former as the only
+way of confirming a model, but to construct a model of the relation between
+the two in which the former is analyzed as a derivative phenomenon.
+
+\item Alten proposes to analyze his own awareness as a derivative
+phenomenon, to take a stance outside all human awareness. But this is the
+pretense of the God-like perspective. He postulates both his own limitedness
+and his ability to step outside it! This is an overt contradiction. Indeed, it is
+the archetype of the overt self-deception in beliefs which my philosophy
+exposes. "I can tell the Empire State Building exists now even though I
+cannot now perceive it."
+\end{enumerate}
+
+\item In my technical philosophical writings, I call attention to certain
+self-vitiating "nodes" in the logic of common sense. These nodes include the
+concept of non-experience and the assertion that there is language. I often
+find that others dismiss these examples as jokes that can be isolated from
+cognition or the logic of common sense, rather than acknowledging that they
+are self-vitiating nodes in the logic of common sense. As a result, I have
+concluded that it is probably futile to debate the abstract validity of my
+analysis of these nodes. It does indeed appear as if I am debating over an
+abstract joke, and it is not apparent why I would attribute such great
+importance to a joke.
+
+\essaytitle{Philosophical Aspects of Walking Through Walls} represents my
+present approach. The advantage of this approach is that it makes
+unmistakable the reason why I attribute so much importance to these
+philosophical studies. I am not merely debating the abstract validity of a few
+isolated linguistic jokes; I seek to overthrow the life-world. The only
+significance of my technical philosophical writings is to offer an explanation
+of why the life---world is subject to being undermined.
+
+When I speak of walking through walls, the mistake is often made of
+trying to understand this reference within the framework of present-day
+scientific common sense. Walking through walls is understood as it would be
+pictured in a comic-book episode. But such an understanding is quite beside
+the point. What I am advocating---to skip over the intermediate details and go
+directly to the end result---is a restructuring of the whole modern cognitive
+orientation such that one doesn't even engage in scientific hypothesizing or
+have "object perceptions," and thus wouldn't know whether one was
+walking through a wail or not.
+
+At first this suggestion may seem like another joke, a triviality. But my
+genius consists in recognizing that it is not, that there is a residue of
+non-vacuity and non-triviality in this proposal. There may be only a
+hair's-breadth of difference between the state I propose and mental
+incompetance or death---but still, there is all of a hair's-breadth. I magnify
+this hair's-breadth many times, and use it as a lever to overturn civilization.
+
+\item I am often asked in philosophical discussion how it is that we are
+now talking if language is vitiated. Let me comment that merely pointing
+over and over to one of the two circumstances which create a paradox does
+not resolve the paradox. Indeed, a paradox arises when there are two
+circumstances in conflict. The "fact" that we are talking is one of the two
+circumstances which conjoin in the paradox of language; the other
+circumstance being the self-vitiating "nodes" I have mentioned. To repeat
+over and over that we are now talking does not resolve any paradoxes.
+
+Contrary to what the question of how it is that we are now talking
+suggests, we do not "see" language. (That is, we do not experience an
+objective relation between words and things.) The language we "see" is a
+shell whose "transcendental reference" is provided by self-deception.
+
+\item Does the theory of amcons show that the contradiction exposed in
+\essaytitle{The Flaws Underlying Beliefs} is admissible and thus loses its philosophical
+force? No. An amcon is between two things that you see, e.g. stationary
+motion. It is between two sensed qualities, the simultaneous experiencing of
+contradictory qualities. (But "He left an hour ago" begins to be a borderline
+case. Here the point is the ease with which we swallow an expression which
+violates logical rules. Also expansion of an arc: a case even more difficult to
+classify.) The contradiction in \essaytitle{The Flaws Underlying Beliefs} has to do first
+with the logic of common sense, with the logical rules of language. It has to
+do, secondly, with the circumstance that you don't see something, yet act as
+if you do. Amcons should not be used to justify self-deception in the latter
+sense, to rescue every cheap superstition.
+\end{enumerate}
diff --git a/essays/philosophy_proper.tex b/essays/philosophy_proper.tex
new file mode 100644
index 0000000..45fb9a2
--- /dev/null
+++ b/essays/philosophy_proper.tex
@@ -0,0 +1,1210 @@
+\chapter{Philosophy Proper (\enquote{Version 3,} 1961)}
+\subsection*{Chapter 1: Introduction (Revised, 1973)}
+
+This monograph defines philosophy as such---philosophy proper---to be
+an inquiry as to which beliefs are "true," or right. The right beliefs are
+tentatively defined to be the beliefs one does not deceive oneself by holding.
+Although beliefs will be regarded as mental acts, they will be identified by
+their propositional formulations. Provisionally, beliefs may be taken as
+corresponding to non-tautologous propositions.
+
+Philosophy proper is an ultimate activity in the sense that no belief or
+supposed knowledge is conceded to be above philosophical examination. It is
+also an unavoidable activity in the sense that the notion of a belief, and the
+notion of judging the truth of a belief, are intrinsic to common sense and the
+natural language. Philosophers may not have achieved convincing results in
+philosophy proper; but the question of which beliefs are right is
+continuously posed for us even if we do not respect the way in which
+philosophers have dealt with it.
+
+All of the obstacles to philosophy proper arise because beliefs are
+normally held in order to satisfy non-cognitive needs. It will be heipful to
+examine this situation at some length. However, nothing can be done here
+beyond examining the situation. It is already clear that the interest of this
+monograph in beliefs is cognitive. It would be inappropriate to try to gain
+approval for philosophy proper by appealing to the values of those who hold
+beliefs in order to satisfy non-cognitive needs.
+
+it is implicit in beliefs that they correspond to cognitive claims, that
+they are subject to being judged true or false, and that their value rests on
+their truth. Nevertheless, beliefs can and do satisfy non-cognitive needs,
+quite apart from whether they are true. In order for a belief to satisfy some
+non-cognitive need, it is not necessary for the belief to be true; it merely has
+to be held. Concern with the ultimate philosophical validity of beliefs is rare.
+Concern with beliefs is normally concern with their ability to satisfy
+non-cognitive needs.
+
+To be specific, the literature of credulity contains remarks such as "I
+could not stand to live if I did not believe so-and-so," or "Even if so-and-so is
+true I don't want to know it." These remarks manifest the needs with which
+we are concerned. To take note of these remarks is already to uncover a level
+of self-deception. It is important to realize that this self-deception is explicit
+and self-admitted. To recognize it has nothing to do with imputing
+subconscious motives to behavior, as is done in psychoanalysis. Further, to
+recognize it is by no means to advance a theory of the ultimate origin of
+beliefs, a theory which would presuppose a judgment as to the philosophical
+validity of the beliefs. To theorize that the ultimate origin of beliefs lies in
+the denial of frustrating experiences, or in primal anxieties which are
+alleviated by mythological inventions, would be inappropriate when we have
+not even begun our properly philosophical inquiry. The only self-deceptions
+being considered here are admitted self-deceptions.
+
+A partial classification of the circumstances in which beliefs are held for
+non-cognitive reasons follows.
+
+\begin{enumerate}
+\item Beliefs may be directly tied to one's morale. "I couldn't stand to live if I didn't believe in God." "If President Nixon is guilty I don't want to know it."
+
+\item One may believe for reasons of conformity. The conversion of Jews to Catholicism in late medieval Spain was an extreme example.
+
+\item The American philosopher Santayana said that he believed in Catholicism for esthetic reasons.
+
+\item Moral doctrines are sometimes justified on the grounds of their efficacy in maintaining public order, rather than their philosophical validity.
+
+\item A more complicated and more interesting situation arises when one
+who claims to be engaged in a cognitive inquiry somehow circumscribes the
+inquiry so as to ensure in advance that it will yield certain preferred results.
+Such a circumscribed inquiry will be called "theologizing," in recognition of
+the archetypal activity in this category.
+
+When we raise the question of whether the natural sciences are
+instances of theologizing, it becomes apparent that the issue of non-cognitive
+motives for beliefs is no light matter. According to writers on the scientific
+method such as A. d'Abro, the scientist is compelled to operate as if he
+believed in the "real existence of a real absolute objective universe---a
+common objective world, one existing independently of the observer who
+discovers it bit by bit." The scientist holds this belief, even though it is a
+commonplace of college philosophy courses that it is unprovable, because he
+must do so in order to get on to the sort of results he considers desirable.
+The scientist claims to be engaged in a cognitive inquiry; yet the inquiry
+begins with an act of faith which it is impermissible to scrutinize. It follows
+that science is an instance of theologizing. If scientists cannot welcome a
+demonstration that their "metaphysical" presuppositions are invalid, then
+their interest in science cannot be cognitive.
+
+The scientist's non-cognitive motive for believing differs from the
+non-cognitive motives described earlier in one notable respect. Each of the
+non-cognitive needs described earlier required a given belief, and could not
+be satisfied by that belief's negation. But inside a science's circumscribed
+area of inquiry, the scientist can welcome the establishment of either of two
+contradictory propositions; in other words, his non-cognitive need can be
+satisfied by either proposition. It is in this sense that he can impartially test
+or decide between two propositions, or make new discoveries. On the other
+hand, with regard to the metaphysical presuppositions of science, only a
+single alternative is welcome.
+
+\item Academicians will readily acknowledge that they are not interested
+in scholarly work by unknown persons with no academic credentials. To
+academic mathematicians and biologists, whether Galois and Mendel had
+made valid discoveries was irrelevant. Thus, academicians as academicians
+circumscribe their purported interest in the cognitive in two ways---once as
+scientists; and once for reasons of personal gain and prestige.
+
+\item The strangest instance of a non-cognitive need for a belief is
+provided by the person who holds a fearful belief which is widely considered
+to be superstitious, such as belief in Hell. As always, the test of whether the
+motive for the belief is cognitive is the question of whether the person would
+welcome a demonstration that the belief is invalid. There is reason to suspect
+that persons who cling to fearful beliefs would not welcome such a
+demonstration, perverse as their attitude may seem. After all, they take no
+comfort in the widespread rejection of the belief as superstitious. Thus, it
+seems that a masochistic need for fearful beliefs must be recognized.
+\end{enumerate}
+
+This examination of non-cognitive motives for beliefs is, to repeat,
+limited to circumstances in which there is explicit self-deception, or
+self-deception that can be demonstrated directly from internal evidence. The
+examination cannot be carried further unless we become able to judge
+whether the beliefs referred to are, after all, valid. Thus, we will now turn to
+our properly philosophical inquiry, which will occupy the remainder of this
+monograph.
+
+\signoffnote{(Note: Chapters 2-7 were written in 1961, at a time when I used
+unconventional syntax and punctuation. They are printed here without
+change.)}
+
+\section{The Linguistic Solution of Properly Philosophical Problems}
+\subsection*{Chapter 2 : Preliminary Concepts}
+
+In this part of the book I will be concerned to solve the problem of
+philosophy proper, the problem of which beliefs are right, by discussing
+language, certain linguistic expressions. To motivate what follows I might
+tentatively say that I will consider beliefs as represented by statements,
+formulations of them (for example, \formulation{Other persons have minds} as
+representing the belief that other persons have minds), so that the problem
+will be which statements are true. Actually, to solve this problem we will be
+driven far beyond answers to the effect that given statements are true (or
+false).
+
+To make this book as engaging as possible, I would like to start right
+into the solution of the problem, to begin with the material in the next
+chapter. However, it effects, I think, a considerable clarification and
+simplification of the presentation of the solution if I first introduce certain
+concepts in an extended discussion. Then, when they enter into the solution
+they won't have to be just suggested in a condensed explanation which has
+to be repeated over and over. Thus, this chapter will be a properly
+philosophically neutral introduction of the concepts, an introduction which
+doesn't in itself say anything about the rightness of given beliefs (or the
+truth of given statements). The chapter is as a result not so interesting as the
+others, but I hope the reader will bear with me through it.
+
+The first concept is a new one, that of "explication". Explication of a
+familiar linguistic expression is what might traditionally be said to be finding
+a definition of the expression; it amounts partly to determining what it is
+wanted that the expression "mean". To explain: I will be discussing
+philosophically important expressions, familiar to the reader, such that their
+"meaning" needs clarifying, such that it is not clear to him how he wants to
+use them. I will be concerned with the suggestion of expressions, of which
+the "meanings", uses, are clear, which will be acceptable to the reader as
+replacements for the expressions of which the uses are obscure; that is,
+which have the uses that, it will turn out, the expressions of which the uses
+are obscure are supposed to have. Since the expressions which are to be
+replacements can be equivalent as expressions (sounds, bodies of marks) to
+the expressions they are to replace, it can also be said that I will be
+concerned with the suggestion of clear uses, of the expressions of which the
+uses are obscure, which are, it will turn out, the uses the reader wants the
+expressions to have. To be more specific about the conditions of
+acceptability of such replacements, if the familiar expressions (expressions of
+which the uses were obscure) were supposed to be names, have referents
+(and non-referents), then the new: expressions must clearly have referents.
+Further, the new expressions must deserve (by having appropriate referents
+in the case of names) the principal connotations of the familiar expressions,
+especially the distinctive, honorific connotations of the familiar expressions.
+(I will not say here just how I use "connotation". What the connotations of
+an expression are will be suggested by giving sentences about, in the case of a
+supposed name for example, what the referents of the expression are
+supposed to be like.) "Finding", or constructing, an expression (with its use)
+supposed to be acceptable to oneself as.a replacement, of the kind described,
+for an expression familiar to oneself, will be said to be "explicating" the
+expression familiar to oneself. The expression to be replaced will be said to
+be the "explicandum", and the suggested replacement, the "explication".
+Incidentally, if clarification shows that the desired use of the explicandum is
+inconsistent, then it can't have an explication at all acceptable, or what is the
+same thing, any explication will be as good as any other.
+
+I should mention that my use of "explication" is different from that of
+Rudolph Carnap, from whom I have taken the word rather than use the very
+problematic "definition". For him, explication is a scientist's, or philosopher
+of science's, devising a new precise concept, useful in natural science,
+suggested by a vague, unclear common concept (for example, that of
+"work"); whereas for me it is in effect constructing (if possible) that precise,
+clear concept which is the nearest equivalent to an unclear common concept.
+
+Here is an example in the acceptability of explications. Suppose that an
+expression is suggested, as an explication for "thing having a mind" (if
+supposed to be a name, have referents), which has as referents precisely the
+things which have certain facial expressions, or talk, or have certain other
+"overt" behavior, or even certain brain electricity. Then I expect that this
+expression will not be acceptable to the reader as an explication for "thing
+having a mind", since "thing having a mind" presumably has the connotations
+for the reader "that having a mind is not the same as, is very different from,
+higher than, having certain facial expressions, talking, certain other overt
+behaving, or having certain brain electricity---the mind is observable only by
+the thing having it", and the explication doesn't deserve these connotations:
+the connotations of the explicandum are exclusive of the referents of the
+proposed explication. It doesn't make any difference if there's a causual
+connection between having a mind and the other things, because the
+expression 'thing having a mind' itself, and not the supposed effects of
+having a mind, is what is under discussion.
+
+As the reader can tell from the example, I will, in evaluating
+expressions, have to speak of what I assume the connotations of words are
+for the reader. If any of my assumptions are incorrect, the book will be
+slightly less relevant to the reader's philosophical problems than it would be
+otherwise. Even so, the reader should get from this part the method of
+finding good explications, and its use in solving properly philosophical
+problems.
+
+Especially important in deciding whether an explication for a supposed
+name is good is the check of the referents of the explication against the
+connotations of the explicandum. Traditional philosophers, in the rare cases
+when they have suggested explications for expressions in dealing with
+philosophical problems, have suggested absurdly bad ones, which can quickly
+be shown up by such a check. Examples which are typically horrible are the
+explications for "thing having a mind" mentioned above.
+
+The second concept I will discuss is that of true statement. As I will be
+discussing the "truth" of formulations of beliefs, statements, in the next two
+chapters, and as the concept of true statement is quite obscure (making it a
+good example of one needing explication), it will be helpful for me to clarify
+the concept beforehand, to give a partial explication for "true statement".
+(Partial because the explication, although much clearer than the
+explicandum, will itself have an unclear word in it.)
+
+Well, what is a "statement"? How do what are usually said to be
+"statements" state? Take a book and look through it, a book in a language
+you don't read, so you won't assume that it's obvious what it means. What
+does the book, the object, do? How does it work? Note that talking just
+about the marks in the book, or what seem (!) to be the rules of their
+arrangement, or the like, won't answer these questions. In fact, I expect that
+when the reader really thinks about them, the questions won't seem easy
+ones to answer. Now to begin answering them, one of the most important
+connotations of "true statement", and, more generally, of "statement", as
+traditionally and commonly used, is that a "statement" is an "assertion
+which has truth value" (is true or false) (or "has content", as it is sometimes
+said, rather misleadingly). That is, the "verbal" part of a statement is
+supposed to be related in a certain way to something "non-verbal", or at
+least not in the language the verbal part of the statement is in. Further, a
+statement is supposed to be "true" or not because of something having to do
+with the non-verbal thing to which the verbal part of the statement is
+related. (The exceptions are the "statements" of formalist logic and
+mathematics, which are not supposed to be assertions; they are thus
+irrelevant to statements of the kind ordinary persons and philosophers are
+interested in.) Thus, if "true statement" is to be explicated, "assertion having
+truth value" and "is true" (and "has content" in a misleading use) have to be
+explicated, as they are obscure, and as it must be clear that the explication
+for "true statement" deserves the connotations which were suggested with
+"assertion having truth value" and "is true". One important conclusion from
+these observations is that although "sentences" (the bodies of sound or
+bodes of marks such as "The man talks") are often said to be "statements",
+would not be sufficient (to say the least) to explicate "statement" by simply
+identifying it with "sentence" (in my sense); something must be said about
+such matters as that of being an assertion having truth value. For the same
+reason, it is not sufficient (to say the least) to simply identify "statement"
+with "sentence", the latter being explicated in terms of the ("formal") rules
+for the formation of (grammatical) sentences, as these rules have no
+reference to such matters as that of being an assertion having truth value.
+
+In explicating "true statement" I will use the most elegant approach, one
+relevant to the interest in such matters as that of being an assertion having
+truth value. This is to begin by describing a simple, if not the simplest, way
+to make an assertion. As an example, I will describe the simplest way to
+make the assertion that a thing is a table. The way is to "apply" \term{table} to
+the thing. It is supposed that \term{table} has been "interpreted", that is, that it is
+"determinate" to which, of all things, applications of \term{table} are (to be said
+to be) "true". (It is good to realize that it is also supposed that it is
+"determinate" which, of all things (events), are "occurrences of the word
+"table", are expressions "equivalent to" "table".) The word "determinate" is
+the intentionally ambiguous one in this explication; I don't want to commit
+myself yet on how an expression becomes interpreted. As for 'apply', one
+can "apply" the word to the thing by pointing out "first" the word and
+"then" the thing. 'point out' is restricted to refer to "ostension", pointing
+out things in one's presence, things one is perceiving, and not to "directing
+attention to things not in one's presence" as well. The assertion is 'true', of
+course, if and only if the thing to which 'table' is applied is one of the things
+to which it is determinate that the application of 'table' is (to be said to be)
+"true", otherwise "false". It should be clear that such a pointing out of a
+"first" thing and a "second", the first being an interpreted expression, is an
+assertion of a simple kind, does have truth value and so forth. Let me further
+suggest 'interpreted expression' as an explication for 'name'; with respect to
+this explication, the things to which equivalent names ("occurances of a
+name") may be truthfully applied are the referents of the equivalent names,
+other things being non-referents. (Incidentally, I could have started with the
+concept of a name and its referents, and then said how to make a simple
+assertion using a name.) Then what I have intentionally left ambiguous is
+how a name has referents; I have not said, for example, whether the relation
+between name and referents is an "objective, metaphysical entity", which
+would be getting into philosophy proper.
+
+The point of describing this simple way of making an assertion is that
+what one wants to say are "statements", namely sentences used in the
+context of certain conventions, can be regarded as assertions of the "simple"
+kind; thus an explication for 'true statement' can be found. To do so, first
+let us say that the "complex name" gotten by replacing a sentence's "main
+verb" with the corresponding participle is the "associated name" of the
+sentence. For example, the associated name of 'Boston is in Massachusetts' is
+'Boston being in Massachusetts'. In the case of a sentence with coordinate
+clauses there may be a choice with respect to what is to be taken as the main
+verb, but this presents no significant difficulty. Example: sentence: \said{The
+table in the room will have been black only if it had been pushed by one
+man while the other man talked}; main verb: 'will have been' or 'had been
+pushed'. Also, English may not have a participle to correspond to every verb,
+but this is in theory no difficulty; the lacking participle could obviously be
+invented. Now what we would like to say one does, in using a sentence to
+make a statement, is to so to speak "assert" its associated name; this
+"asserted name" being "true" if and only if it has a referent. However, one
+doesn't assert names; names just have referents---it is statements that one
+makes, "asserts", and that are "true" or "false". How, then, do we explicate
+this "asserting" of a name? By construing it as that assertion, of the simple
+kind, which is the application of 'having a referent' to the name. In other
+words, from our theoretical point of view, to use a sentence to make a
+statement, one begins with a name (the sentence's associated name), and
+puts it into the sentence form, an act equivalent by convention to applying
+'having a referent' to it. For example, the sentence 'Boston is in
+Massachusetts' should be regarded as the simple assertion which is the
+application of 'having a referent' to 'Boston being in Massachusetts'.
+
+Now this approach may seem "unnatural" or incomplete to the reader
+for several reasons. First there is the syntactical oddity: the sentence is
+replaced by a statement "about" it (or to be precise its associated name).
+Well, all I can say is that this oddity is the inevitable result of trying to
+describe explicitly all that happens when one uses a sentence to make a
+statement; I can assure the reader that the alternate approaches are even
+more unnatural. Secondly, it may seem natural enough to speak of
+interpreting "simple names" (Fries' Class 1 words), but not so natural to
+speak of interpreting complex names (what could their referents be?). Of
+course, this is because complex names are to be regarded as formed from
+simpler names by specified methods; that is, their interpretations (and thus
+referents) are in specified relations to those of the simple names from which
+they are formed. The relations are indicated by the words, in the complex
+names, which are not names, and by the order of the words in the complex
+names. An example worth a comment is associated names containing such
+words as 'the'; in making statements, these names have to be in the context
+of additional conventions, understandings, to have significance. It will be
+clear that what these relations (and referents) are, the explication of these
+relations, is not important for my purposes. Thirdly, I have not said anything
+about what the "meaning" (intension), as opposed to the referents (and
+non-referents), of a name is. (I might say that a thing can't have an intension
+unless it has referents or non-referents.) This matter is also not important for
+my purposes (and gets into philosophy proper). Finally, my approach tells
+the reader no more than he already knew about whether a given statement is
+true. Quite so, and I said that the discussion would be properly
+philosophically neutral. In fact, it is so precisely because of the ambiguous
+word 'determinate', because I haven't said anything about how names get
+referents. Even so, we have come a long way from blank wonder about how
+one (sounds, marks) could ever state anything, a long way towards
+explicating how asserting works. (And to the philosopher of language with
+formalist prejudices, the discussion has been a needed reminder that if
+language is to be assertional, say something, then names and referring in
+some form must have the central role in it.)
+
+"Statements", then, can be regarded as assertions of the 'simple' kind
+which are made in the special, conventional way, involving sentences, I have
+described. I could thus explicate 'true statement' as referring to those true
+"simple" assertions made in the special way, and it should be clear that this
+would be a good explication. However, as the connotations of 'true
+statement' having to do with the method of apptying the first member to the
+second are, I expect, of secondary importance compared to those having to
+do with such matters as being an assertion having truth value, it ts more
+elegant to explicate 'true statement' as referring to all true assertions of the
+"simple" kind. For the purposes of this book it is not important which of
+the two explications the reader prefers.
+
+So much for the preliminaries.
+
+\subsection*{Chapter 3 : "Experience"}
+
+I will introduce in this chapter some basic terminology, as the main step
+in taking the reader from ordinary English and traditional philosophical
+language to a language with which my philosophy can be exposited. This
+terminology is important because one of the main difficulties in expositing
+my philosophy (or any new philosophy) is that current language is based on
+precisely some of the assumptions, beliefs, I intend to question. It will, I
+think, be immediately clear to the reader at all familiar with modern
+philosophy that the problems of terminology I am going to discuss are
+relevant to the problem of which beliefs are right.
+
+First, consider the term 'non-experience'. Although the concept of a
+non-experience is intrinsically far more "difficult" than the concept of
+"experience" which I will be discussing presently, it is, I suppose,
+presupposed in all "natural languages" and throughout philosophy, is so
+taken for granted that it is rarely discussed in itself. Thus, the reader should
+have no difficulty understanding it. Examples of non-experiences are
+perceivable objects---for example, a table (as opposed to one's perceptions of
+it), existing external to oneself, persisting when one is not perceiving it; the
+future (future events); the past; space (or better, the distantness of objects
+from oneself); minds other than one's own; causal relationships as ordinarily
+understood; referental relationships (the relationships between names and
+their referents as ordinarily understood; what I avoided discussing in the
+second chapter); unperceivable "things" (microscopic objects (of course,
+viewing them through microscopes does not count as perceiving them),
+essences, Being); in short, most of the things one is normally concerned with,
+normally thinks about, as well as the objects of uncommon knowledge. (To
+simplify the explanation of the concept, make it easier on the reader, I am
+speaking as if I believed that there are non-experiences, that is, introducing
+the concept in the context of the beliefs usually associated with it.)
+Non-experiences are precisely what one has beliefs about. One believes that
+there are microscopic living organisms, or that there are none (or that one
+can not know whether there are any---this is not a non-belief but a complex
+belief about the relation of the realm where non-experiences could be to the
+mind). Incidentally, that other minds, for example, are non-experiences is
+presumably a connotation of 'other minds' for the reader, as explained in the
+second chapter.
+
+In the history of philosophy, the concept of non-experience comes first.
+Then philosophers begin to develop theories of how one knows about
+non-experiences (epistemological theories). The concept of a perception, or
+experience of something, is introduced into philosophy. The theory is that
+one knows about non-experiences by perceiving, having experiences of, some
+of them. For example, one knows that there is a table before one's eyes
+(assuming that there is) by having a visual perception or experience of it, by
+having a "visual-table-experience". The theory goes on to say that these
+perceptions are in the mind. Then, if one has a visual-table-experience in
+one's mind when there is no table, one is hallucinated. And so forth. Now
+there are two sources of confusion in all this for the naive reader. First,
+saying that perceptions of objects are in one's mind is not saying that they
+are, for example, visualizations, imaginings, such as one's visualization of a
+table with one's eyes closed. Perceptions of objects do not seem "mental".
+The theory that they are in the mind is a belief. This point leads directly to
+the second source of confusion. Does the English word 'table', as ordinarily
+used to refer to a table when one is looking at it, refer to the table, an entity
+external to one's perceptions which persists when not perceived, or to one's
+perception of it, to the visual-table-experience? If distinguishing between
+the two, and the notion that the table-experience is in his mind, seem silly to
+the reader, then he probably uses 'table', 'perceived table', and
+'table-experience' as equivalent some of the time. The distinction, however,
+is not just silly; anyone who believes that there are tables when he is not
+perceiving them must accept it to be consistent. At any rate there is this
+confusion, that it is not always clear whether English object-names are being
+used to refer to perceived non-experiences or to experiences, the
+perceptions.
+
+Now let us ignore for a moment the connotations that experiences are
+experiences, perceptions, of non-experiences, and are in the mind. The term
+'experience' is important here because with it philosophers finally made a
+start at inventing a term for the things one knows directly, unquestionabiy
+knows, or, better, which one just has, or are just there (whether they are
+experiences, perceptions, of non-experiences or not). A traditional
+philosopher would say that if one is having a table-experience, one may not
+know whether it's a true perception of a table, whether there's an objective
+table there; or whether it's an hallucination; but one unquestionably knows,
+has, the table-experience. And of course, with respect to one's experiences
+not supposed to be perceptions of anything, such as visualizations, one
+unquestionably knows, has them too. A better way of putting it is that there
+is no question as to whether one has one's experiences or what they are like.
+One doesn't believe (that one has) one's experiences; to try to do so would
+be rather like trying to polish air. In fact, "thinking" that one doesn't have
+one's experiences, if this is possible, is a belief, a wrong one (as will be
+shown, although it should already be obvious if the reader has the slightest
+idea of what I am talking about), and in fact a perfectly insane one. Now the
+reader must not think that because I say experiences are unquestionably
+known I am talking about tautologies, or about beliefs which some
+philosophers say can be known by intuition even though unprovable, or say
+cannot really be doubted without losing one's sanity (for example, some
+philosophers say this about the belief that other persons have minds). In
+speaking of experiences I am not trying to trick the reader into accepting a
+lot of beliefs I am not prepared to justify, as many philosophers do by
+appealing to intuition or sanity or what not, a reprehensible hyprocrisy
+which shows that they are not the least interested in philosophy proper. One
+does not have other-persons'-having-minds-experiences (nor are the objective
+tables one supposedly perceives table-experiences); one believes that other
+persons have minds (or that there is an objective table corresponding to one's
+table-experience), and this belief could very well be wrong (in fact, it is, as
+will be shown).
+
+I have explained the current use of the term 'experience'. Now I want
+to propose a new use for the term, which, except where otherwise noted,
+will be that of the rest of this book. (Thus whereas in discussing
+'non-experience' I was merely explaining and accepting the current use of
+the term, in the case of 'experience' I am going to suggest a new use for the
+term.) As I explained, the concept of non-experience preceded that of
+experience, and the latter was developed to explain how one knows the
+former. What I am interested in, however, is not 'experience' as it implies.
+'perceptions, of non-experiences, and in the mind', but as it refers to that
+which one unquestionably knows, is immediate, is just there, is not
+something one believes exists. I am going to use 'experience' to refer, as it
+already does, to that immediate "world", but without the implication that
+experience is perception of non-experience, and in the mind: the same
+referents but without the old connotations. In other words, in my use
+'experience' is completely neutral with respect to relationships to
+non-experiences, is not an antonym for 'non-experience' as conventionally
+used, does not presuppose a metaphysic. The reader is being asked to take a
+leap of understanding here, because there is all the difference in philosophy
+between 'experience' as implying, connoting, relatedness to non-experiences
+or in particular the realm where they could be, and 'experience' without
+these connotations.
+
+Viewing this discussion of terminology in retrospect, it should be
+obvious that although my term 'experience' was introduced last, it is
+intrinsically, logically, the simplest, most immediate, most inevitable of the
+terms, and should be the easiest to understand. In contrast, the notions I
+discussed in reaching it may seem a little arbitrary. As a matter of fact, I
+have used the perspective of the Western philsophical tradition to explain my
+term, but this doesn't mean that it is relevant only to that tradition or,
+especially, the theory of knowing about non-experiences. Even if the reader's
+conceptual background does not involve the concept of non-experience, and
+especially the modern Western theory of knowing about non-experiences, he
+ought to be able to understand, and realize the "orimacy" of, my term
+'experience'. The term should be supra-cultural.
+
+I have gone to some length to explain my use of the term 'experience'.
+As I have said, it is "intrinsically" the simplest term, but I can not define it
+by just equating it to some English expression because all English, including
+the traditional term 'experience', the antonym of 'non-experience', is based
+on metaphysical assumptions, does have implications about non-experience,
+in short, is formulations of beliefs. These implications are different for
+different philosophers according as their metaphysics (or, as is sometimes
+(incorrectly) said, "ontologies") differ. Even such a sentence as "The table is
+black" implies the formulation \formulation{Material objects are real} (to the materialist),
+or \formulation{So-called objects are ideas in the mind} (to the idealist), or \formulation{Substances
+and attributes are real}, and so forth, traditionally. As a result, in order to
+explain the new term I have had to use English in a very special way,
+ultimately turning it against itself, so as to enable the reader to guess how I
+use the term. That is, although there is nothing problematic about my use of
+\term{experience}, about its referents, there is about my English, for example
+when I say that the connotation of relatedness to non-experience is to be
+dropped from \term{experience}. There can be this new term, the philosopher is
+not irrevocably tied to English or other natural language and its implied
+philosophy, as some philosophers claim; because a term is able to be a name,
+to be used to make assertions, not by being a part of conventional English or
+other natural language, but by having referents.
+
+As I suggested at the beginning of this chapter, I need to introduce my
+\term{experience} because without it I cannot question all beliefs, everything
+about non-experiences, since in English there is always the implication that
+there could be non-experiences. The term is a radical innovation; one of the
+most important in this book. The fact that although it is the "simplest" and
+least questionable term, it is a radical innovation and is difficult to explain
+using English, shows how philosophically inadequate English and the
+philosophies it implies are. Now if the reader has not understood my
+\term{experience} he is likely to precisely mis-understand the rest of the book as
+an attempt to show that there are no non-experiences. (It's good that this
+isn't what I'm trying to show, because it is self-contradictory: for there to be
+no non-experiences there would have to be a realm empty of them, and this
+realm would have to be a non-experience.) If he is lucky he will just find the
+book incomprehensible, or possibly even come to understand the term from
+the rest of what I say, using it. But if he does understand the term, then he is
+past the greatest difficulty in understanding the book; in fact, he may
+already realize what I'm going to say.
+
+\subsection*{Chapter 4 : The Linguistic Solution}
+
+Now that I have explained the key terminology for this part of the
+book, I can give the solution to properly philosophical problems, the
+problems of which beliefs are right, in the form of conclusions about the
+language in which the beliefs are formulated. My concern here is to present
+the solution as soon as possible, so as to make it clear to the reader that my
+work contains important results, is an important contribution to philosophy,
+and not just admirable sentiments or the formulation of an attitude or a
+philosophically neutral analysis of concepts or the like. For this reason I will
+not be too concerned to make the solution seem natural, or intuitive, or to
+explore all its implications; that will come later.
+
+However, in the hope that it will make the main "argument" of this
+chapter easier to understand, I will precede it with a short, non-rigorous
+version of it, which should give the "intuitive insight" behind the main
+argument. Consider the question of whether one can know if a given belief is
+true. Now a given belief is cognitively arbitrary in that it cannot be justified
+from the standpoint of having no beliefs, cannot be justified without
+appealing to other beliefs. Thus the answer must be skepticism: one cannot
+know if a given belief is true. However, this skepticism is a belief---a
+contradiction. The ultimate conclusion is that to escape inconsistency, to be
+right, one must, at the linguistic level, reject all talk of beliefs, of knowing if
+they are true, reject all formulations of beliefs. The "necessity", but
+inconsistency, of skepticism "shows" my conclusion in an intuitively
+understandable way.
+
+To get on to the definitive version of my "argument". I will say that
+one name "depends" on another if and only if it has the logical relation to
+that other that \name{black table} has to \name{table}: a referent of the former is
+necessarily a referent of the latter (one of the relations between names
+mentioned in the second chapter). Now the associated name of any
+statement, or formulation, of a belief of necessity depends on
+'non-experience', since non-experiences are what beliefs are about. For
+example, \name{Other persons having minds}, the associated name of the
+formulation \formulation{Other persons have minds}, certainly depends on
+\term{non-experience}. Thus, anything true of \term{non-experience} will be true of the
+associated name of any formulation of a belief.
+
+In the last chapter I introduced, explained the concepts of
+non-experience and experience (in the traditional sense, as the antonym of
+\term{non-experience}), showed the connotations of the expressions
+\term{non-experience} and \term{experience} (traditional). What I did not go on to
+show, left for this chapter, is that if one continues to analyze these concepts,
+one comes on crucial implications which result in contradictions. What
+follows is perhaps the most concentrated passage in this book, so that the
+reader must be willing to read it slowly and thoughtfully. Consider one's
+experience (used in my, "neutral", sense unless I say otherwise). Could there
+be something in one's experience, a part of one's experience, which was
+awareness of whether it's experience (traditional), of whether it's related to
+non-experience, of whether there is non-experience, awareness of
+non-experience? No, as should be obvious from the connotations shown in
+the last chapter. (Compare this with the point that one cannot (cognitively)
+justify a belief from the standpoint of having no beliefs, cannot justify it
+without appealing to other beliefs). If there could be, if such awareness were
+just an experience, the distinctness of experience from experience
+(traditional) and so forth would disappear. The concepts of experience
+(traditional) and so forth would be superfluous, in fact, one couldn't have
+them: experience (traditional) and so forth would just be absorbed into
+experience. One concludes that there cannot be anything in one's experience
+which is awareness of whether it's experience (traditional), of whether there
+is non-experience. But then this awareness, which is in part about experience
+(traditional) and non-experience and thus involves awareness of them, is in
+one's experience---a contradiction. In fact, the same holds for the awareness
+which is "understanding the concepts" of non-experience and the rest as
+they are supposed to be understood. And for "understanding"
+\term{non-experience} (and the rest) as it is supposed to be, being aware of its
+referents (and non-referents); since to name non-experience, it must be an
+experience (traditional). And even for being aware of the referents (and
+non-referents) of "non-experience", which to name an experience
+(traditional) must be one. One mustn't assume that one understands
+'non-experience' --- and "non-experience" --- and \triquote{non-experience}; but here
+one is, using "non-experience" and \triquote{non-experience} to say so (which
+certainly implies that one assumes one understands them). It is impossible
+for there to be non-experiences. When one begins to examine closely the
+concept of non-experience, it collapses.
+
+(A final point for the expert. This
+tangle of contradictions is intrinsic in the concept of non-experience; it does
+not result because I have introduced a violation of the law that names cannot
+name themselves. This should be absolutely clear from the two sentences
+about names, which show contradictions --- that one must not assume that
+one understands certain expressions, but that one uses the expressions to say
+so (does assume it) --- with explicit stratification.)
+
+My exposition has broken down in a tangle of contradictions. Now
+what is important is that it has done so precisely because I have talked about
+experience (traditional), non-experience, and the rest, because I have spoken
+as if there could be non-experiences, because I have used 'experience'
+(traditional), 'non-experience', and the rest. Thus, even though what I have
+said is a tangle of contradictions, it is not by any means valueless. Since it is
+a tangle of contradictions precisely because it involves 'experience'
+(traditional), 'non-experience', and the rest, it shows that one who "accepts"
+the expressions, supposes that they are valid language, has inconsistent
+desires with respect to how they are to be used. The expressions can have no
+explications at all acceptable to him. He cannot consistently use the
+expressions (the way they're supposed to be). The expressions, and,
+remembering the paragraph before last, any formulation of a belief, are
+completely discredited. (What is not discredited is language referring to
+experiences (my use). If it happens that an expression I have said is a
+formulation of a belief does have a good explication for the reader, then it is
+not a formulation of a belief for him but refers to experiences.) Now there is
+an important point about method which should be brought out. If all
+"non-experiential language", "belief language", is inconsistent, how can I
+show this and yet avoid falling into contradiction when I say it? The answer
+is that I don't have to avoid falling into contradiction; that I fall into
+contradiction precisely because I use formulations of beliefs shows what I
+want to show. This, then, is the linguistic solution; as I said we would, we
+have been driven far beyond any such conclusion as 'all formulations of
+beliefs are false'.
+
+Now what do these conclusions about formulations of beliefs, about
+belief language, say about beliefs themselves, about whether a given belief is
+right? Well, to the extent that a belief is tied up with its formulation, since
+the formulation is discredited, the belief is, must be wrong. After all, if a
+belief were right, its formulation would necessarily have an acceptable
+explication which was true; in short, the belief would have a true
+formulation (to see this, note that the contrary assertion is itself a
+formulation of a belief---leading to a contradiction). Incidentally, this point
+answers those who would say, that the inconsistency of their statements of
+belief taken literally does not discredit their beliefs, as the statements are not
+to be taken literally, are metaphorical or symbolic truths. To continue, one
+who because of having a belief took its formulation seriously, expected that
+it could have an acceptable explication for him, could not turn out to be an
+expression he could not properly use, must be deceiving himself in some
+way. Now there is another important point about "method" to be made.
+The question will probably continually recur to the critical reader how one
+can "know", be aware that any given belief is wrong, without having beliefs.
+The answer is that one way one can be aware of it is simply to be aware of
+the inconsistency of belief language, which awareness is not a belief.
+(Whether belief language is inconsistent is not a matter of belief but of the
+way one wants expressions used; being aware of the inconsistency is like
+being aware with respect to a table, "that in my language, this is to be said to
+be a "table"".) Incidentally, to wrap things up, the common belief as to how
+a name has referents is that there is a relation between the name and its
+referents which is an objective, metaphysical entity, a non-experience; this
+belief is wrong. How, in what sense a name can have referents will not be
+discussed here.
+
+The unsophisticated reader may react to all of this with a lot of 'Yes,
+but...' thoughts. If he doesn't more or less identify beliefs with their
+formulations, and doesn't have an intuitive appreciation of the force of
+linguistic arguments, he my tend to regard my result as a mere (if
+embarrassing) curiosity. (Of course, it isn't, but I am concerned with how
+well the reader understands that.) And there does remain a lot to be said
+about beliefs themselves (as mental acts), and where the self-deception is in
+them; it is not even clear yet just what the relation of a belief to its
+formulation is. Then the reader might ask whether there aren't beliefs whose
+rejection as wrong would conflict with experience, or which it would be
+impossible or dangerous not to have. I now turn to the discussion of these
+matters.
+
+
+\clearpage
+
+
+2/22/1963
+
+
+Tony Conrad and Henry Flynt demonstrate
+against Lincoln Center, February 22,
+
+
+1963
+(photo by Jack Smith)
+
+\clearpage
+
+
+\section{Completion of the Treatment of Properly Philosophical Problems}
+
+
+\subsection*{Chapter 5 : Beliefs as Mental Acts}
+
+
+In this chapter I will solve the problems of philosophy proper by
+discussing believing itself, as a ("conscious") mental act. Although I will be
+talking about mental acts and experience, it must be clear that this part of
+the book, like the fast part, is not epistemology or phenomenology. I will
+not try to talk about "perception" or the like, in a mere attempt to justify
+"common-sense" beliefs or what not. Of course, both parts are incidentally
+relevant to epistemology and phenomenology, since in discussing beliefs I
+discuss the beliefs which constitute those subjects.
+
+I should say immediately that 'belief', in its traditional use as supposed
+to refer to "mental acts, often unconscious, connected with the realm of
+non-experience", has no explication at all satisfactory, has been discredited.
+This point is important, as it means that one does not want to say that one
+does or does not "have beliefs", in the sense important to those having
+beliefs, that beliefs (in my sense) will not do as referents for "belief" in the
+use important to those having beliefs; helping to fill out the conclusion of
+the last part. Now when I speak of a "belief" I will be speaking of an
+experience, what might be said to be "an act of consciously believing, of
+consciously having a belief", of what is "in one's head" when one says that
+one "believes a certain thing". Further, I will, for convenience in
+distinguishing beliefs, speak of belief "that others have minds", for example,
+or in general of belief "that there are non-experiences" (with quotation
+marks), but I must not be taken as implying that beliefs manage to be
+"about non-experiences". (Thus, what I say about beliefs will be entirely
+about experiences; I will not be trying to talk "about the realm of
+non-experience, or the relation of beliefs to it".) I expect that it is already
+fairly clear to the reader what his acts of consciously believing are (if he has
+any); I will be more concerned with pointing out to him some features of his
+"beliefs" (believing) than with the explication of 'act of consciously
+believing', although I will need to make a few comments about that too.
+What I am trying to do is to get the reader to accept a useful, possibly new,
+use of a word ('belief') salvaged from the unexplicatible use of the word,
+rather than rejecting the word altogether.
+
+There is a further point about terminology. The reader should
+remember from the third chapter that quite apart from the theory "that
+perceptions are in the mind", one can make a distinction between mental
+and non-mental experiences, between, for example, visualizing a table with
+one's eyes closed, and a "seen" table, a visual-table-experience. Now I am
+going to say that visualizations and the like are "imagined-experiences". For
+example, a visualization of a table will be said to be an
+"imagined-visual-table-experience". The reader should not suppose that by
+"imagined" I mean that the experiences are "hallucinations", are "unreal". I
+use "imagined" because saying 'mental-table-experience" is too much like
+saying "table in the mind" and because just using 'visualization' leaves no way
+of speaking of mental experiences which are not visualizations. Speaking of
+an "imagined-table-experience" seems to be the best way of saying that it is
+a mental experience, and then distinguishing it from other mental
+experiences by the conventional method of saying that it is an imagining "of
+a (non-mental) table-experience" (better thought of as meaning an imagining
+like a (non-mental) table-experience). In other words, an
+imagined-x-experience (to generalize) is a "valid" experience, all right, but it
+is not a non-mental x-experience; it is a mental experience which is like a
+(non-mental) x-experience in a certain way. Incidentally, an "imagined-imagined-experience" is impossible by definition; or is no different from an
+imagined-experience, whichever way you want to look at it. If this
+terminology is a little confusing, it is not my fault but that of the
+conventional method of distinguishing different mental experiences by
+saying that they are imaginings "of one or another non-mental experiences".
+
+I can at last ask what one does when one believes "that there is a table,
+not perceived by oneself, behind one now", or anything else. Well, in the
+first place, one takes note of, gives one's attention to, an
+imagined-experience, such as an imagined-table-experience or a visualization
+of oneself with one's back to a table; or to a linguistic expression, a supposed
+statement, such as \lexpression{There is a table behind me}. This is not all one does,
+however; if it were, what one does would not in the least deserve to be said
+to be a "belief" (a point about the explication of my 'belief'). The
+additional, "essential" component of a belief is a self-deceiving "attitude"
+toward the experience. What this attitude is will be described below. Observe
+that one does not want to say that the additional component is a belief
+about the experience because of the logical absurdity of doing so, or, in
+other words, because it suggests that there is an infinite regress of mental
+action. Now the claim that the attitude is "self-deceiving" is not, could not
+be, at all like the claim "that a belief as a whole, or its formulation, fails to
+correspond in a certain way to non-experience, to reality, or is false". The
+question of "what is going on in the realm of non-experience" does not arise
+here. Rather, my claim is entirely about an experience; it is that the attitude,
+the experience not itself a belief but part of the experience of believing, is
+"consciously, deliberately" self-deceiving, is a "self-deception experience". I
+don't have to "prove that the attitude is self-deceiving by reference to what
+is going on in the realm of non-experience"; when I have described the
+attitude and the reader is aware of it, he will presumably find it a good
+explication, unhesitatingly want, to say that it is "self-deceiving".
+
+I will now say, as well as can be, what the attitude is. In believing, one
+is attentive primarily to the imagined-experience or linguistic expression as
+mentioned above. The attitude is "peripheral", is a matter of the way one is
+atttentive. Saying that the attitude is "conscious, deliberate", is a little
+strong if it seems to imply that it is cynical self-brainwashing; what I am
+trying to say is that it is not an "objective" or "subconscious" self-deception
+such as traditional philosophers speak of, one impossible to be aware of. This
+is about as much as I can say about the attitude directly, because of the
+inadequacy of the English descriptive vocabulary for mental experiences;
+with respect to English the attitude is a "vague, elusive" thing, very difficult
+to describe. I will be able to say more about what it is only by suggestion, by
+saying that it is the attitude "that such and such" (the reader must not think
+I mean the belief "that such and such"). If the experience to which the
+attention is primarily given in believing is an imagined-x-experience, then the
+self-deceiving attitude is the attitude "that the imagined-x-experience is a
+(non-mental) x-experience". As an example, consider the belief "that there is
+a table behind one". If one's attention in believing is not on a linguistic
+expression, it will be on an imagined-experience such as an
+imagined-table-experience or a visualization of a person representing oneself
+(to be accurate) with his back to a table, and one will have the self-deceiving
+attitude "that the imagined-experience is a table or oneself with one's back
+to a table". Of course, if one is asked whether one's imagined-x-experience is
+a (non-mental) x-experience, one will say that it is not, that it is admittedly
+an imagined-experience but "corresponds to a non-experience". This is not
+inconsistent with what I have said: first, I don't say that one believes "that
+one's imagined-x-experience is an x-experience"; secondly, when one is asked
+the question, one stops believing "that there is a table behind one" and starts
+believing "that one's imagined-experience corresponds in a certain way to a
+non-experience", a different matter (different belief).
+
+lf one's attention in believing is primarily on a linguistic expression
+(which if a sentence, will be pretty much regarded as its associated name),
+the self-deceiving attitude is the attitude "that the expression has a
+referent". With respect to the belief "that there is a table behind one", one's
+attention in believing would be primarily on the expression \expression{There is a table
+behind me}, pretty much regarded as 'There being a table behind me', and
+one would have the self-deceiving attitude "that this name has a referent".
+Unexplicatible expressions, then, function as principal components of
+beliefs.
+
+\inlineaside{This paragraph is complicated and inessential; if it begins to confuse
+the reader it can be skipped.} I will now describe the relation between the
+version, of a belief, involving language and the version not involving
+language. In the version not involving language, the attention is on an
+imagined-x-experience which is "regarded" as an x-experience, whereas in
+the version involving language, the attention is on something which is
+"regarded" as having as referent "something" (the attitude is vague here).
+For the latter version, the idea is "that the reality is at one remove", and
+correspondingly, one whose "language" consists of formulations of beliefs
+doesn't desire to have as experiences, or perceive, or even be able to imagine,
+referents of expressions---which, for the more critical person, may make
+believing easier. Thus, just as one takes note of the imagined-x-experience in
+the version of the belief not involving language, has something which
+functions as the thing the belief is about, so in the version involving language
+one has the attitude that the expression has a referent. Further, just as one
+has the attitude that the imagined-x-experience is an x-experience in the
+version not involving language, does not recognize that what functions as the
+thing believed in is a mere imagined-experience, so in the version involving
+"language" one takes note of an 'expression' not having a referent, since a
+referent could only be a (mere) experience. One who expects an expression,
+which is the principal component of a belief, to have a good explication does
+so on the basis of the self-deceiving attitude one has towards it in having the
+belief. In trying to explicate the expression, one finds inconsistent desires
+with respect to what its referents must be. These desires correspond to the
+way the expression functions in the belief: the desire that it be possible for
+awareness of the referent to be part of one's experience corresponds to the
+attitude, in believing, that the expression has a referent; and the desire that it
+not be possible for awareness of the referent to be (merely) part of one's
+experience corresponds to the expression's not having a referent in believing.
+Pointing out that the expression is unexplicable discredits the belief of which
+it is the principal component, just as pointing out that a belief not involving
+language consists of being attentive to an imagined-experience and having the
+attitude that it is not an imagined-experience, discredits that belief.
+
+Such, then, is what one does when one believes. If the reader is rather
+unconvinced by my description, especially because of my speaking of
+"attitudes", then let him consider the following summary: there must be
+something more to a mental act than just taking note of an experience for it
+to be a "belief"; this something is "peripheral and elusive", so that I am
+calling the something an "attitude", the most appropriate way in English to
+speak of it; the attitude, an experience not itself a belief but part of the
+experience which is the belief, is thus isolated; the attitude is
+"self-deceiving", is a "(conscious) self-deception experience", because when
+aware of it the reader will presumably want to say that it is. The attitude just
+about has to be a ("conscious") self-deception experience to transform mere
+taking note of an experience into something remotely deserving to be said to
+be a "belief". The decision as to whether the attitude is to be said to be
+"self-deceiving" is to be made without trying to think "about the relation of
+the belief as a whole to the realm of non-experience", to do which would be
+to slip into having beliefs, other than the one under consideration, which
+would be irrelevant to our concern here. Ultimately, the important thing is
+to observe what one does in believing, and particularly the attitude, more
+than to say that the attitude is "self-deceiving".
+
+In order for my description of believing to be complete, I must mention
+some things often associated with believing but not "essential" to it. First,
+one may take note of non-mental and imagined-experiences other than the
+one to which attention is primarily given. If one has a table-experience and
+believes "that it is a table-perception corresponding to an objectively existing
+table', one may give much of his attention to the table-experience in so
+believing, associate the table-experience strongly with the belief. One may in
+believing give attention to non-mental experiences supposed to be 'evidence
+for, confirmation of, one's belief" (more will be said about confirmation
+shortly). If one's attention in believing is primarily on the linguistic
+expression 'x', one may give attention to a referent of
+'imagined-x(-experience)', an "imagined-referent" of 'x'; or to
+imagined-y-experiences such that y-experiences are supposed, said, to be
+"analogous to the referent of 'x'". In the latter case the y-experiences will be
+mutually exclusive, and less importance will be given to them than would be
+to imagined-referents. An example of imagined-referents in believing is
+visualizing oneself with one's back to a table, as the imagined-referent of
+'There being a table behind one'. An example of imagined-y-experiences
+(such that y-experiences are mutually exclusive) which are said to be
+"analogous to referents", in believing, is the visualizations associated with
+beliefs "about entities wholly other than, transcending, experience, such as
+Being".
+
+Secondly, there are associated with beliefs logical "justifications",
+"arguments", for them, "defenses" of them. I will not bother to explicate
+the different kinds of justifications because it is so easy to say what is wrong
+with all of them. There are two points to be made. First, explication would
+show that the matter of justifications for beliefs is just a matter of language
+and beliefs of the kind already discussed. Secondly, as I have suggested
+before, whether a statement or belief is right is not dependent on what the
+justifications, arguments for it are. (If this seems to fail for inductive
+justification, the kind invoiving the citing of experience supposed to be
+evidence for, confirmation of, the belief, it is because the metaphysical
+assumptions on which induction is based are rarely stated. Without them
+inductive justifications are just non sequiturs. An example: this table has
+four legs; therefore ("it is more probable that") any other table has four
+legs.) Justification of a statement or belief does nothing but conjoin to it
+superfluous statements or beliefs, if anything. The claim that a justification,
+argument can show that a belief is not arbitrary, gratuitous, in that it can
+show that to be consistent, one must have the belief if one has a Sesser,
+weaker belief, is simply self-contradictory. If a justification induces one to
+believe what one apparently did not believe before hearing the justification,
+then one already had the belief "implicitly" (it was a conjunct of a belief
+one already had), or one has accepted superfluous beliefs conjoined with it.
+
+I will conclude this chapter first with a list of philosophical positions
+my position is not. Although I have already suggested some of this material,
+I repeat it because it is so important that the reader not misconstrue my
+position as some position which is no more like mine than its negation is,
+and which I show to be wrong. My position is not disbelief. (Incidentally, it
+is ironic that 'disbeliever', without qualification, has been used by believers
+as a term of abuse, since, as disbelief is belief which is the negation of some
+belief, any belief is disbelief.) In particular, I am not concerned to deny "the
+existence of non-experience", to "cause non-experiences to vanish", so to
+speak, to change or cause to vanish some of the reader's non-mental
+experiences, "perceived objects". My position is not skepticism of any kind,
+is not, for example, the belief "that there is a realm where there could either
+be or not be certain entities not experiences, but our means of knowing are
+inadequate for finding which is the case." My position is not a mere
+"decision to ignore non-experiences, or beliefs". The philosopher who denies
+"the existence of non-experiences", or denies any belief, or who is skeptical
+of any belief, or who merely "decides to ignore non-experiences, or beliefs",
+has some of the very beliefs I am concerned to discredit.
+
+What I have been concerned to do is to discredit formulations of
+beliefs, and beliefs as mental acts, by pointing out some features of them. In
+the first part of the book I showed the inconsistency of linguistic expressions
+dependent on 'non-experience', and pointed out that those who expect them
+to have explications at all acceptable are deceiving themselves; discrediting
+the beliefs of which the expressions are formulations. In this chapter, I have
+described the mental act of believing, calling the reader's attention to the
+self-deception experience involved in it, and thus showing that it is wrong.
+To conclude, in discrediting beliefs I have shown what the right
+philosophical position is: it is not having beliefs (and realizing, for any belief
+one happens to think of, that it is wrong (which doesn't involve having beliefs)).
+
+\subsection*{Chapter 6 : Discussion of Some Basic Beliefs}
+
+In the preceding chapters I have been concerned, in discrediting any
+given belief, to show what the right philosophical position is. In this chapter
+I will turn to particular beliefs, supposed knowledge, to make it clear just
+what, specifically, have been discredited. Now if the reader will consider the
+entire "history of world thought", the fantastic proliferation of activities at
+least partly "systems of knowledge" which constitute it, Platonism,
+psychoanalysis, Tibetian mysticism, physics, Bantu witchcraft,
+phenomenology, mathematical logic, Konko Kyo, Marxism, alchemy,
+comparative linguistics, Orgonomy, Thomism, and so on indefinitely, each
+with its own kind of conclusions, method of justifying them, applications,
+associated valuations, and the like, he will quickly realize that I could not
+hope to analyze even a fraction of them to show just how "non-experiential
+language", and beliefs, are involved in them. And I should say that it is not
+always obvious whether the concepts of non-experiential language, and
+belief, are relevant to them. Zen is an obvious example (although as a matter
+of fact is unquestionably does involve beliefs, is not for example an
+anticipation of my position). Further, many quasi-systems-of-knowledge are
+difficult to discuss because the expositions of them which are what one has
+to work with, are badly written, in particular, fail to state the insights behind
+what is presented, the real reasons why it can be taken seriously, and are
+incomplete and confused.
+
+What I will do, then, to specifically illustrate my results, is to discuss a
+few particular beliefs which are found in almost all systems of "knowledge";
+have been given especial attention in modern Western philosophy and are
+thus especially relevant to the immediate audience for this book; and are so
+"basic" (accounting for their ubiquity) that they are either just assumed, as
+too trivially factual to be worthy the attention of a profound thinker, or if
+they are explicit are said to be so basic that persons cannot do without them.
+The discussion will make it specifically clear that it is not necessary to have
+these beliefs, that not having them is not "inconsistent" with one's
+experience; and is thus important for the reader who is astonished at the idea
+of rejecting any given belief, the idea of any given belief's being wrong and
+of not having it.
+
+Consider beliefs to the effect "that the world is ordered", beliefs
+formulated in "natural laws", beliefs "about substance", and the like.
+Rejection of them may seem to lead to a problem. After all, one's "perceived
+world" is not "chaotic", is it? The reader should observe that in rejecting
+beliefs "that the world is ordered" I do not say that his "perceived world" is
+("subjectively") chaotic (that is, extremely unfamiliar, strange). The
+non-strange character of one's "perceived world" is associated with beliefs
+"about substance" and beliefs formulated in natural laws, but it is not "the
+world being ordered"; and taking note of the non-strange character of one's
+"perceived world" is not part of what is "essential" in these beliefs.
+
+Rejection of "spatio-temporal" beliefs may seem to lead to a problem.
+After all, cannot one watch oneself wave one's hand towards and away from
+oneself? Of course one can "watch oneself wave one's hand" (in a non-strict
+sense---and if the reader uses the expression in this sense it will not be a
+formulation of a belief for him). However, that one can "watch oneself wave
+one's hand" (in the non-strict sense) does not imply "that there are spatially
+distant, and past and future events"; and although experiences such as a
+visual---"moving"---hand experience are associated with spatio-temporal
+beliefs, taking note of them is not part of what is essential in those beliefs.
+
+Rejection of beliefs "about the objectivity of linguistic referring" may
+seem to lead to a problem. After all, when one says that a table is a "table",
+doesn't one do so unhesitatingly, with a feeling of satisfaction, a feeling that
+things are less mysterious, strange, when one has done so, and without the
+slightest intention of saying that it is a "non-table"? The reader should
+observe that I do not deny this. These experiences are associated with beliefs
+"about the objectivity of referring", but they are not "objective referring";
+and taking note of them is not part of what is essential in those beliefs.
+
+Rejection of the belief "that other humans (better, things) than oneself
+have minds" my seem to lead to a problem. After all, "perceived other
+humans" talk and so forth, do they not? The reader should observe that in
+rejecting the belief "that others have minds" I do not deny that "perceived
+other humans" talk and so forth. Other humans' talking and so forth is
+associated with the belief "that others have minds", but it is not "other
+humans having minds"; and taking note of others talking and so forth is not
+part of what is essential in believing "that others have minds", points I
+anticipated in the second chapter.
+
+Finally, many philosophers will violently object to rejection of
+temporal beliefs of a certain kind, namely beliefs of the form "If \x, then \y\
+will follow in the future", especially if \y\ is something one wants, and \x\ is
+something one can do. (After all, doesn't it happen that one throws the
+switch, and the light goes on?) They object so strongly because they fear
+"that one cannot live unless one has and uses such knowledge". They say,
+for example, "that one had better know that one must drink water to live,
+and drink water, or one won't live". Now "one's throwing the switch and the
+light's coming on" (in a non-strict sense) is like the experiences associated
+with other temporal beliefs; that one can do it (in the non-strict sense) does
+not imply "that there are past or future events", and taking note of it is not
+part of what is essential in the belief "that if one throws the switch, then the
+light will come on". As for what the philosophers say, fear, believe "about
+the necessity of such knowledge for survival", it is just more beliefs of the
+same kind, so that rejection of it is similarly unproblematic. If this abrupt
+dismissal of the fears as wrong is terrifying to the reader, then it just shows
+how badly he is in need of being straightened out philosophically.
+Incidentally, all this should make it clear that it is futile to try to "save"
+beliefs (render them justifiable) by construing them as predictions.
+
+By now the reader has probably observed that the beliefs, and their
+formulations, which I have been discussing, the ones he is presumably most
+suspicious of rejecting, are all strongly (but not essentially) associated with
+non-mental experiences of his. The reader may no longer seriously have the
+beliefs, but have problems in connection with them, get involved in
+defending them, and be suspicious of rejecting them, merely because he
+continues to use the formulations of the beliefs, but to refer to the
+experiences associated with them (as there's no other way in English to do
+so), and confusedly supposes that to reject the beliefs and formulations is to
+deny that he has the experiences. Now I am not denying that he has the
+experiences. As I said in the last chapter, I am not trying to convince the
+reader that he doesn't have experiences he has, but to point out to him the
+self-deception experiences involved in his beliefs. The reader should be wary
+of thinking, however, on reading this, that maybe he doesn't have any beliefs
+after all, just uses the belief language he does to refer to experiences. It
+sometimes happens that people who have beliefs and as a result use belief
+language excuse themselves on the basis that they are just using the language
+to refer to experiences, an hypocrisy. If one uses belief formulations, it's
+usually because one has beliefs.
+
+The point that the language which one may use to describe experiences
+is formulations of beliefs, is true generally. As I said in the third chapter, all
+English sentences are, traditionally anyway, formulations of beliefs. As a
+result, those who want to talk about experiences (my use) and still use
+English are forced to use formulations of beliefs to refer to strongly
+associated experiences, and this seems to be happening more and more; often
+among quasi-empiricists who naively suppose that the formulations have
+always been used that way, except by a few "metaphysicians". I have had to
+so use belief language throughout this book, the most notable example being
+the introduction of my use of "experience" in the third chapter. Thus, some
+of what I say may imply belief formulations for the reader when it doesn't
+for me, and be philosophically problematic for him; he must understand the
+book to some extent in spite of the language, as I suggested in the third
+chapter. I have tried to make this relatively easy by choosing, to refer to
+experiences, language with which they are very strongly associated and
+which is only weakly associated with beliefs, and, the important thing, by
+announcing when the language is used for that purpose.
+
+It is time, though, that I admit, so as not to be guilty of the hypocricy I
+was exposing earlier, that most of the sentences in this book will be
+understood as formulations of beliefs, that, in other words, I have presented
+my philosophy to the reader by getting him to have a series of beliefs. This
+does not invalidate my position, because the beliefs are not part of it. They
+are for the heuristic purpose of getting the reader to appreciate my position,
+which is not having beliefs (and realizing, for any belief one happens to think
+of, that it is wrong (which doesn't involve believing)); and they may well not
+be held when they have accomplished that purpose. I hope I will eventually
+get around to writing a version of this book which presents my position by
+suggesting to the reader a series of imaginings (and no more), rather than
+beliefs; developing a new language to do so. The reason I stick with English
+in this book is of course (!) that readers are too "unmotivated" (lazy!) to
+learn a language of an entirely new kind to read a book, having
+unconventional conclusions, in philosophy proper.
+
+\subsection*{Chapter 7 : Summary}
+
+The most important step in understanding my work is to realize that I
+am trying neither to get one to adopt a system of beliefs, nor to just ignore
+beliefs or the matter of whether they are right. Once the reader does so, he
+will find that my position is quite simple. The reader has probably tended to
+construe the body of the book, the second through the sixth chapters, as a
+formulation of a system of beliefs; or as a proposal that he ignore beliefs or
+the matter of whether they are right. Even if he has, a careful reading of
+them will, I hope, have prepared him for a statement of my position which is
+supposed to make it clear that the position is simple and right. This
+statement is a summary, and thus cannot be understood except in
+connection with the second through the sixth chapters. First, I reiterate that
+my position is not a system of beliefs, supported by a long, plausible
+argument. This means, incidentally, that it is absurd to "remain
+unconvinced" of the rightness of my position, or to "doubt, question" it, or
+to take a long time to decide whether it is right: one can "question" (not
+believe) disbelief, but not unbelief. (Not to mention that it is a wrong belief
+to be "skeptical" of my position in the sense of believing "that although the
+position may subjectively seem right, there is always the possibility that it is
+objectively wrong".) I am trying, not to get one to adopt new beliefs but to
+reject those one already has, not to make one more credulous but less
+credulous. If one "questions my position" then one is misconstruing it as a
+belief for which I try to give a long, plausible argument, and is trying to
+decide which is more plausible, my argument that all beliefs are false, say, or
+the arguments that beliefs are true. It may well take one a long time to
+understand my position, but if one is taking a long time to decide whether it
+is right then one is wasting one's time thinking about a position I show to be
+wrong. Secondly, my position is not a proposal that one ignore beliefs or the
+matter of whether they are right. Thus, it is absurd to conclude that my
+position is irrefutable but trivial, that one who has beliefs can also be right.
+
+Now for the statement of the position. Imagine yourself without
+beliefs. One certainly is without beliefs when one is not thinking, for
+example (although not only then). This being without beliefs is my position.
+Now this position can't be wrong inasmuch as you aren't doing anything to
+be "true or false", to be self-deceiving. Now imagine that someone asks you
+to believe something, for example, to believe "that there is a table behind
+you". Then if you are going to do what he asks, and believe (as opposed to
+continuing not to think; or only imagining---for example, "visualizing
+yourself with your back to a table"), you are going to have to have the
+attitude that you are in effect perceiving what you don't perceive, that is,
+deceive yourself. (What else could he be asking you to do?) You are going
+to have to be wrong. That's all there is to it.
+
+As for my language here, it is primarily intended to be suggestive,
+intended, at best, to suggest imaginings to you which will enable you to
+realize what the right philosophical position is (as in the last paragraph). The
+important thing is not whether the sentences in this book correspond to true
+statements in your language (although I expect the key ones will, the
+expressions in them being construed as referring to the experiences
+associated with them); it is for you to realize, observe what you do when
+you don't have beliefs and when you do. You are not so much to study my
+language as to begin to ask what one who asks you to believe wants you to
+do, anyway. The language isn't sufficiently flawless to absolutely force the
+complete realization of what the right position is on you (it doesn't have to
+be flawless to unquestionably discredit "non-experiential language"); if you
+don't want to realize where the self-deception is in believing you can just
+ignore the book, and "justify" your doing so on the basis of what I have said
+about language such as I have used. The point is that the book is not
+therefore valueless.
+
+So much for what the right philosophical position is. From having
+beliefs to not having them is not a trivial step; it is a complete
+transformation of one's cognitive orientation. Yet astonishing as the latter
+position is when first encountered, does it not become, in retrospect,
+"obvious"? What other position could be the resolution of the fantastic
+proliferation of conflicting beliefs, and of the "profound" philosophical
+problems (for example, "Could an omnipotent god do the literally
+impossible?", "Are statements about what I did in the past while alone
+capable of intersubjective verification?") arising from them? And again, one
+begins to ask, when one is asked to believe something, what it is that one is
+wanted to do, anyway; and one's reaction to the request comes to be "Why
+bother? Cognitively, what is the value of doing so? I'd just be deceiving
+myself". Also, how much simpler my position is than that of the believer.
+And although in a way the believer's position is the more natural, since one
+"naturally" tends to deceive oneself if there's any advantage in doing so
+(that is, being right tends not to be valued), in another way my position is,
+since it is simple, and since the non-believer isn't worried by the doubts
+which arise for one who tries to keep himself deceived.
+
diff --git a/essays/some_objections.tex b/essays/some_objections.tex
new file mode 100644
index 0000000..1954d9e
--- /dev/null
+++ b/essays/some_objections.tex
@@ -0,0 +1,159 @@
+\chapter{Some Objections to My Philosophy}
+
+
+\textbf{A.} The predominant attitude toward philosophical questions in
+educated circles today derives from the later Wittgenstein. Consider the
+philosopher's question of whether other people have minds. The
+Wittgensteinian attitude is that in ordinary usage, statements which imply
+that other people have minds are not problematic. Everybody knows that
+other people have minds. To doubt that other people have minds, as a
+philosopher might do, is simply to misuse ordinary language. (See
+Philosophical Investigations, \S 420.) Statements which imply that other
+people have minds works perfectly well in the context for which they were
+intended. When philosophers find these statements problematic, it is because
+they subject the statements to criticism by logical standards which are
+irrelevant and extraneous to ordinary usage. (\S \S 402, 412, 119, 116.)
+
+For Wittgenstein, the existence of God, immortal souls, other minds,
+and the Empire State Building (when I am not looking at it) are all things
+which everybody knows; things which it is impossible to doubt "in a real
+case." (\S 303, Iliv. For Wittgenstein's theism, see Norman Malcolm's
+memoir.) The proper use of language admits of no alternative to belief in
+God; atheism is just a mistake in the use of language.
+
+
+In arguing against Wittgenstein, I will concentrate on the real reason
+why I oppose him, rather than on less fundamental technical issues. We read
+that in the Middle Ages, people found it impossible not to believe that they
+would be struck by lightning if they uttered a blasphemy; just as
+Wittgenstein finds the existence of God impossible to doubt "in a real case."
+Yet even Wittgenstein does not defend the former belief; while the Soviet
+Union has shown that a government can function which has repudiated the
+latter belief. There is a tremendous discovery here: that beliefs which were as
+inescapable---as impossible to doubt in a real case---as any belief we may have
+today, were subsequently discarded. How was this possible? My essay \essaytitle{The
+Flaws Underlying Beliefs} shows how. Further, it shows that the belief that
+the Empire State Building exists when I am not looking at it, or the belief
+that I would be killed if I jumped out of a tenth story window, are no
+different in principle from beliefs which we have already discarded. It Is
+perfectly possible to project a metaphysical outlook on experience which is
+totally different from the beliefs Wittgenstein inherited, and it is also
+possible not to project a metaphysical outlook on experience at all. Let us be
+absolutely clear: the point is not that we do not know with one hundred per
+cent certainty that the Empire State Building exists; the point is that we
+need not believe in the Empire State Building at all. \essaytitle{The Flaws Underlying
+Beliefs} shows that factual propositions, and the propositions of the natural
+sciences, involve outright self-deception.
+
+These discoveries have consequences far more important than the
+technical issues involved. It is by no means trivial that I do not have to pray,
+or to fast, or to accept the moral dictates of the clergy, or to give money to
+the Church. Because the Church prohibited the dissection of human
+cadavers, it took an atheist to originate the modern subject of anatomy. In
+analogy with this example, the rest of my writings are devoted to exploring
+the consequences of rejecting beliefs that Wittgenstein says are impossible to
+doubt in a real case, as in my essay \essaytitle{Philosophical Aspects of Walking
+Through Walls.} I oppose Wittgenstein because he descended to extremes of
+intellectual dishonesty in order to prevent us from discovering these
+consequences.
+
+A reply to the Wittgensteinian attitude which is technically adequate
+can be provided in short order, for when Wittgenstein's central philosophical
+maneuver is identified, its dishonesty becomes transparent. It is not
+necessary to enumerate the fallacies in the Wittgensteinian claim that logical
+connections and logical standards are extrinsic to the natural language, or in
+the aphorism that "the meaning is the use" (as an explication of the natural
+language). In other words, there is no reason why I should bandy descriptive
+linguistics with Wittgenstein. Wittgenstein was wrong at a level more basic
+than the level on which his philosophical discussions were conducted.
+
+Wittgenstein held that philosophical or metaphysical controversies
+literally would not arise if it were not for bad philosophers. They would not
+arise because there is nothing problematic about sentences, expressing
+Wittgenstein's inherited beliefs, in ordinary usage. This rhetorical maneuver
+is the inverse of what it seems to be. Wittgenstein doesn't prove that the
+paradoxes uncovered by "bad" philosophers result from a misuse of ordinary
+language; he defines the philosophers' discussions as a misuse of ordinary
+language because they uncover paradoxes is ordinary language propositions.
+Wittgenstein waits to see whether a philosopher uncovers problems in
+ordinary language propositions; and if the philosopher does so, then
+Wittgenstein defines his discussion as improper usage. Wittgenstein waits to
+see whether evidence is against his side, and if it is, he defines it as
+inadmissible.
+
+Consider the philosopher's question of how I know whether the \textsc{Empire
+State Building} continues to exist when I am not looking at it. The
+Wittgensteinian position on this question would be that it is problematic
+because it is a misuse of ordinary language; and because there is no
+behavioral context which constitutes a use for the question. According to
+this position, we would not encounter such problems if we would use
+ordinary language properly. But what does this position amount to? The
+philosopher's question has not been proved improper; it has been defined as
+improper because it leads to problems. The reason why "the proper use of
+ordinary language never leads to paradoxes" is that Wittgenstein has defined
+proper use as use in which no paradoxes are visible. Wittgenstein has not
+resolved or eliminated any problems; he has just refused to notice them.
+Wittgenstein attempts to pass off, as a discovery about philosophy and
+language, a gratuitous definition to the effect that certain portions of the
+natural language which embarrass him are inadmissible, a gratuitous ban on
+certain portions of the natural language which embarrass him. His purpose is
+to make criticism of his inherited beliefs impossible, to give them a spurious
+inescapability. Wittgenstein's maneuver is the last word in modish
+intellectual dishonesty.
+
+\gap
+
+\textbf{B.} In philosophy, arguments which start from an immediate which
+cannot be doubted and attempt to prove the existence of an objective reality
+are called transcendental arguments. Typically, such an argument says that if
+there is experience, there must be subject and object in experience; if there
+are subject and object, subject and object must be objectively real; and thus
+there must be objectively real mind and matter. Clearly, the belief which
+leaps the gap from the immediate to the objectively real is smuggled into the
+middle of the argument by a play on the words \enquote{subject} and \enquote{object.}
+
+When the sophistry is cleared away, it becomes apparent that the
+attempt to attain the trans-experiential or extra-experiential within
+experience faces a dilemma of overkill. If the attempt could succeed, it
+would have only collapsed objective reality to my subjectivity. If it could be
+"proved" that I know the distant past, other minds, God, angels, archangels,
+etc. from immediate experience, then all these phenomena would be
+trivialized. If other minds were given in my experience, they would only be
+my mind. The interest of the notion of objective reality is precisely its
+otherness and unreachability. If it could be reached from the immediate, it
+would be trivial. We ask how I know that the Empire State Building exists
+when I am not looking at it. If the answer is that I know through immediate
+experience, then objective reality has been collapsed to my subjectivity. The
+dilemma for transcendental arguments is that they propose to overcome the
+gap between the appearance of a thing and the thing itself, yet they do not
+want to conclude that appearances exhaust reality.
+
+There are two special assumptions which are smuggled into supposedly
+assumptionless transcendental arguments. First, there is the belief that there
+is an objective relationship between descriptive words and the things they
+describe, an objective criterion of the use of descriptive words. Secondly,
+there is the belief that correlations between the senses have an objective
+basis. (It is claimed that this belief cannot be doubted, but the claim is
+controverted by intersensory illusions such as the touching of a pencil with
+crossed fingers.)
+
+Transcendental arguments are secular theology, because they are
+addressed to a reader who wants only philosophical analyses that have
+conventional conclusions. A transcendental argument will contain a step
+such as the following, for example. We can have "real knowledge" of
+particular things only if there is an objective relationship between descriptive
+words and the things they describe; thus there must be such a relationship.
+This argument is plausible only if the reader can be trusted to overlook the
+alternative that we don't have this "real knowledge."
+
+In the way of supplementary remarks, we may mention that
+transcendental arguments typically commit the ontological fallacy: inferring
+the existence of a thing from the idea or name of the thing. Finally,
+transcendental arguments share a confusion which originates in the
+empiricism they are directed against: the confusion between doing
+fundamental philosophy and doing the psychology of perception. Many
+transcendental arguments are similar to current doctrines in scientific
+psychology. But they fail as philosophy, because scientific psychology takes
+as presuppositions, and cannot prove, the very beliefs which transcendental
+arguments are supposed to prove.
+
diff --git a/essays/walking_through_walls.tex b/essays/walking_through_walls.tex
new file mode 100644
index 0000000..b45f201
--- /dev/null
+++ b/essays/walking_through_walls.tex
@@ -0,0 +1,156 @@
+\chapter{Philosophical Aspects of Walking Through Walls}
+
+
+We read that in the Middle Ages, people found it impossible not to
+believe that they would be struck by lightning if they uttered a blasphemy.
+Yet I utterly disbelieve that I will be struck by lightning if I utter a
+blasphemy. Beliefs such as the one at issue here will be called fearful beliefs.
+Elsewhere, I have argued that all beliefs are self-deceiving. I have also
+observed that there are often non-cognitive motives for holding beliefs, so
+that a technical, analytical demonstration that a belief is self-deceiving will
+not necessarily provide a sufficient motive for renouncing it. The question
+then arises as to why people would hold fearful beliefs. It would seem that
+people would readily repudiate beliefs such as the one about blasphemy as
+soon as there was any reason to doubt them, even if the reason was abstract
+and technical. Yet fearful beliefs are held more tenaciously than any others.
+Further, when philosophers seek examples of beliefs which one cannot
+afford to give up, beliefs which are not mere social conventions, beliefs
+which are truly objective, they invariably choose fearful beliefs.
+
+Fearful beliefs raise some subtle questions about the character of beliefs
+as mental acts. If I contemplate blasphemy, experience a strong fear, and
+decide not to blaspheme, do I stand convicted of believing that I will be
+punished if I blaspheme, or may I claim that I was following an emotional
+preference which did not involve any belief? Is there a distinction between
+fearful avoidance and fearful belief? Can the emotion of fear be
+self-deceiving in and of itself? Must a belief have a verbal, propositional
+formulation, or is it possible to have a belief with no linguistic representation
+whatever?
+
+It is apparent that fearful beliefs suggest many topics for speculation.
+This essay, however, will concentrate exclusively on one topic, which is by
+far the most important. Given that people once held the belief about
+blasphemy, and that I do not, then I have succeeded in dispensing with a
+fearful belief. Two beliefs which are exactly analogous to the one about
+blasphemy are the belief that if I jump out of a tenth story window I will be
+hurt, and the belief that if I attempt to walk through a wall I will bruise
+myself. Given that I am able to dispense with the belief about blasphemy, it
+follows that, in effect, I am able to walk through walls relative to medieval
+people. That is, my ability to blaspheme without being struck by lightning
+would be as unimaginable to them as the ability to walk through walls is
+today. The topic of this essay is whether it is possible to transfer my
+achievement concerning blasphemy to other fearful beliefs.
+
+\visbreak
+
+I am told that \enquote{if you jump out of a tenth story window you really will
+be hurt.} Yet the analogous exhortation concerning blasphemy is not
+convincing or compelling at all. Why not? I suggest that the nature of the
+"evidence" implied in the exhortation should be examined very closely to
+see if it does not represent an epistemological swindle. In the cases of both
+blasphemy and jumping out of the window, I am told that if I perform the
+action I will suffer injury. But do I concede that I have to blaspheme, in
+order to prove that I can get away with it? Actually, I do not blaspheme; I
+simply do not perform the action at all. Yet I do not have any belief
+whatever that it would be dangerous to do so. Why should anyone suppose
+that because I do not believe something, I have to run out in the street,
+shake my fist at the sky, and curse God in order to validate may disbelief?
+Why should the credulous person be able to put me in in the position of
+having to accept the dare that "you have to do it to prove you don't believe
+it's dangerous"? Could it not be that this dare is some sort of a swindle?
+The structure of the evidence for the supposedly unrelinquishable belief
+should be examined very closely to see if it is not so much legerdemain.
+
+The exhortation continues to the effect that if I did utter blasphemy I
+really would be struck by lightning. I still do not find this compelling. But
+suppose that I do see someone utter a blasphemy and get struck by lightning.
+Surely this must convert me. But with due apologies to the faithful, I must
+report that it does not. There is no reason why it should make me believe. I
+do not believe that blaspheming will cause me to be struck by lightning, and
+the evocation of frightful images---or for that matter, something that I
+see---would provide no reason whatever for sudden credulity. There is an
+immense difference between seeing a person blaspheme and get struck by
+lightning, and believing that if one blasphemes, one will get struck by
+lightning. This difference should be quite apparent to one who does not hold
+the belief.\footnote{In more conventional terms, the civilization in which I tive is so
+profoundly secular that its secularism cannot be demolished by one
+"sighting."}
+
+In general, the so-called evidence doesn't work. There is a swindle
+somewhere in the evidence that is supposed to make me accept the fearful
+belief. Upon close scrutiny, each bit of evidence misses the target. Yet the
+whole conglomeration of "evidence" somehow overwhelmed medieval
+people. They had to believe something that I do not believe. I can get away
+with something that they could not get away with.
+
+It is not that I stand up in a society of the faithful and suddenly
+blaspheme. It is rather that the whole medieval cognitive orientation had
+been completely reoriented by the time it was transmitted to me. Or in other
+words, the medieval cognitive orientation was restructured throughout
+during the modern era. In the process, the compelling conglomeration of
+evidence was disintegrated. Isolated from their niches in the old orientation,
+the bits of evidence no longer worked. Each bit missed the target. I do not
+have a head-on confrontation with the medieval impossibility of
+blaspheming. I slip by the impossibility, where they could not, because I
+structure the entire situation, and the evidence, differently.
+
+The analysis just presented, combined with analyses of beliefs which I
+have made elsewhere, assures me that the belief that "if I try to walk
+through the wall I will fail and will bruise myself" is also discardable. I am
+sure that I can walk through walls just as successfully as I can blaspheme.
+But to do so will not be trivial. As I have shown, escaping the power of a
+fearful belief is not a matter of head-on confrontation, but of restructuring
+the entire situation, of restructuring evidence, so that the conglomeration of
+evidence is disintegrated into isolated bits which are separately powerless.
+Only then can one slip by the impossibility. I cannot exercise my freedom to
+walk through walls until the whole cognitive orientation of the modern era is
+restructured throughout.
+
+The project of restructuring the modern cognitive orientation is a vast
+one. The natural sciences must certainly be dismantled. In this connection it
+is appropriate to make a criticism about the logic of science as Carnap
+rationalized it. Carnap considered a proposition meaningful if it had any
+empirically verifiable proposition as an implication. But consider an
+appropriate ensemble of scientific propositions in good standing, and
+conceive of it as a conjunction of an infinite number of propositions about
+single events (what Carnap called protocol-sentences). Only a very small
+number of the latter propositions are indeed subject to verification. If we
+sever them from the entire conjunction, what remains is as effectively
+blocked from verification as the propositions which Carnap rejected as
+meaningless. This criticism of science is not a mere technical exercise. A
+scientific proposition is a fabrication which amalgamates a few trivially
+testable meanings with an infinite number of untestable meanings and
+inveigles us to accept the whole conglomeration at once. It is apparent at the
+very beginning of \booktitle{Philosophy and Logical Syntax} that Carnap recognized this
+quite clearly; but it did not occur to him to do anything about it. For us,
+however, it is essential to be assured that science can be dismantled just as
+the proof can be dismantled that I will be struck by lightning if I blaspheme.
+
+We can suggest some other approaches which may contribute to
+overcoming the modern cognitive orientation. The habitual correlation of
+the realm of sight and the realm of touch which occurs when we perceive
+"objects" is a likely candidate for dismantling.\footnote{The psychological jargon for
+this correlation is "the contribution of intermodal organization to the
+object Gestalt."}
+
+From a different traditon, the critique of scientific fact and of
+measurable time which is suggested in Luk\'{a}cs' \booktitle{Reification and the
+Consciousness of the Proletariat} might be of value if it were developed.\footnote{Lulkacs also implied that scientific truth would disappear in a communist
+society---that is, a society without necessary labor, in which the right to
+subsistence was unconditional. He implied that scientific quantification and
+facticity are closely connected with the work discipline required by the
+capitalist mode of production; and that like the price system, they constitute
+a false objectivity which we accept because the social economic institutions
+deprive us of subsistence if we fail to submit to them. Quite aside from the
+historical unlikelihood of a communist society, this suggestion might be
+pursued as a thought experiment to obtain a more detailed characterization
+of the hypothetical post-scientific outlook.}
+
+Finally, I may mention that most of my own writings are offered as
+fragmentary beginnings in the project of dismantling the modern cognitive
+orientation.
+
+Someday we will realize that we were always free to walk through
+walls. But we could not exercise this freedom because we structured the
+whole situation, and the evidence, in an enslaving way.
+