summaryrefslogtreecommitdiffstats
path: root/essays/post_formalism_memories.tex
diff options
context:
space:
mode:
Diffstat (limited to 'essays/post_formalism_memories.tex')
-rw-r--r--essays/post_formalism_memories.tex673
1 files changed, 673 insertions, 0 deletions
diff --git a/essays/post_formalism_memories.tex b/essays/post_formalism_memories.tex
new file mode 100644
index 0000000..bf7decc
--- /dev/null
+++ b/essays/post_formalism_memories.tex
@@ -0,0 +1,673 @@
+\chapter{Post-Formalism in Constructed Memories}
+\section{Post-Formalist Mathematics}
+
+Over the last hundred years, a philosophy of pure mathematics has
+grown up which I prefer to call "formalism." As Willard Quine says in the
+fourth section of his essay "Carnap and Logical Truth,' formalism was
+inspired by a series of developments which began with non-Euclidian
+geometry. Quine himself is opposed to formalism, but the formalists have
+found encouragement in Quine's own book, \booktitle{Mathematical Logic}. The best
+presentation of the formalist position can be found in Rudolph Carnap's
+\booktitle{The Logical Syntax of Language}. As a motivation to the reader, and
+as a heuristic aid, I will relate my study to these two standard books. (It will
+heip if the reader is thoroughly familiar with them.) it is not important
+whether Carnap, or Quine, or formalism---or my interpretation of them---is
+"correct," for this essay is neither history nor philosophy. I am using history
+as a bridge, to give the reader access to some extreme mathematical
+innovations.
+
+The formalist position goes as follows. Pure mathematics is the
+manipulation of the meaningless and arbitrary, but typographically
+well-defined ink-shapes on paper 'w,' 'x,' 'y,' 'z,' '{}',' '(,' '),' '$\downarrow$,' and '$\in$.'
+These shapes are manipulated according to arbitrary but well-detined
+mechanical rules. Actually, the rules mimic the structure of primitive
+systems such as Euclid's geometry. There are formation rules, mechanical
+definitions of which concatenations of shapes are "sentences." One sentence
+is '$((x) (x\in x) \downarrow (x) (x\in x))$.' There are transformation rules, rules for the
+mechanical derivation of sentences from other sentences. The best known
+trasformation rule is the rule that $\psi$ may be concluded from $\varphi$ and
+$\ulcorner \varphi \supset \psi \urcorner$;
+where '$\supset$' is the truth-functional conditional. For later convenience, I will
+say that $\varphi$ and $\ulcorner \varphi \supset \psi \urcorner$ are "impliors,"
+and that $\psi$ is the "implicand."
+Some sentences are designated as "axioms." A "proof" is a series of
+sentences such that each is an axiom or an implicand of preceding sentences.
+The last sentence in a proof is a "theorem."
+
+This account is ultrasimplified and non-rigorous, but it is adequate for
+my purposes. (The reader may have noticed a terminological issue here. For
+Quine, an implication is merely a logically true conditional. The rules which
+are used to go from some statements to others, and to assemble proofs, are
+rules of inference. The relevant rule of inference is the modus ponens; $\psi$ is
+the ponential of $\varphi$ and $\ulcorner \varphi \supset \psi \urcorner$. What I
+am doing is to use a terminology of
+implication to talk about rules of inference and ponentials. The reason is
+that the use of Quine's terminology would result in extremely awkward
+formulations. What I will be doing is sufficiently transparent that it can be
+translated into Quine's terminology if necessary. My results will be
+unaffected.) The decisive feature of the arbitrary game called "mathematics"
+is as follows. A sentence-series can be mechanically checked to determine
+whether it is a proof. But there is no mechanical method for deciding
+whether a sentence is a theorem. Theorems, or rather their proofs, have to be
+puzzled out, to be discovered. in this feature lies the dynamism, the
+excitement of traditional mathematics. Traditional mathematical ability is
+the ability to make inferential discoveries.
+
+A variety of branches of mathematics can be specialized out from the
+basic system. Depending on the choices of axioms, systems can be
+constructed which are internally consistent, but conflict with each other. A
+system can be "interpreted," or given a meaning within the language of a
+science such as physics. So interpreted, it may have scientific value, or it may
+not. But as pure mathematics, all the systems have the same arbitrary status.
+
+By "formalist mathematics" I will mean the present mathematical
+systems which are presented along the above lines. Actually, as many authors
+have observed, the success of the non-Euclidian "imaginary" geometries
+made recognition of the game-like character of mathematics inevitable.
+Formalism is potentially the greatest break with tradition in the history of
+mathematics. In the Foreward to \booktitle{The Logical Syntax of Language}, Carnap
+brilliantly points out that mathematical innovation is still hindered by the
+widespread opinion that deviations from mathematical tradition must be
+justified---that is, proved to be "correct" and to be a faithful rendering of
+"the true logic." According to Carnap, we are free to choose the rules of a
+mathematical system arbitrarily. The striving after correctness must cease, so
+that mathematics will no longer be hindered. \said{Before us lies the boundless
+ocean of unlimited possibilities.} In other words, Carnap, the most reputable
+of academicians, says you can do anything in mathematics. Do not worry
+whether whether your arbitrary game corresponds to truth, tradition, or
+reality: it is still legitimate mathematics. Despite this wonderful Principle of
+Tolerance in mathematics, Carnap never ventured beyond the old
+ink-on-paper, axiomatic-deductive structures. I, however, have taken Carnap
+at his word. The result is my "post-formalist mathematics." I want to stress
+that my innovations have been legitimized in advance by one of the most
+reputable academic figures of the twentieth century.
+
+Early in 1961, I constructed some systems which went beyond
+formalist mathematics in two respects. 1. My sentential elements are
+physically different from the little ink-shapes on paper used in all formalist
+systems. My sentences are physically different from concatenations of
+ink-shapes. My transformation rules have nothing to do with operations on
+ink-shapes. 2. My systems do not necessarily follow the axiomatic-deductive,
+sentence-implication-axiom-proof-theorem structure. Both of these
+possibilities, by the way, are mentioned by Carnap in \papertitle{Languages as
+Calculi.} A "post-formalist system," then, is a formalist system which differs
+physically from an ink-on-paper system, or which lacks the
+axiomatic-deductive structure.
+
+As a basis for the analysis of post-formalist systems, a list of structural
+properties of formalist systems is desirable. Here is such a list. By
+"implication" I will mean simple, direct implication, unless I say otherwise.
+\begin{enumerate}
+\item A sentence can be repeated at will.
+
+\item The rule of implication refers to elements of sentences: sentences
+are structurally composite.
+
+\item A sentence can imply itself.
+
+\item The repeat of an implior can imply the repeat of an implicand: an
+implication can be repeated.
+
+\item Different impliors can imply different implicands.
+
+\item Given two or three sentences, it is possible to recognize
+mechanically whether one or two directly imply the third.
+
+\item No axiom is implied by other, different axioms.
+
+\item The definition of "proof" is the standard definition, in terms of
+implication, given early in this essay.
+
+\item Given the axioms and some other sentence, it is not possible to
+recognize mechanically whether the sentence is a theorem.
+Compound indirect implication is a puzzle.
+\end{enumerate}
+
+Now for the first post-formalist system.
+
+{ \centering \large "\textsc{Illusions}" \par}
+
+\begin{sysrules}
+A "sentence" is the following page (with the figure on it) so long as the
+apparent, perceived ratio of the length of the vertical line to that
+of the horizontal line (the statement's "associated ratio") does not
+change. (Two sentences are the "same" if end only if their
+associated ratios are the same.)
+
+A sentence Y is "implied by" a sentence X if and only if Y is the same as X,
+or else Y is, of all the sentences one ever sees, the sentence having
+the associated ratio next smaller than that of X.
+
+Take as the axiom the first sentence one sees.
+
+Explanation: The figure is an optical illusion such that the vertical line
+normally appears longer than the horizontal line, even though their
+lengths are equal. One can correct one's perception, come to see
+the vertical line as shorter relative to the horizontal line, decrease
+the associated ratio, by measuring the lines with a ruler to convince
+oneself that the vertical line is not longer than the other, and then
+trying to see the lines as equal in length; constructing similar
+figures with a variety of real (measured) ratios and practicing
+judging these ratios; and so forth.
+\end{sysrules}
+
+\img{illusions}
+
+"IIlusions" has Properties 1, 3--5, and 7--8. Purely to clarify this fact, the
+following sequence of integers is presented as a model of the order in which
+associated ratios might appear in reality. (The sequence is otherwise totally
+inadequate as a model of "Illusions.") 4 2 1; 4 2; 5 4 2 1; 4 3 1. The
+implication structure would then be
+
+\img{illusionstructure}
+
+The axiom would be 4, and 5 could not appear in a proof. "IIlusions" has
+Property 1 on the basis that one can control the associated ratio. Turning to
+Property 4, it is normally the case that when an implication is repeated, a
+given occurrence of one of the sentences involved is unique to a specific
+occurrence of the implication. In "Illusions," however, if two equal
+sentences are next smaller than X, the occurrence of X does not uniquely
+ belong to either of the two occurrences of the implication. Compare '\begin{tabular}{c c c} t & h & e \\ h & & \\ e & & \end{tabular}',
+where the occurrence of 't' is not unique to either occurrence of 'the'.
+Subject to this explanation, "Illusions" has Property 4. "Illusions" has
+Property 8, but it goes without saying that the type of implication is not
+modus ponens. Properties 3, 5, and 7 need no comment. As for Property 2,
+the rule of implication refers to a property of sentences, rather than to
+elements of sentences. The interesting feature of "IIlusions" is that it
+reverses the situation defined by Properties 6 and 9. Compound indirect
+implication is about the same as simple implication. The only difference is
+the difference between being smaller and being next smaller. And there is
+only one axiom (per person).
+
+Simple direct implication, however, is subjective and illusive. It
+essentially involves changing one's perceptions of an illusion. The change of
+associated ratios is subjective, elusive, and certainly not numerically
+measurable. Then, the order in which one sees sentences won't always be
+their order in the implications and proofs. And even though one is exposed
+to all the sentences, one may have difficulty distinguishing and remembering
+them in consciousness. If I see the normal illusion, then manage to get
+myself to see the lines as being of equal length, I know I have seen a
+theorem. What is difficult is grasping the steps in between, the simple direct
+implications. If the brain contains a permanent impression of every sensation
+it has received, then the implications objectively exist; but they may not be
+thinkable without neurological techniques for getting at the impressions. In
+any case, "proof" is well-defined in some sense---but proofs may not be
+thinkable. "Illusions" is, after all, not so much shakier in this respect than
+even simple arithmetic, which contains undecidable sentences and
+indefinable terms.
+
+In \booktitle{The Logical Syntax of Language}, Carnap distinguishes pure syntax
+and descriptive syntax; and says that pure syntax should be independent of
+notation, and that every system should be isomorphic to some ink-on-paper
+system. In so doing, Carnap violates his ov'n Principle of Tolerance. Consider
+the following trivial formalist system.
+
+{ \centering \large "\textsc{Order}" \par}
+
+\begin{sysrules}
+A "sentence" is a member of a finite set of integers.
+
+Sentence Y is "implied by" sentence X if and only if Y=X, or else of all the
+sentences, Y is the one next smaller than X.
+
+Take as the axiom the largest sentence.
+\end{sysrules}
+
+Is the pure syntax of "\textsc{Illusions}" insomorphic to "\textsc{Order}"? The preceding
+paragraph proved that it is not. The implication structure of "Order" is
+mechanical to the point of idiocy, while the implication structure of
+"Illusions" is, as I pointed out, elusive. The figure
+
+\img{orderstructure}
+
+where loops indicate multiple occurances of the same sentence, could
+adequately represent a proof in "Order," but could not remotely represent
+one in "Illusions." The essence of "Illusions" is that it is coupled to the
+reader's subjectivity. For an ink-on-paper system even to be comparable to
+"IIlusions," the subjectivity would have to be moved out of the reader and
+onto the paper. This is utterly impossible.
+
+Here is the next system.
+
+{ \centering \large "\textsc{Innperseqs}" \par}
+
+\begin{sysrules}
+Explanation: Consider the rainbow halo which appears to surround a small
+bright light when one looks at it through fogged glass (such as
+eyeglasses which have been breathed on). The halo consists of
+concentric circular bands of color. As the fog evaporates, the halo
+uniformly contracts toward the light. The halo has a vague outer
+ring, which contracts as the halo does. Of concern here is what
+happens on one contracting radius of the halo, and specifically
+what happens on the segment of that radius lying in the vague
+outer ring: the outer segment.
+
+A "sentence" (or halopoint) is the changing halo color at a fixed point, in
+space, in the halo; until the halo contracts past the point.
+
+Several sentences "imply" another sentence if and only if, at some instant,
+the several sentences are on an outer segment, and the other
+sentence is the inner endpoint of that outer segment.
+
+An "axiom" is a sentence which is in the initial vague outer ring (before it
+contracts), and which is not an inner endpoint.
+
+An "innperseq" is a sequence of sequences of sentences on one radius
+satisfying the following conditions. 1. The members of the first
+sequence are axioms, 2. For each of the other sequences, the first
+member is implied by the non-first members of the preceding
+sequence; and the remaining inembers (if any) are axioms or first
+members of preceding sequences. 3. All first members, of
+sequences other than the last two, appear as non-first members. 4.
+No sentence appears as a non-first member more than once. 5. The
+last sequence has one member.
+
+In the diagram on the following page, different positions of the vague outer
+ring at different times are suggested by different shadings. The
+outer segment moves "down the page." The figure is by no means
+an innperseq, but is supposed to help explain the definition.
+\end{sysrules}
+
+Successive bands represent the vague outer ring at successive times as it fades in
+toward the small bright light.
+
+Innperseqs Diagram
+
+\img{innperseqs}
+
+"Sentences" at
+
+ \begin{tabular}{ c r l }
+ \bimg{time1} & $time_1$: & $a_1 a_2 a_3 a_4 a_5 a_6 a_7 b$ \\
+ & & $a_1,a_2 \rightarrow\ b$ \\
+ \end{tabular}
+
+ \begin{tabular}{c r l}
+ \bimg{time2} & $time_2$: & $a_2 a_3 a_4 a_5 a_6 a_7 b c$ \\
+ & & $a_3 \rightarrow\ c$ \\
+ \end{tabular}
+
+ \begin{tabular}{c r l}
+ \bimg{time3} & $time_3$: & $a_4 a_5 a_6 a_7 b c d$ \\
+ & & $a_4,a_5 \rightarrow\ d$ \\
+ \end{tabular}
+
+ \begin{tabular}{c r l}
+ \bimg{time4} & $time_4$: & $a_6 a_7 b c d e$ \\
+ & & $a_6,b \rightarrow\ e$ \\
+ \end{tabular}
+
+ \begin{tabular}{c r l}
+ \bimg{time5} & $time_5$: & $a_7 b c d e f$ \\
+ & & $a_7,c \rightarrow\ f$ \\
+ \end{tabular}
+
+ \begin{tabular}{c r l}
+ \bimg{time6} & $time_6$: & $c d e f g$ \\
+ & & $d,e \rightarrow\ g$ \\
+ \end{tabular}
+
+"Axioms" $a_1 a_2 a_3 a_4 a_5 a_6 a_7$
+
+
+Innperseq \\
+$(a_3,a_2,a_1)$
+$(b,a_3)$
+$(c,a_5,a_4)$
+$(d,b,a_6)$
+$(e,c,a_7)$
+$(f,e,d)$
+$(g)$
+
+In "Innperseqs," a conventional proof would be redundant unless all
+the statements were on the same radius. And even if the weakest axiom were
+chosen (the initial outer endpoint), this axiom would imply the initial inner
+endpoint, and from there the theorem could be reached immediately. In
+other words, to use the standard definition of "proof" in "Innperseqs"
+would result in an uninteresting derivation structure. Thus, a more
+interesting derivation structure is defined, the "innperseq." The interest of
+an "innperseq" is to be as elaborate as the many restrictions in its definition
+will allow. Proofs are either disregarded in "Innperseqs"; or else they are
+identified with innpersegs, and lack Property 8. "Innperseqs" makes the
+break with the proof-theorem structure of formalist mathematics.
+
+Turning to simple implication, an implicand can have many impliors;
+and there is an infinity of axioms, specified by a general condition. The
+system has Property 1 in the sense that a sentence can exist at different
+times and be a member of different implications. It has Property 4 in the
+sense that the sentences in a specific implication can exist at different times,
+and the implication holds as long as the sentences exist. It has Property 3 in
+that an inner endpoint implies itself. The system also has Properties 5 and 7;
+and lacks Property 2. But, as before, Properties 6 and 9 are another matter.
+Given several sentences, it is certainly possible to tell mechanically whether
+one is implied by the others. But when are you given sentences? If one can
+think the sentences, then relating them is easy---but it is difficult to think the
+sentences in the first place, even though they objectively exist. The diagram
+suggests what to look for, but the actual thinking, the actual sentences are
+another matter. As for Property 9, when "theorems" are identified with last
+members of innperseqs, I hesitate to say whether a derivation of a given
+sentence can be constructed mechanically. If a sentence is nearer the center
+than the axioms are, an innperseq can be constructed for it. Or can it? The
+answer is contingent. "Innperseqs" is indeterminate because of the difficulty
+of thinking the sentences, a difficulty which is defined into the system. It is
+the mathematician's capabilities at a particular instant which delimit the
+indeterminacies. Precisely because of the difficulty of thinking sentences, I
+will give several subvariants of the system.
+
+{ \centering \large \textsc{Indeterminacy} \par}
+\begin{sysrules}
+A "totally determinate innperseq" is an innperseq in which one thinks all the
+sentences.
+
+An "implior-indeterminate innperseq" is an innperseq in which one thinks
+only each implicand and the outer segment it terminates.
+
+A "sententially indeterminate innperseq" is an innperseq in which one thinks
+only the outer segment, and its inner endpoint, as it progresses
+inward.
+\end{sysrules}
+
+
+Let us return to the matter of pure and descriptive syntax. The interest
+of "Illusions" and "Innperseqs" is precisely that their abstract structure
+cannot be separated from their physical and psychological character, and
+thus that they are not isomorphic to any conventional ink-on-paper system. I
+am trying to break through to unheard of, and hopefully significant, modes
+of implication; to define implication structures (and derivation structures)
+beyond the reach of past mathematics.
+
+\subsection{Constructed Memory Systems}
+
+In order to understand this section, it is necessary to be thoroughly
+familiar with \essaytitle{Studies in Constructed Memories,} the essay following this
+one. (I have not combined the two essays because their approaches are too
+different.) I will define post-formalist systems in constructed memories,
+beginning with a system in an M*-Memory.
+
+{ \centering \large "\textsc{Dream Amalgams}" \par}
+
+\begin{sysrules}
+A "sentence" is a possible method, an $A_{a_i}$. with respect to an M*-Memory.
+The sentence $A_{a_p}$ "implies" the sentence $A_{a_q}$ if and only if the $a_q$th
+M*-assertion is actually thought; and either $A_{a_q} = A_{a_p}$, or else there is
+cross-method contact of a mental state in $A_{a_q}$ with a state in $A_{q_p}$\footnote{sic?}
+
+The axioms must be chosen from sentences which satisfy two conditions.
+The mental states in the sentences must have cross-method contact
+with mental states in other sentences. And the M*-assertions
+corresponding to the sentences must not be thought.
+
+Explanation: As \essaytitle{Studies in Constructed Memories} says, there can be
+cross-method contact of states, because a normal dream can
+combine totally different episodes in the dreamer's life into an
+amalgam.
+\end{sysrules}
+
+"\textsc{Dream Amalgams}" has Properties 1-5. For the first time, sentences are
+structurally composite, with mental states being the relevant sentential
+elements. Implication has an unusual character. The traditional type of
+implication, modus ponens, is "directed," because the conditional is
+directed. Even if $\ulcorner\varphi\supset\phi\urcorner$ is true
+$\ulcorner\varphi\supset\phi\urcorner$ may not be. Now implication is also
+directed in "\textsc{Dream Amalgams,}" but for a very different reason.
+Cross-method contact, unlike the conditional, has a symmetric character.
+What prevents implication from being necessarily symmetrical is that the
+implicand's M*-assertion actually has to be thought, while the implior's
+M*-assertion does not. Thus, implication is both subjective and mechanical,
+it is subjective, in that it is a matter of volition which method is remembered
+to have actually: been used. It is mechanical, in that when one is
+remembering, one is automatically aware of the cross-method contacts of
+states in $A_{a_q}$. The conditions on the axioms ensure that they will have
+implications without losing Property 7.
+
+As for compound implication in "\textsc{Dream Amalgams,}" the organism
+with the M*-Memory can't be aware of it at all; because it can't be aware
+that at different times it remembered different methods to be the one
+actually used. (In fact, the organism cannot be aware that the system has
+Property 5, for the same reason.) On the other hand, to an outside observer
+of the M*-Memory, indirect implication is not only thinkable but
+mechanical. It is not superfluous because cross-method contact of mental
+states is not necessarily transitive. The outside observer can decide whether a
+sentence is a theorem by the following mechanical procedure. Check
+whether the sentence's M*-assertion has acually been thought; if so, check all
+sentences which imply it to see if any are axioms; if not, check all the
+sentences which imply the sentences which imply it to see if any are axioms;
+etc. The number of possible methods is given as finite, so the procedure is
+certain to terminate. Again, an unprecedented mode of implication has been
+defined.
+
+When a post-formalist system is defined in a constructed memory, the
+discussion and analysis of the system become a consequence of constructed
+memory theory and an extension of it. Constructed memory theory, which
+is quite unusual but still more or less employs deductive inference, is used to
+study post-formalist modes of inference which are anything but deductive.
+
+To aid in understanding the next system, which involves infalls in a
+D-Memory, here is an
+
+{ \centering \large \framebox[1.1\width]{"Exercise to be Read Aloud"} \par}
+
+(Read according to a timer, reading the first word at O' O", and prolonging
+and spacing words so that each sentence ends at the time in parentheses after
+it. Do not pause netween sentences.)
+
+\begin{tabular}{ r l }
+ ($event_1$) & All men are mortal. (17") \\
+
+ ($Sentence_1=event_2s$) & The first utterance lasted 17" and ended at 17"; and lasted 15" and ended 1" ago. (59") \\
+
+ ($S_2=event_3$) & The second utterance lasted 42" and ended at 59": and lasted 50" and ended 2" ago. (1' 31") \\
+
+ ($S_3=event_4$) & The third utterance lasted 32" and ended at 1' 31"; and lasted 40" and ended 1" ago. (2' 16") \\
+\end{tabular}
+
+Since '32' in $S_3$ is greater than '2' in $S_2$, $S_2$ must say that $S_1$ ($=event_2$)
+ended 30" after $S_2$ began, or something equally unclear. The duration of $S_2$
+is greater than the distance into the past to which it refers. This situation is
+not a real infall, but it should give the reader some intuitive notion of an
+infall.
+
+
+\newcommand{\midheading}[1]{
+ { \centering \large \textsc{#1} \par}}
+
+\midheading{"Infalls"}
+
+\begin{sysrules}
+ A "sentence" is a D-sentence, in a D-Memory such that $event_{j+1}$ is the first
+thinking of the jth D-sentence, for all j.
+
+Two sentences "imply" another if and only if all three are the same; or else
+the three are adjacent (and can be written $S_{j+1},S_j,S_{j-1}$), and are such
+that $\delta_j=x_{j+1}-x_j> z_j,$ $S^D_{j-1}$ is the implicand. (The function of $S_{j+1}$ is to
+give the duration $\delta_j=x_{j+1}-x_j$ of $S_j$. $S_j$ states that $event_j$, the first
+thinking of $S^{D}_{j-1}$, ended at a distance $z_j$ into the past, where $z_j$ is smaller
+than $S^D_j$'s own duration. The diagram indicates the relations.)
+\end{sysrules}
+
+\img{infallsdiag}
+
+In this variety of D-Memory, the organism continuously thinks successive
+D-sentences, which are all different, just as the reader of the above exercise
+continuously reads successive and different sentences. Thus, the possibility
+of repeating a sentence depends on the possibility of thinking it while one is
+thinking another sentence---a possibility which may be far-fetched, but which
+is not explicitly excluded by the definition of a "D-Memory." If the
+possibility is granted, then "\textsc{Infalls}" has Properties 1--5. Direct implication is
+completely mechanical; it is subjective only in that the involuntary
+determination of the $z_j$ and other aspects of the memory is a 'subjective'
+process of the organism. Compound implication is also mechanical to an
+outside observer of the memory, but if the organism itself is to be aware of
+it, it has to perform fantastic feats of multiple thinking.
+
+"\textsc{Dream Amalgams}" and "\textsc{Infalls}" are systems constructed with
+imaginary elements, systems whose "notation" is drawn from an imaginary
+object or system. Such systems have no descriptive syntax. Imaginary objects
+were introduced into mathematics, or at least into geometry, by Nicholas
+Lobachevski, and now I am using them as a notation. For these systems to
+be nonisomorphic to any ink-on-paper systems, the mathematician must be
+the organism with the M*-Memory or the D*-Memory. But this means that
+in this case, the mathematics which is nonisomorphic to any ink-on-paper
+system can be performed only in an imaginary mind.
+
+Now for a different approach. Carnap said that we are free to choose
+the rules of a system arbitrarily. Let us take Carnap literally. I want to
+construct more systems in constructed memories---so why not construct the
+system by a procedure which ensures that constructed memories are
+involved, but which is otherwise arbitrary? Why not suspend the striving
+after "interesting" systems, that last vestige of the striving after
+"correctness," and see what happens? Why not construct the rules of a
+system by a chance procedure?
+
+To construct a system, we have to fill in the blanks in the following rule
+schema in such a way that grammatically correct sentences result.
+
+\newcommand{\blankspace}{\_\_\_\_\_\_\_\_\_\_}
+
+\midheading{Rule Schema}
+
+\begin{sysrules}
+A "sentence" is a(n) \blankspace.
+
+Two sentences "imply" a third if and only if the two sentences \blankspace\ the third.
+
+An "axiom" is a sentence that \blankspace.
+\end{sysrules}
+
+
+I now spread the pages of \essaytitle{Studies in Constructed Memories} on the floor.
+With eyes closed, I hold a penny over them and drop it. I open my eyes and
+copy down the expressions the penny covers. By repeating this routine, I
+obtain a haphazard series of expressions concerning constructed memories. It
+is with this series that I will fill in the blanks in the rule schema. In the next
+stage, I fill the first (second, third) blank with the ceries of expressions
+preceding the-first (second, third) period in the entire series.
+
+\midheading{"Haphazard System"}
+
+\begin{sysrules}
+A "sentence" is a the duration D-sentences $\triangle\ (\mathparagraph^m)$ conclude these
+"$\Phi*$-Reflection," or the future Assumption voluntarily force of
+conviction for conclusion the Situation or by ongoing that this
+system? be given telling between the Situation 1.
+
+Two sentences "imply" a third if and only if the two sentences is\slash was
+contained not have to the acceptance that a certain and malleable
+study what an event involves material specifically mathematics:
+construct accompanies the rest, extra-linguistically image organism
+can fantasy not remembering $\Phi*$-Memory, the future interval defined
+in dream the third.
+
+An "axiom" is a sentence that internally D-sentences, just as the
+"$\Phi*$-Memory" sentences $A_{a_1}$ is $A_{a_2}$.
+
+In the final stage, I cancel the smallest number of words I have to in
+order to make the rules grammatical.
+\end{sysrules}
+
+\midheading{"Fantasied Amnesia"}
+
+\begin{sysrules}
+A "sentence" is a duration or the future force of conviction for the Situation
+or this system given Situation 1.
+
+Two sentences "imply" a third if and only if the two sentences have the
+acceptance that a certain and malleable study extra-linguistically can
+fantasy not remembering the future interval defined in the third.
+
+An "axiom" is a sentence that internally just sentences $A_{a_2}$.
+\end{sysrules}
+
+It becomes clear in thinking about "Fantasied Amnesia" that its
+metametamathematics is dual. Describing the construction of the rules, the
+metamathematics, by a systematic performance, is one thing. Taking the
+finished metamathematics at face value, independently of its origin, and
+studying it in the usual manner, is another. Let us take "Fantasied Amnesia"
+at face value. As one becomes used to its rules, they become somewhat more
+meaningful. I will say that an "interpretation" of a haphazard system is an
+explanation of its rules that makes some sense out of what may seem
+senseless. "Interpreting" is somewhat like finding the conditions for the
+existence of a constructed memory which seemingly cannot exist. The first
+rule of "Fantasied Amnesia" is a disjunction of three substantives. The
+"Situation" referred to in the second substantive expression is either
+Situation 1 or else an unspecified situation. The third substantive expression
+apparently means "this system, assuming Situation 1," and refers to
+"Fantasied Amnesia" itself. The definition of "sentence" is thus meaningful,
+but very bizarre. The second rule speaks of "the acceptance" as if it were a
+written assent. The rule then speaks of a "malleable study" as "fantasying"
+something. This construction is quite weird, but let us try to accept it. The
+third rule speaks of a sentence that "sentences" (in the legal sense) a possible
+method. So much for the meaning of the rules.
+
+Turning to the nine properties of formalist systems, the reference to
+"the future interval" in the implication rule of "Fantasied Amnesia"
+indicates that the system has Property 2; and the system can perfectly well
+have Property 8. It does not have Property 6 in any known sense. Certainly
+it does have Property 9. it just might have Property. 1. But as for the other
+four properties, it seems out of the question to decide whether "Fantasied
+Amnesia" has them. For whatever it is worth, "Fantasied Amnesia" is on
+balance incomparable to formalist systems.
+
+My transformation rule schema has the form of a biconditional, in
+which the right clause is the operative one. If a transformation rule were to
+vary, in such a way that it could be replaced by a constant rule whose right
+clause was the disjunction of the various right clauses for the variable rule,
+then the latter would vary "trivially." 1 will say that a system whose
+transformation rule can vary non-trivially is a "heterodeterminate" system.
+Since 1 have constructed a haphazard metamathematics, why not a
+heterodeterminate metamathematics? Consider a mathematician with an
+M-Memory, such that each $A_{a_i}$. is the consistent use of a different
+transformation rule, a different definition of "imply," for the mathematics
+in which the mathematician is discovering theorems. The consistent use of a
+transformation rule is after all a method---a method for finding the
+commitments premisses make, and for basing conclusions in premisses. When
+the mathematician goes to remember which rule of inference he has actually
+been using, he "chooses" which of the possible methods is remembered to
+have actually been used. This situation amounts to a heterodeterminate
+system. tn fact, the metamathematics cannot even be written out this time; I
+can only describe it metametamathematically in terms of an imaginary
+memory.
+
+We are now in the realm of mathematical systems which cannot be
+written out, but can only be described metametamathematically. I will
+present a final system of this sort. It is entitled \textsc{"System Such That No One
+Knows What's Going On."} One just has to guess whether this system exists,
+and if it does what it is like. The preceding remark is the
+metametamathematical description, or definition, of the system.
+
+\subsection{Epilogue}
+
+Ever since Carnap's Principle of Tolerance opened the floodgates to
+arbitrariness in mathematics, we have been faced with the prospect of a
+mathematics which is indistinguishable from art-for-art's-sake, or
+amusement-for-amusement's-sake. But there is one characteristic which saves
+mathematics from this fate. Mathematics originated by abstraction from
+primitive technology, and is indispensable to science and technology---in
+short, mathematics has scientific applications. The experience of group
+theory has proved, I hope once and for all, the bankruptcy of that narrow
+practicality which would limit mathematics to what can currently be applied
+in science. But now that mathematics is wide open, and anything goes, we
+should be aware more than ever that scientific applicability is the only
+objective value that mathematics has. I would not have set down constructed
+memory theory and the post-formalist systems if I did not believe that they
+could be applied. When and how they will be is another matter.
+
+And what about the "validity" of formalism? The rise of the formalist
+position is certainly understandable. The formalists had a commendable,
+rationalistic desire to eliminate the metaphysical problems associated with
+mathematics. Moreover, formalism helped stimulate the development of the
+logic needed in computer technology (and also to stimulate this paper). In
+spite of the productiveness of the formalist position, however, it now seems
+beyond dispute that formalism has failed to achieve its original goals. (My
+pure philosophical writings are the last word on this issue.) Perhaps the main
+lesson to be learned from the history of formalism is that an idea does not
+have to be "true" to be productive.
+
+
+\section*{Note}
+Early versions of \textsc{"Illusions"} and \textsc{"Innperseqs"} appeared in my essay
+"Concept Art," published in An Anthology, ed. La Monte Young, New
+York, 1963. An early, July 1961 version of \textsc{"System Such That No One
+Knows What's Going On"} appeared in dimension 14, Ann Arbor, 1963,
+published by the University of Michigan College of Architecture and Design.
+