summaryrefslogtreecommitdiffstats
diff options
context:
space:
mode:
authorgrr <grr@lo2.org>2024-05-25 02:02:06 -0400
committergrr <grr@lo2.org>2024-05-25 02:02:06 -0400
commitcd002748f43964aa7c38222c95370faae64212d1 (patch)
tree8d845cadd95cc965fe7f65c16541ab67f64d26ff
parent38f418e0b206b372b9dafeecc6536f574eb502ea (diff)
downloadblueprint-cd002748f43964aa7c38222c95370faae64212d1.tar.gz
change usage of math mode
-rw-r--r--essays/post_formalism_memories.tex36
1 files changed, 18 insertions, 18 deletions
diff --git a/essays/post_formalism_memories.tex b/essays/post_formalism_memories.tex
index 6f7d45b..6cf9b4d 100644
--- a/essays/post_formalism_memories.tex
+++ b/essays/post_formalism_memories.tex
@@ -185,7 +185,7 @@ Property 1 on the basis that one can control the associated ratio. Turning to
Property 4, it is normally the case that when an implication is repeated, a
given occurrence of one of the sentences involved is unique to a specific
occurrence of the implication. In \sysname{Illusions,} however, if two equal
-sentences are next smaller than X, the occurrence of X does not uniquely
+sentences are next smaller than $X$, the occurrence of $X$ does not uniquely
belong to either of the two occurrences of the implication. Compare figure \ref{thestructure},
where the occurrence of `$t$' is not unique to either occurrence of `$the$'.
Subject to this explanation, \sysname{Illusions} has Property 4. \sysname{Illusions} has
@@ -234,8 +234,8 @@ the following trivial formalist system.
\begin{sysrules}
A \term{sentence} is a member of a finite set of integers.
-Sentence Y is \term{implied by} sentence X if and only if Y=X, or else of all the
-sentences, Y is the one next smaller than X.
+Sentence $Y$ is \term{implied by} sentence $X$ if and only if $Y=X$, or else of all the
+sentences, $Y$ is the one next smaller than $X$.
Take as the \term{axiom} the largest sentence.
\end{sysrules}
@@ -412,19 +412,19 @@ In order to understand this section, it is necessary to be thoroughly
familiar with \essaytitle{Studies in Constructed Memories,} the essay following this
one. (I have not combined the two essays because their approaches are too
different.) I will define post-formalist systems in constructed memories,
-beginning with a system in an $M^*$-Memory.
+beginning with a system in an M*-Memory.\editornote{The term M*-Memory is defined on page \pageref{mstardef}.}
\midheading{\enquote{Dream Amalgams}}
\begin{sysrules}
-A \term{sentence} is a possible method, an $A_{a_i}$. with respect to an $M^*$-Memory.
+A \term{sentence} is a possible method, an $A_{a_i}$. with respect to an M*-Memory.
The sentence $A_{a_p}$ \enquote{\term{implies}} the sentence $A_{a_q}$ if and only if the $a_q$th
-$M^*$-assertion is actually thought; and either $A_{a_q} = A_{a_p}$, or else there is
+M*-assertion is actually thought; and either $A_{a_q} = A_{a_p}$, or else there is
cross-method contact of a mental state in $A_{a_q}$ with a state in $A_{a_p}$.
The \term{axioms} must be chosen from sentences which satisfy two conditions.
The mental states in the sentences must have cross-method contact
-with mental states in other sentences. And the $M^*$-assertions
+with mental states in other sentences. And the M*-assertions
corresponding to the sentences must not be thought.
\emph{Explanation}: As \essaytitle{Studies in Constructed Memories} says, there can be
@@ -442,8 +442,8 @@ $\ulcorner\phi\supset\varphi\urcorner$ may not be. Now implication is also
directed in \sysname{Dream Amalgams,} but for a very different reason.
Cross-method contact, unlike the conditional, has a symmetric character.
What prevents implication from being necessarily symmetrical is that the
-implicand's $M^*$-assertion actually has to be thought, while the implior's
-$M^*$-assertion does not. Thus, implication is both subjective and mechanical,
+implicand's M*-assertion actually has to be thought, while the implior's
+M*-assertion does not. Thus, implication is both subjective and mechanical,
it is subjective, in that it is a matter of volition which method is remembered
to have actually: been used. It is mechanical, in that when one is
remembering, one is automatically aware of the cross-method contacts of
@@ -451,15 +451,15 @@ states in $A_{a_q}$. The conditions on the axioms ensure that they will have
implications without losing Property 7.
As for compound implication in \sysname{Dream Amalgams,} the organism
-with the $M^*$-Memory can't be aware of it at all; because it can't be aware
+with the M*-Memory can't be aware of it at all; because it can't be aware
that at different times it remembered different methods to be the one
actually used. (In fact, the organism cannot be aware that the system has
Property 5, for the same reason.) On the other hand, to an outside observer
-of the $M^*$-Memory, indirect implication is not only thinkable but
+of the M*-Memory, indirect implication is not only thinkable but
mechanical. It is not superfluous because cross-method contact of mental
states is not necessarily transitive. The outside observer can decide whether a
sentence is a theorem by the following mechanical procedure. Check
-whether the sentence's $M^*$-assertion has acually been thought; if so, check all
+whether the sentence's M*-assertion has acually been thought; if so, check all
sentences which imply it to see if any are axioms; if not, check all the
sentences which imply the sentences which imply it to see if any are axioms;
etc. The number of possible methods is given as finite, so the procedure is
@@ -503,8 +503,8 @@ infall.
\midheading{\enquote{Infalls}}
\begin{sysrules}
- A \term{sentence} is a $D$-sentence, in a D-Memory such that $event_{j+1}$ is the first
-thinking of the $j$th $D$-sentence, for all $j$.
+ A \term{sentence} is a D-sentence, in a D-Memory such that $event_{j+1}$ is the first
+thinking of the $j$th D-sentence, for all $j$.
Two sentences \enquote{imply} another if and only if all three are the same; or else
the three are adjacent (and can be written $S_{j+1},S_j,S_{j-1}$), and are such
@@ -522,12 +522,12 @@ thinking of $S^{D}_{j-1}$, ended at a distance $z_j$ into the past, where $z_j$
\label{infallsdiag}
\end{figure}
-In this variety of $D$-Memory, the organism continuously thinks successive
-$D$-sentences, which are all different, just as the reader of the above exercise
+In this variety of D-Memory, the organism continuously thinks successive
+D-sentences, which are all different, just as the reader of the above exercise
continuously reads successive and different sentences. Thus, the possibility
of repeating a sentence depends on the possibility of thinking it while one is
thinking another sentence---a possibility which may be far-fetched, but which
-is not explicitly excluded by the definition of a \enquote{$D$-Memory.} If the
+is not explicitly excluded by the definition of a \enquote{D-Memory.} If the
possibility is granted, then \sysname{Infalls} has Properties 1--5. Direct implication is
completely mechanical; it is subjective only in that the involuntary
determination of the $z_j$ and other aspects of the memory is a \enquote{subjective}
@@ -541,7 +541,7 @@ object or system. Such systems have no descriptive syntax. Imaginary objects
were introduced into mathematics, or at least into geometry, by Nicholas
Lobachevski, and now I am using them as a notation. For these systems to
be nonisomorphic to any ink-on-paper systems, the mathematician must be
-the organism with the $M^*$-Memory or the $D$-Memory. But this means that
+the organism with the M*-Memory or the D-Memory. But this means that
in this case, the mathematics which is nonisomorphic to any ink-on-paper
system can be performed only in an imaginary mind.