summaryrefslogtreecommitdiffstats
diff options
context:
space:
mode:
-rw-r--r--plato_time_notes.otx1993
1 files changed, 141 insertions, 1852 deletions
diff --git a/plato_time_notes.otx b/plato_time_notes.otx
index dab4d07..f8c8f26 100644
--- a/plato_time_notes.otx
+++ b/plato_time_notes.otx
@@ -1,1891 +1,180 @@
% chapter i
-\defpnote{1.1}{A.N. Whitehead, \bt{Process and Reality}
-(New York: The Macmillan Company, 1941), p. 63.}
-
-{2}{W.H. Walsh,
-\et{Plato and the Philosophy of History: History and Theory in the Republic,}
- \jt{History and Theory}
-(The Hague: Mouton \& Co., 1962), II, 1, pp. 1--16.}
-
-{3}{K.R. Popper,
-\bt{The Open Society and its Enemies}
-(2 vols.; 2\tss{nd} ed. rev.; London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1952).}
-
-{4}{Walsh, op. cit., p. 6.}
-
-{5}{See, for example. R.L. Nettleship,
+\defpnote{0.1}{A.N. Whitehead, \bt{Process and Reality}
+ (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1941), p. 63.}
+\defpnote{0,2}{W.H. Walsh,
+ \et{Plato and the Philosophy of History: History and Theory in the Republic,}
+ \jt{History and Theory}
+ (The Hague: Mouton \& Co., 1962), II, 1, pp. 1--16.}
+\defpnote{0.3}{K.R. Popper,
+ \bt{The Open Society and its Enemies}
+ (2 vols.; 2\tss{nd} ed. rev.; London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1952).}
+\defpnote{0.4}{Walsh, op. cit., p. 6.}
+\defpnote{0.5}{See, for example. R.L. Nettleship,
\bt{Lectures on the Republic of Plato }
(New York: The Macmillan Company,
1955), and E. Barker,
\bt{Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle}
(New York: Dover Publications, Imnc., 1959).
Both of these authors make slight reference to the \bt{Timaeus} while discussing Plato's \dq{Political Philosophy.}}
-
-{1.6}{R.G. Bury,
+\defpnote{0.6}{R.G. Bury,
\et{Plato and History,}
\jt{Classical Quarterly,}
New Series, 1--2, pp. 86--94.}
-
-{1.7}{Edward MacKinnon, S.J.,
+\defpnote{0.7}{Edward MacKinnon, S.J.,
\et{Time in Contemporary Physics,}
\jt{International Philosophical Quarterly,}
II, 3, (September, 1962), p. 429.}
-
-{0.8}{Hermann Gauss,
+\defpnote{0.8}{Hermann Gauss,
\bt{Philosophischer Handkommentar zu den Dialogen Platos},
vol. III part 2 (Bern: Herbart Lang, 1961)}
-
-{0.9}{Bertrand Russell,
+\defpnote{0.9}{Bertrand Russell,
\bt{Mysticism and Logic}
(Garden City, New York: Doubleday \& Co., 1917). }
-
-{0.10}{Whitehead, loc, cit.}
-
-{0.11}{Werner Heisenberg,
+\defpnote{0.10}{Whitehead, loc, cit.}
+\defpnote{0.11}{Werner Heisenberg,
\bt{Physics and Philosophy}
(New York: Harper \& Brothers, 1955), ch. 4.}
-
-{0.12}{See, for example. F.M. Cornford,
+\defpnote{0.12}{See, for example. F.M. Cornford,
\bt{From Religion to Philosophy}
(New York: Harper \& Brothers, 1957).}
-
-{0.13}{F.M. Cornford,
+\defpnote{0.13}{F.M. Cornford,
\bt{Plato's Cosmology},
(London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, Ltd., 1937), p. 8.}
-
-{0.14}{Carl G. Hempel,
+\defpnote{0.14}{Carl G. Hempel,
\et{Fundamentals of Concept Formation in Empirical Science,}
\bt{International Encyclopaedia of Unified Science},
vols. I and IT;
\ul{Foundations of the Unity of Science}
vol. II, no. 7 (University of Chicago Press, 1952)}
-
-{0.15}{Hans Meyerhoff, ed.,
+\defpnote{0.15}{Hans Meyerhoff, ed.,
\bt{The Philosophy of History in Our Time}
(New York: Doubleday \& Co., 1959),
which contains a valuable anthology of the important authors in this field and some of their most representative views.}
% chapter ii
-CHAPTER IT
-THE ORDER OF THE DIALOGUES
-
-
-In the first chapter, it was stated that an attempt
-will be made in this study to verify the hypothesis that
-the Timaeus is a late dialogue in which Plato significantly
-
-
-reformulates his earlier doctrines of eternity, image, and
-time. It was stated that the hypothesis was to be investigated by dividing it into two logically interrelated
-aspects; first, the order of the dialogues will be
-established and their relative chronology will be documented;
-second, the doctrines of the late dialogues will be
-
-traced insofar as they develop the tripartite theme ofr
-eternity, image, and time.
-
-It was said that the first aspect relied upon
-criteria which demand an interpretation of the significance
-of Plato's style, and that the second aspect depends on an
-interpretation of Plato's thought. In this chapter, the
-criteria which do not depend on an interpretation of
-Plato's thought will be discussed. This chapter assumes
-that some knowledge of the order or Plato's dialogues is
-needed in order to interpret them intelligently, and so
-the chapter which discusses how the scholars established
-this order precedes the chapter which discusses Platonic
-doctrine. :
-
-It should be stated at the outset that one cannot
-
-
-simply assume that a dialogue which was composed later
-
-
-
-
-
-than another is therefore necessarily a more mature work.
-This is precisely what must be demonstrated. In this
-chapter, the chronology of the dialogues is ascertained
-insofar as this is possible by citing the conclusions of
-those scholars who have specialized in the use of stylistic criteria. If one establishes the chronological
-order of composition there is a valid presumption that
-it also representa some sort of development in doctrine.
-If, then, one shows in addition that the doctrines
-developed follow an ascending order of reflection, the
-point is made. 'thus, the arguments are not independent
-of each other.
-
-If it can be shown that there is a development of
-doctrine which can be traced through the late dialogues,
-then it can be shown that this progression facilitates
-
-
-comprehension of the doctrine of the Timaeus. More
-
-
-specifically, the themes of eternity, image, and time
-
-can be traced through the late dialogues only after one
-knows which dialogues are late and in what order they
-should be read. Thus the chronology of the dialogues
-
-and the progression of doctrine are not separate items but
-logically interrelated aspects of a larger argument.
-
-It would be possible to postulate an order for the
-dialogues which would support the view that the doctrine
-of the Timaeus is a culmination, and each scholar could
-do this without reference to non-interpretative criteria.
-
-
-'But, in this way, so many different postulates would ensue
-
-
-
-that it would become impossible for scholars to reach any
-agreement among themselves. This in fact is what happened
-when doctrinal criteria alone were used, and it resulted
-in such widespread disagreement that a need for some sort
-of non-interpretative criteria by which to establish the
-sequence of the dialogues was finally perceived. Further,
-the reliance on interpretative criteria alone and the
-subsequent differences in the alleged order could support
-the conclusion that the relation of the dialogues to each
-other had no bearing on their respective doctrines, since
-each scholar might postulate a different chronology. But
-Plato himself contradicted this view in those of his
-
-
-dialogues which refer to each other, as, for example, in
-
-
-the Timaeus, which refers to the Republic almost explicitly
-by repeating 'ciods doctrines of the HKepublic which are
-found nowhere else in those of Plato's written works which
-have come down to us.
-
-The proceedure followed in this chapter is as
-follows. Firat, the testimony of the ancients is adduced.
-then the efforts of scholars to use stylistic and Linguistic
-criteria are described. Then, biographical intormation
-about Plato's life and travels is recounted. Finally,
-Plato's own description of his life and his travels is
-presented. By drawing from each of these sources, one can
-compile a composite picture of the criteria by which the
-order of the dialogues can be established, without
-
-
-reference to an interpretation of Piato's thought. It will
-
-
-
-be shown that all of these sources lead to the conclusion
-that there is a group of dialogues which are later than
-others, and that the Timaeus is the latest of this group.
-
-
-In the next chapter, it will be shown that the doctrinal
-interpretation of these dialogues leads to a greater
-insight into the doctrine of the imaeus.
-
-
-I_The Traditional View
-Writing in his "Commentary," A.E. Taylor presents
-
-
-an impressive list of ancients who authenticate the Timaeus
-as Plato's work. He cites Aristotle's references to
-passages of the Timaeus and the fact that Aristotle refers
-to the Timaeus as a completed dialogue. In addition to
-reminding us that Aristotle may be presumed to know the
-works of his teacher, Taylor cites, in regard to the
-
-
-authenticity of the Timaeus, the testimony of Theophrastus,
-
-
-Plutarch, Chalcidius, Xenocrates, Crantor, Poseidonius,
-Procius, Plotinus, Boethius, Cicero, and Diogenes Laertius, !
-This list is offered against the view of Schelling, who
-contended that the Timaeus was spurious, and by it,
-
-taylor demonstrates that those who do not recognize the
-Timaeus as authentic are in the decided minority. There is
-little need to recapitulate all of the scholarship on each
-of these authors’ claims and it is certainly sate to regard
-
-
-Taylor's scholarship in these matters as impeccable.
-
-
-. ' avs. Taylor, commenter on Plato's iimaeus
-(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1928), pe. 4.
-
-
-te
-
-
-To this List, Cornfrord adds the names of Galen,
-Theon, Derclydes, and Adrastus, who not only knew the
-Zimaeug to be Plato's own but in addition agreed that it
-was the work of Plato's maturity. Summing up his own
-argument, Cornford says, "All the ancient Platonists from
-Aristotle to Simplicius, all the medieval and modern
-scholars have assumed that this dialogue contains the
-mature doctrine of its author." Again it seems unnecessarv
-to repeat the details of Cornford's scholarship which may,
-like Taylor's, be regarded as impeccable. Both authors
-
-
-state that the ancients regarded the Timaeus as Plato's
-
-
-mature work.
-
-But the testimony of the ancients is hardly sufficient
-to establish beyond doubt that the Timaeus is both Plato's
-work, and, in addition, a work of Plato's old age. Citing
-the ancients lends a great deal of support to the claim
-
-
-that the Timaeus is authentic, but the claim that it is a
-
-
-late work bears closer scrutiny. This is especially true
-in view of the fact that, at one time, a lively controversy
-
-
-with regard to the alleged maturity of the Timaeus took
-
-
-place among the scholars.
-
-Between the time of the ancients and the moderns,
-the Timaeug was not unknown. Jaeger presents a short and
-terse history of the Timaeus in the middle ages. Beginning
-
-
-2 ¥F.M. Cornford, Plato's Cosmology, p. viii.
-
-
-
-
-
-with the fact that Plato's Timaeus deeply influenced
-
-
-Augustine, and through Augustine, the whole of the middle
-ages, and continuing through the Renaissance by way of the
-Byzantine theologian and mystic Gemistos Plethon, who
-brought Plato to the Quattrocento, Jaeger also describes
-the treatment Plato received at the academy of the Medicis,
-
-
-where Marsilius Ficinus taught from the text of the
-
-
-Timaeug."
-
-
-Jaeger notes a change in the eighteenth century,
-when Schleiermacher seems to have resuscitated a Plato who
-was nonetheless very much alive. However, theretofore,
-Plato had been regarded as a mystic and as a theologian
-whose doctrine was as systematic and systematized as the
-Aristotelianism of the Schoolmen. Plato was regarded only
-as the author of the theory of ideas."
-
-According to Jaeger, it was Schleierzacher's
-contention that the form which a philosophy took was a
-creative expression of the philosopher's individuality,
-and it was Plato's genius, he thought, to dramatize, and to
-
-
-use philosophy as a "continuous philosophical discussion
-
-
-aimed at discovering the truth. ">
-
-
-> Werner Jaeger, Paideia: The Ideals of Greek
-Culture (3vols.; New York: Oxford University Press,
-1943), II, pp. 77, 78.
-
-4 Ibid., p. 78.
-
-
-> Ibid., p. 79.
-
-
-
-
-Immediately after Schleiermacher's view became
-known, there followed a period during which the philological investigation of every last minute hypothesis of
-Plato's was undertaken with the painstakingly precise
-attention for which philologists are deservedly famous.
-However, it soon became evident that the forest was being
-obscured by the trees.
-
-
-It remained for C.F. Hermann®
-
-
-to regard the problems
-of authenticating not only the authorship but the chronology of Plato's dialogues as of paramount importance, and
-Jaeger tells us that Hermann came to regard the dialogues
-as "stages in the gradual development of Plato's philosophy."? Thus Hermann brought "into the center of interest
-@\& problem which had hitherto been little considered, and
-gave it much greater importance. This was the problem of
-the dates at which the several dialogues had been written, "8
-Since various authors developed differing opinions on the
-dating of the dialogues by using doctrinal criteria alone,
-4t was the task of philology and researches into stylistic
-
-
-differences and minute characteristics of language to fix
-
-
-the date of composition as exactly as possible.
-
-
-© o.F. Hermann, Geschichte und 8 m der
-Platonischen Phil EOUONTy 1e30), in Jaeger,
-oS ae Pe 79.
-
-T Jaeger, Op, cite, p. 79.
-
-5 tpad., p. 80.
-
-
-
-II The Stylistic Controversy |
-
-T. Gomperz presents an entire chapter on the question
-of the authenticity and order of Plato's dialogues.? He
-makes a good summary of some of the chief difficulties to
-be encountered in an evaluation of the results of the whole
-stylistic controversy, and gives evidence of how and to
-what extent the whole question has been settled,
-
-He begins with a tantalizing supposition: suppose
-Speusippus had sat down one afternoon, and, in fifteen
-minutes, written on a scrap of paper the order of the
-Platonic dialogues. But, of course, Speusippus did no such
-thing, nor did anyone else, so that the scholars were left
-with the need to know the order of the dialogues, but,
-also, they were left with a need to construct methods of
-establishing the chronology, with no hints from Plato or
-the Academy as to which methods would prove the most
-fruitful, 1°
-
-Initially, each man interpreted the dialogues in
-what he felt was the logical order of Platonic philosophy.
-But this produced almost as many logical orders as there
-were interpreters.
-
-According to Gomperz (and others, including Jaeger)
-
-
-it was Schleiermacher who first attempted to find his own
-
-
-9 Theodor Gomperz, eyock thinkers, trans. G.G. Berry
-(London: John Murray, 1905).
-
-
-10 Ipad., pe 275.
-
-
-
-way out of this myriad of opinions. By viewing Plato's
-doctrine developmentally, and, starting with Aristotle's
-guarantees as to certain authentic passages and chronologies, he set about constructing an orderly arrangement of
-the dialogues. However, this attempt got off to a wrong
-start because, since only approximately half of Aristotle's
-works are extent, it became possible for some to construct
-what was called the argument from silence, i.e., those
-works of Plato which Aristotle did not mention might be
-regarded as spurious. !! Gomperz points out that this was
-really an excess of Platonic zeal since it included only
-those works which Aristotle claimed were Plato's best. '*
-Notwithstanding these efforts, Gomperz states that
-
-
-even in ancient tradition, the Laws were regarded as Plato's
-
-
-last work. Campbell then perceived that there were
-stylistic similarities between the Laws and the Timaeus
-and the Critias, including the fact that some 1500 words
-were used in these works which do not appear in any of
-Plato's earlier works.!> In addition, these works appear
-last on the list of Plato's works which was kept by
-Aristophanes of Byzantium, the Librarian of Alexandria.
-
-
-But these are not final criteria. Gomperz asks "...is not
-
-
-11 Ibid., p. 278.
-
-
-12 Ipad.
-15 Ipaa., pp. 279, 283.
-
-
-
-an author's 'advance,’ his progress towards perfection
-the surest criterion for the chronological arrangement of
-his works"? He answers his own question in the affirmative,
-but reminds us that this road leads to diverse and varied
-interpretations of "advance," because there are so many
-possible meanings for this tern. '*
-
-For these reasons, the stylistic methods were tried.
-Describing them as "linguistic...and verbal statistics, "!5
-Gomperz lists some of the criteria employed:
-
-@. number and use of particles
-
-b. new words and phrases
-
-c. certain formulae of affirmation and negation
-
-d. special superlatives !©
-
-He goes on to say that the use of these criteria
-produced "astonishing agreement between many different
-
-
-investigators."!7 They noted that the style of the Laws,
-
-
-known to be late, (from other sources) was very similar to
-the style of the Timaeus, Critias, Sophist, Statesman, and
-the Philebus.
-
-
-He concludes:
-
-
-The determination of the chronologically separate
-
-
-14 Ipda., p. 284.
-'5 Ipaa., p. 285.
-16 psa,
-
-17 Ibid., p. 286.
-
-
-
-
-groups and the distribution among these groups
-
-of the {individual dialogues...are problems
-
-which may be regarded as finally solved; the
-
-more ambitious task of settling the chronological
-
-order within all the groups cannot yet be said to
-
-have been completed. !
-
-However, Jaeger claimed,
-
-This method, in its turn, was at first successful;
-but it was later discredited by its own exaggerations. It actually undertook, by the purely
-mechanical application of language tables, to
-determine the exact date of every dialogue.19
-
-Before entering into this lively controversy, it is
-necessary to distinguish a few crucial points; otherwise,
-Jaeger's claim that the movement discredited itself will not
-be intelligible. First, let it be noted that it 1s sometimes impossible to distinguish very well between the
-date of composition of a dialogue, that is, the period of
-time during which Plato is said to have actually written
-down his thoughts, and the date at which the dialogue
-appeared, that is, was circulated, and, as we should say,
-released for publication. Although it is sometimes possible
-to indicate that a dialogue was actually composed in the
-late period of Plato's life, one cannot simply equate a
-late doctrine and a late writing. This distinction is
-necessary if one is to assert that the doctrine of the
-Timaeyus is a late formulation in Plato's life, and, as our
-documentation will attempt to indicate, both the formulation
-
-
-of doctrine and the actual composition of the Jimacus seem
-
-
-~ Ibid., p. 287. 19 Jaeger, loce cit.
-
-
-
-
-
-to be very late, according to the sources available to us.
-But one cannot jump immediately from the conclusion that a
-dialogue was written late to the conclusion that its
-doctrine is therefore, on that basis alone, a late doctrine.
-It should be pointed out in this regard that we have no
-
-way of knowing whether Plato did or did not compose in the
-last years of his life, dialogues whose doctrine and style
-we should call early or middle doctrines. Like anyone else,
-he might incorporate in late writing what he had formulated
-much earlier. Although it is unlikely that Plato set early
-or middle doctrines down on paper in his late years, it is
-aimost impossible to establish this unlikelihood to a
-degree of satisfaction which would entirely eliminate
-controversy. For example, the last few pages of the Philebus
-seem not to be in the same style or in the doctrinal spirit
-as the rest of the dialogue. It may well be that this
-dialogue was left unfinished by Plato, and was completed by
-the Academy after Plato's death, and that the completion
-was accomplished by an academician whose insight and
-doctrinal leaning corresponds to what we should call the
-middle period of Plato's philosophy.
-
-However, in the instance of the imaeus, it is claimed
-here that both the doctrine and the composition of the
-dialogue are to be placed in the last years of Plato's
-life, and that it was probably a late doctrine, because it
-
-
-was composed late. These are the two sides or halves of the
-
-
-ks
-
-
-
-argument which we are following in the attempt to verify
-our hypothesis. On the one hand, if the dialogue was
-written late, we have probable grounds to infer that ite
-doctrine is a late one. But it is unwise to conclude only
-from its late composition that the Timaeus contains a late
-view. In addition to establishing its date of composition
-one must examine its doctrine, to see whether it reveals a
-more developed form of Plato's later thought. Having made
-this distinction, it is now possible to pass in review
-the main points of the stylistic controversy, whose
-protaganists and antagonists tried by what we are calling
-non-interpretative criteria, to establish the late date of
-composition of the Timaeus.
-
-Campbe112° presents a brief outline of the history
-of attempts to date the dialogues. He recounts how
-Schleiermacher was so assured that Plato had a complete
-system of philosophy to expound that there must have been
-a pedagogical order of the dialogues which Plato intended
-so that his students could gradually master his philosophical
-systen.
-
-Campbell says that Schleiermacher's conception of a
-"complete system gradually revealed" was a stirring one
-
-
-which caused a renaissance of Platonic scholarship. Later,
-
-
-20 L. Campbell, "Plato," Encyclopaedia britannica,
-llth ed., Vol. XXI, pp. 808-824.
-
-
-
-
-
-C.F. Hermann's statement that the gradual development of
-Plato's thought in the dialogues was not a pedagogical
-gradualism but reflected the slow maturation and development of Plato's mind, brought about a quickening of
-interest beyond even that which Schleilermacher had precipitated. Ueberweg discerned that the Sophist and the
-Statesman must be placed between the Republic and the Laws
-
-
-on the basis of Hermann's view. Ueberweg and other Hegelians
-felt that the non-being of the Sophist represented a
-dialectical advance over the Republic and welcomed the
-chance to demonstrate this point of view by mapping out
-
-the dialogues in a series of dialectical advances, -! Grote,
-on the other hand felt so strongly that the Protagoras was
-Plato's most mature doctrine that he discounted the
-chronological attempts of Schleiermacher, Hermann, and
-Ueberweg.
-
-Campbell adopted a different method of reasoning.
-Starting with the conclusion that the Laws remained
-unedited because Plato died before he could do so himself,
-and noting that the Laws contains a reference to the death
-of Dionysius Il, and inferring from the tone and style of
-the Laws that it is almost a monologue and represents a
-departure from the Socratic dialogues, and adding the
-agreement of the Ancients with his own view, Campbell
-
-
-21 Ipid., p. 810.
-
-
-
-'concluded that the Laws is probably the last of Plato's
-
-
-works. Then, Campbell reasoned that both the Timaeus and
-
-
-the Critias presuppose the Republic, and both resemble
-
-
-the Laws in style and tone. Thus they should both precede
-the Laws. Since the Sophist and the Statesman seem to
-
-
-belong together, he placed the Philebus between them and
-the Timaeus and Critias. So, Campbell concluded, the order
-
-
-of the late dialogues must be begun at the Sophist, and
-followed by the Statesman, Philebus, Timaeus, Critias, and
-
-
-Laws. ° He says, in addition, that Dittenberger and Ritter
-followed him in taking this view, and that Lutoslawski
-later reached the same conclusions. —> Jaeger says that he
-himself reached these same conclusions by another route.
-
-
-He also agreed with Campbell that the Parmenides, and
-
-
-Theatetus immediately precede the Sophist.
-
-
-It should be pointed out that Campbell's chain of
-reasoning depends on the placement of the Laws as the last
-of the dialog'es, and this placement does not rest
-exclusively on non-interpretative bases, since it includes
-the criterion of the tone and style of Plato's language.
-One must have at least a comprehension of the tones and
-styles of the language in which Plato wrote and some
-
-
-knowledge of the relation of style to the content which
-
-
-22 Ipig.
-23 Ip4a.
-
-
-
-is expressed by language. To avoid confusion, it is
-necessary to define certain terms as they are employed in
-this study. By stylistic criteria, I mean the use made by
-reputable scholars of observations such as the presence
-or absence of Socrates in a dialogue, or the apparent
-attempt on Plato's part to have his passage read more
-smoothly and without unnecessary interruptions. Such
-devices as the avoidance of hiatus and the use of
-anacoluthic sentence endings are here called stylistic.
-The term stylometry refers to the application of statistical procedures to the number of particles in a paragraph,
-or to the frequency of certain words in one dialogue as
-against another; clearly, it carries metric connotations,
-and necessitates only the sort of competence which can
-easily be programmed into a computer. Whereas the stylistic
-reader must understand what he reads, the stylometric
-reader ought to avoid understanding the passage he
-subjects to statistical criteria. A similar difference
-could be found between counting a number of unknown
-objects, which, by analogy, would represent the stylometric method, and concluding that the objects so counted
-are a strange lot of objects, which be analogy, would
-represent the stylistic method. It is one thing to count
-the number of clausulae and quite another to notice that a
-passage reads more smoothly because of the presence of a
-number of clausulae. Thus objections to the use of stylometric scholarship need not carry equal weight if referred |
-
-
-
-to stylistic scholarship. It would be impossible, for
-example, to put words of the Laws into a computer and
-
-
-arrive at the conclusion that the Laws 1s a late dialogue,
-
-
-without at the same time programming into the computer the
-criteria according to which one says that a certain
-language style is late or early. There are similar studies
-concerning the language of Homer in progress at Columbia
-University, and there too, the criteria of "lateness"
-must be agreed upon before the "purely mechanical application of language tables to determine the exact date of
-every dialogue" is undertaken. Thus, Campbell's argument
-should read as follows; if the Laws is agreed to be last,
-then the remainder follows on stylistic grounds. And it
-should be tallied against Jaeger that the placement of the
-Laws as last does not rest on "purely mechanical" criteria.
-This conclusion bears directly on the question of
-
-
-the chronology and the relation of the Seventh Letter to
-
-
-the Timaeus, because the Seventh Letter contains a
-
-
-description of certain events in Sicilian politics in which,
-Plato was directly involved. These events were significant
-experiences for Plato, and their impress is discernible
-
-in certain passages of the Timaeus. Detailed comment on the
-impact of the Sicilian journeys on the doctrine of the
-Timaeus will be reserved for the discussion of the
-
-doctrine of the-Timaeus in the fourth chapter. Suffice
-
-4t here to point out that the autobiographical material
-Which the Seventh Letter makes available was taken over
-
-
-= 40
-by the stylists,-" 25 and added to their attempts to :
-establish the order of the avavoedee: Again, this shows
-that the stylistic criteria cannot be viewed as "purely
-machanical." On the one hand this limite the extent to
-which stylistic criteria may be said to be non-interpretative; on the other hand, since interpretative sources
-enter into stylistic researches, it seems to add to the
-reliability of stylistic criteria in establishing the
-order of the dialogues.
-
-A.E. Taylor says that the real impetus for the
-
-
-stylometric method was received from Campbell's groundbreaking edition of the Sophist and Statesman, and that
-
-
-Dittenberger, Ritter, and Lutoslawski continued and
-extended Campbell's efforts, but, he adds, these scholars
-were able to agree further that there was a definite break
-in style between the Theatetus and the whole group of
-dialogues Which Campbell had called the late group. However, Taylor says that the stylometric tabulations, while
-they could establish whole groups of dialogues which
-shared a style, could not effectively establish the order
-
-
-of dialogues within a given group. °°
-
-
-24 U.v. Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Platon,I (2d ed.;
-Berlin: Weidman, 1920), in Jaeger, op, cit., p. 80.
-
-
-25 Jaeger, Op. cit., p. 84.
-
-26 A.E. Taylor, "Plato," Encyclopaedia Britannica,
-agar (Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc., 1957),
-pe 49.
-
-
-Le
-
-
-Af
-It is interesting to follow A.E. Taylor's shifting
-
-emphasis and reliance on the stylistic researches. In the
-
-article which he wrote for the Britannica, ! Taylor says
-
-
-there are no stylistic grounds for placing the Timaeus
-
-
-late in the order of Plato's dialogues. However, in the
-Commentary on the Timaeus, -° there is a rather extensive
-description of the stylistic and stylometric criteria and
-@ rather extensive reliance on both of them, albeit
-accompanied by a critique. Later, in Plato, the Man and
-his Work, "2 there is a recapitulation of the stylistic
-criteria and a somewhat limited reliance upon them. One
-can only conclude that Taylor did not deem it worthwhile
-to inform the readers of the Britannica on the intricasies
-of the stylistic controversy. Nevertheless, in all these
-works, Taylor concludes that the Timaeus is the work of
-Plato's last years.
-
-It is informative therefore, to read Taylor's
-description of the satylistic criteria. He summarizes those
-used to establish the late group as follows:
-
-1. @ reduction of dramatic style
-
-2. a lesser role for Socrates
-
-
-3. the presence of a lecture
-
-
-27 Ipid.
-28 A.E. Taylor, Commentary, p. 4.
-
-
-29 alm Taylor, Plato: The Man and His Work (6th
-ed.;3 Aa print.; New York: Meridian Books, Inc., 1959),
-(Pe 436.
-
-
-
-
-4, periodic versus poetic style-0
-He says, in addition, that the last dialogue which bears
-the marks of Plato's earlier style must be the Theatetus,
-and that he shares this view with Ritter"! and
-Lutoslawek1.>*
-
-A.E. Taylor's recapitulation of the stylistic
-criteria is especially interesting in view of the fact
-that he follows Burnet rather carefully, and yet Burnet
-states, "I have ventured to assume the results of the
-stylistic researches inaugurated by Lewis Campbell in
-1867.""2 It is also interesting to note that Burnet, like
-taylor, refers to these researches as stylistic and not
-stylometric, which indicates that he is not willing to go
-so far as Lutoslawski's application of calculus to the
-frequency of hiatus and the use of clausulae in Plato's
-aQialogues. On the other hand, Burnet himself makes use of
-"stylistic" arguments when he notes that the early dialogues
-make use of dramatic form and employ the person ot Socrates
-
-
-centrally in that endeavor, whereas the later dialogues do
-
-
-30 A.E. Taylor, Commentary, pe 4.
-
-
-
-Constantin Ritter, The Essence of Plato's
-EnLiceophy, trans. Adam Alles (London: George Allen \&
-Unwin, Ltd., 1933).
-
-
-32 W. Lutoslawski, Origi ad Growth of Plato's
-Logig (New York: Longmans, rooey.
-
-
-33 John Burnet, Greek Philosophy (London: Macmillan
-\& Co., Ltd., 1914), Part I, p. 212.
-
-
-
-80 with less and less emphasis on drama and on Socrates’
-interlocutory role. On this basis Burnet too concludes
-that the Timaeus is the work of Plato's old age, but
-
-
-reserves decision as to whether the Philebus precedes it or
-
-
-not.
-
-It 18 frequently recognized that Burnet, A.E. Taylor
-and Cornford collectively form something of a school, and
-so it is appropriate to take Cornford's remarks on the
-order of the dialogues into account. This is especially
-
-
-true since his translation of the Timaeus is the most
-
-
-recent and constitutes a valuable synthesis of scholarly
-efforts to understand this dialogue.
-
-In his Plato's Cosmology Cornford discusses the
-dating of the Timaeug but makes only peripheral reference
-to the stylistic criteria.-* He cites Wilamowitz 35 to the
-effect that Timaeus speaks with an authoritative tone, and
-makes little use of the gently poetic questionings of
-Socrates. Cornford also cites Ritter to the effect that
-the fourth person of the Timaeys is left unknown, perhaps
-because Plato wanted to keep open the possibility of writing a fourth dialogue in the series. ©
-
-
-34 Gornford, op, cit.
-
-
-35 Wilamowitz, Platon, I, p. 591, in Jaeger,
-Op. cit., pe sO.
-
-
-36 Constantin Ritter, Neve Untersuchungen uber
-Platon (Munich: 1910), p. 181.
-
-
-
-But Cornford, like Burnet and unlike A.E. taylor, makes
-little mention of the whole matter of stylistic dating.
-He assumes the results of the stylists but prefers to place
-
-
-the Timaeus and Critias just before the Laws for reasons of
-
-
-doctrine rather than for reasons of style.
-
-Ritter says that he learned most "from the English,"
-meaning Burnet, Taylor, and Cornford, and that his own
-researches brought him into "remarkably close agreement...
-with respect to their chronological determinations."-/
-Briefly, his conclusions are theses there are six major
-groupings of dialogues, and the last group, composed of
-the Sophist, Statesman, Timaeus, Critias, Philebus, and
-
-
-Laws, must be late because a "careful study of the differences in language and expression" creates an "indubitable
-means of determining their genuineness as well as the
-approximate date of their appearance." >° In addition, he
-says that there are changes in style and writing which
-are less precise but no less observable by the trained
-observer, and that perhaps the strongest of these
-considerations is the transition from the "poetic" style
-in the early works to the "didactic" style of the later
-
-
-works.-? It 18 interesting to observe that when Zeller
-
-
-3T Ritter, The Essence of Plato's Philosophy, p. 9.
-38 tpia., pe 27.
-39 tpid., pp. 29, 30.
-
-
-
-challenged Ritter to try the stylistic methods on a 7
-modern writer's works, whose chronology could be independantty verified, Ritter was able to arrive at the correct
-chronology of the works of Goethe, 40
-
-Perhaps a summary of the stylistic controversy is
-
-in order at this point. "1 Briefly, it began with the
-efforts of Schleiermacher to reveal what he felt was the
-pedagogical gradualiem of Plato's dialogues. But Hermann
-felt that the gradual development in the dialogues revealed
-not Plato's pedagogical process so much as the gradual
-growth of Plato's own insight. Campbell started with the
-assertion that the Laws was the last work of Plato and
-noted stylistic similarities between the Laws and a whole
-group of dialogues, which included the Sophist, Statesman,
-Philebus, Timaeus, and Critias. Ritter modified the
-
-
-stylistic criteria and made them more precise, and arrived
-at astonishingly similar conclusions. In turn, Wilamowitz
-and Lutoslawski carried the work further (and perhaps to
-excess) by accomplishing stylometric word-counts and
-establishing frequency tables for the number of particles,
-clausulae, and hiatus. They too reached similar conclusions.
-
-
-It emerged that the comparison of styles of writing employed
-
-
-4 Ross has summerized these results in tabular
-form. See appendix A.
-
-
-by Plato in the dialogues could be used by several
-relatively independant scholars to reach agreement on the
-chronology of the dialogues, and, on this basis, it was
-
-
-agreed that the Timaeus was a work of Plato's old age,
-
-
-since the Timaeug and the Crjtias resembled the Laws, |
-
-
-more than any other work of Plato, in its style and
-composition. The researches of Burnet, Taylor, and Cornford
-assume these stylistic results and take them up into a
-
-more comprehensive view of the dialogues. This however
-
-
-does not alter their opinions that the Timaeus is the work
-
-
-of Plato's old age. Taylor and Burnet are uncertain whether
-
-
-the stylistic methods can place the Timaeus after the
-
-
-Philebus and conclude that if this is to be done it must
-
-
-be done on other grounds. More recent researchers have
-little or nothing to add to the stylistic probability that
-
-
-the Timaeus is the work of Plato's old age.
-
-
-The criteria used by these authors are said to be
-non-interpretative, insofar as they refer to the use of
-grammar, style, language devices such as expletives, hiatus,
-clausulae, etc. But other criteria, such as the death of
-Dionysius II, the decreasing importance of the role of
-Socrates in the various dialogues, do, to a certain extent,
-demand a degree of insight and interpretation of the style
-of the dialogues, and are used both as starting points for
-stylistic analyses and as parts of such analyses. They
-
-
-cannot be said to be purely mechanical, nor are they wholly
-
-
-
-objective, but their use by what Ritter calls "trained
-observers" has led to a remarkably wide and detailed
-agreement on the part of scholars to the effect that the
-Timaeug is the work of Plato's old age.
-
-Before we pass on to an examination of those details
-of Plato's biography which help to establish the sequence
-of the late dialogues, there is another point which
-deserves attention, and it is the matter of those dialogues
-which Zeller and Ritter call the "transitional dialogues, "
-
-
-namely the Parmenides and the Theatetus. It is necessary
-
-
-to note that a number of those scholars who have constructed
-chronologies of the dialogues have reached agreement that
-these two dialogues must be placed after the works of
-Plato's middle period, which include the Republic, and
-before the last period, which begins with the Sophist. In
-the next chapter, the doctrinal significance of this
-placement will become evident. It is necessary here only
-
-to document the assertion that reputable scholars have
-
-
-agreed to place the Parmenides and Theatetus immediately
-
-
-before the dialogues of the late period.
-III Biographical Criteria
-Up to this point, we have seen that there is a long
-
-
-and honorable tradition which regards the Timaeus as the
-
-
-work of Plato's old age, and that atylistic criteria, used
-by a small but highly reputable number of Platonic scholars,
-has brought about a condition of wide and detailed agreement that the Timaeus is Plato's work and that he wrote it
-
-
-i
-
-
-in his last few years
-
-To these sources, let us now add a review of those
-details of Plato's life which may be useful in determining
-the order of the dialogues. Again, so far as possible, the
-argument here will attempt to avoid any interpretations of
-Plato's thought, in keeping with the attempt to divide the
-evidence in favor of the nypotheale into two inseparable
-but logically discrete aspects.
-
-Unfortunately, the biographical information which
-we posess about Plato is painfully scant, since most of
-what we know about Plato's life has to be derived from the
-dialogues and the letters. The date of Plato's birth is
-usually said to be 427, although A.E, Taylor gives 428.
-Similarly, the date of Plato's death is usually given as
-347 but A.E. Taylor gives 348. All agree that these dates
-are approximate. The concensus seems to be that Plato was
-approximately eighty or eighty-one when he died.
-
-Plato was descended from an aristocratic family.
-His mother's first husband was Ariston who traced himself
-to Poseidon; her second husband was Pyrilampes, who
-related himself to Pericles. Plato's mother, Perictione,
-was of the family of Solon. 42
-
-' Plato had two brothers, Adeimantus and Glaucon, and
-
-
-a sister, Potone, whose son, Speusippus was therefore
-
-
-42 alk. Taylor, "Plato," Encyclopaedia Britannica,
-pp. 48-64.
-
-
-
-
-Plato's nephew as well as successor as head of the
-Academy. Plato was the youngest child in the family. *?
-According to Cicero, Plato's introduction to Archytas (the
-Strategus of Tarentum) was extremely fortunate since
-Archytas later rescued Plato from slavery, into which he
-had been sold by Dionysius 11.44 the incident of Plato's
-slavery was also recorded by Philodemus in his Index
-Academicorum. "5 However, without the Seventh Letter it is
-not possible to set a precise date for this event. Cicero
-only tells us that Plato was in Sicily and that he was
-ransomed by Archytas from the slavery into which he had
-been sola. *©
-
-After citing the well known details of Plato's birth
-and aristocratic lineage, Ritter reminds us that Plato was
-born during the Peloponesian war and that soon thereafter
-Pericles succumbed to the plague. Plato was six when peace
-was concluded with Sparta in 421 and he was fourteen, an
-
-
-Aimpressionable age, when the Athenian fleet was destroyed
-
-
-43 Field, op. cit., p. 4.
-a According to Field, Plato's benefactor was
-
+\defpnote{1.1}{A.E. Taylor,
+\bt{Commentary on Plato's Timaeus}
+(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1928), p. 4.}
+\defpnote{1.2}{F.M. Cornford,
+\bt{Plato's Cosmology},
+p. viii.}
+\defpnote{1.3}{Werner Jaeger,
+\bt{Paideia: The Ideals of Greek Culture}
+(3 vols.; New York: Oxford University Press, 1943), II, pp. 77--78. }
+\defpnote{1.4}{Ibid., p. 78.}
+\defpnote{1.5}{Ibid., p. 79.}
+\defpnote{1.6}{C.F. Hermann,
+\bt{Geschichte und System der Platonischen Philosophie}
+(Heidelberg: 1839), in Jaeger,
+op. cit., p. 79}
+\defpnote{1.7}{Jaeger, op. cit., p. 79.}
+\defpnote{1.8}{Ibid., p. 80.}
+\defpnote{1.9}{Theodor Gompers,
+\bt{Greek Thinkers},
+trans. G.G. Berry
+(London: John Murray, 1905).}
+\defpnote{1.10}{Ibid., p. 275.}
+\defpnote{1.11}{Ibid., p. 278.}
+\defpnote{1.12}{Ibid.}
+\defpnote{1.13}{Ibid., pp. 279, 283.}
+\defpnote{1.14}{Ibid., p. 284.}
+\defpnote{1.15}{Ibid., p. 285.}
+\defpnote{1.16}{Ibid.}
+\defpnote{1.17}{Ibid., p. 286.}
+\defpnote{1.18}{Ibid., p. 287.}
+\defpnote{1.19}{Jaeger, loc. cit.}
+\defpnote{1.20}{L. Campbell,
+\et{Plato,}
+\bt{Encyclopaedia Britannica,}
+11\tss{th} ed., Vol. XXI, pp. 808--824.}
+\defpnote{1.21}{Ibid., p. 810.}
+\defpnote{1.22}{Ibid.}
+\defpnote{1.23}{Ibid.}
+\defpnote{1.24}{U.V. Wilamowitz-Moellendorff,
+\bt{Platon}, I,
+(2\tss{nd} ed.;
+Berlin: Weidman, 1920), in Jaeger, op. cit., p. 80.}
+\defpnote{1.25}{Jaeger, op. cit., p. 84.}
+\defpnote{1.26}{A.E. Taylor,
+\et{Plato,}
+\bt{Encyclopaedia Britannica},
+XVIII (Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc., 1957),
+p. 49.}
+\defpnote{1.27}{Ibid.}
+\defpnote{1.28}{A.E. Taylor, \bt{Commentary}, p. 4.}
+\defpnote{1.29}{A.E. Taylor,
+\bt{Plato: The Man and His Work}
+(6\tss{th} ed.; 5\tss{th} print.; New York: Meridian Books, Inc., 1959),
+p. 346}
+\defpnote{1.30}{A.E. Taylor, \bt{Commentary}, p. 4.}
+\defpnote{1.31}{Constantin Ritter,
+\bt{The Essence of Plato's Philosophy},
+trans. Adam Alles (London: George Allen \& Unwin, Ltd., 1933).}
+\defpnote{1.32}{W. Lutoslawski,
+\bt{Origin and Growth of Plato's Logic}
+(New York: Longmans, 1928.)}
+\defpnote{1.33}{John Burnet,
+\bt{Greek Philosophy}
+(London: Macmillan \& Co., Ltd., 1914), Part I, p. 212.}
+\defpnote{1.34}{Cornford, op, cit.}
+\defpnote{1.35}{Wilamowitz, \bt{Platon}, I, p. 591, in Jaeger,
+op. cit., p. 8O.}
+\defpnote{1.36}{Constantin Ritter,
+\bt{Neue Untersuchungen uber Platon}
+(Munich: 1910), p. 181.}
+\defpnote{1.37}{Ritter, \bt{The Essence of Plato's Philosophy}, p. 9.}
+\defpnote{1.38}{Ibid., p. 27.}
+\defpnote{1.39}{Ibid., pp. 29--30.}
+\defpnote{1.40}{G.C. Field, \bt{Plato and His Contemporaries: A Study in Fourth-Century Life and Thought} (London: Methuen \& Co., Ltd., 1930), p. 68.}
+\defpnote{1.41}{Ross has summarized these results in tabular
+form: see Appendix A.}
+\defpnote{1.42}{A.E. Taylor, \et{Plato,} \bt{Encyclopaedia Britannica},
+pp. 48--64.}
+\defpnote{1.43}{Field, op. cit., p. 4.}
+\defpnote{1.44}{According to Field, Plato's benefactor was
Archytas (Field, op. cit., p. 16), but according to
-Gomperz it was Anniceris (Gomperz, op. cit., p. 261).
-
-
-45 Field, op. cit., p. 18.
-46 Gomperz, op, cit., p. 261.
-
-
-
-
-off Sicily. 47
-
-In 405, when he was approximately twenty, Plato met
-Socrates, and Ritter tells us that even his exceptional
-education in the arts of drama and poetry were not enough
-to prevent Plato from committing his poetic works to the
-flames, since they were not up to the new philosophical
-standards Socrates had impressed on nim, 48
-
-When "The Thirty" came to rule, Plato was asked to
-join with them, but he could not bring himself to take
-part in a regime which he felt to be responsible for the
-injustice of Socrates' death, so he went instead to Megara
-for a few years. 49
-
-Plato also travelled to Egypt, Crete, Cyrene, and
-Italy and Sicily. The Sicilian travels were "of great
-significance" for Plato's philosophy. In addition to
-Archytas of Tarentum he met other Pythagoreans in Syracuse.
-It was during these travels that he also met Dion and
-Dionysius I. Plato was at this time fourty years old; Dion
-was twenty and Dionysius forty-three, 99
-
-Many years later, after the unfortunate and misconceived rivalry between Dion and Dionysius II, Plato was
-
-
-sold into slavery at the island of Aegina but was soon
-
-
-47 Ritter, The Essence of Plato's Philosophy, pp. 21,
-22.
-
-
-48 tpaa., p. 22.
-49 Ipta., p. 23. © Abia.
-
-
-
-ransomed, His benefactor refused reimbursement, so Plato
-took the sum and applied it to the purchase of a plot of
-ground in the gardens of Akademos, where the founding and
-administration of his school occupied his attention for the
-next twenty years.>!
-
-In 367, Dionysius I dies and Dionysius II is advised
-by Dion to send for Plato. A rivalry takes place between
-Dion and Dionysius. Plato is allowed to return to Athens
-for the duration of the war in which Syracuse is engaged,
-on the promise that he will return as soon as it is over.
-Plato leaves and Dion is banished. °2
-
-Five years later, Plato returns. He tries, with less
-success than before, to have Dion reinstated. He returns
-again to Athens in 360. Three years later, Dion assembles
-an army and marches on Syracuse. He meets with some success
-but is later assassinated. According to Ritter, 52 Plato
-mourns with deeper grief than he had for Socrates,
-although Ritter does not reveal the source of his information.
-
-In 347, Plato dies. Ritter says: "To the end of his
-
-
-life he was mentally alert and active and enjoyed the honour
-
-
-51 Ip4d., p. 24.
-52 Ibid., p. 25.
-53 Ipid., pe 26.
-
-
-
-and respect conferred upon him by his circle of disciples."
-By accepting the authenticity of the Seventh Letter,
-Ritter is able to conclude that the Parmenides and the
-
-
-Theatetus were written before Plato’s Sicilian adventures
-and that the late dialogues were written thereafter. >>
-Thus Ritter is of the opinion that the Parmenides and
-
-
-Theatetus immediately precede the late group and should be
-
-
-read before them, since, in this order, the changes in style
-and doctrine between the Parmenides and the Jheatetus and
-the late group became more clearly recognizeable. In short,
-the influence of Plato's Sicilian experiences can be
-
-better discerned in the late group, and this influence is
-not detectable in the Parmenjdes and Theatetus.
-
-One final biographical point deserves attention
-before we pass on to a discussion of the relevance of
-Plato's letters to the matter of establishing the chronology
-of the dialogues, and it is the problem of determining the
-relative influence of Socrates on Plato's life.
-
-While this problem seems at first sight to belong
-to a discussion of Plato's biography, actually it does not.
-While it is true to say that we have as little information
-
-
-about the details of Socrates’ life as we have of Plato's,
-
-
-o4 Ibid., pe 27.
-
-
-55 Ritter cit., pp. 329 ff.; Untersuchungen
-uber Platon (Stutheeres 1888 » pp. 88 ff,
-
-
-()
-
-
-
-the fact is that we can only determine the influence of |
-Socrates by examining Plato's thought. It is frequently
-asserted that Plato wrote in the dialogue form because he
-held Socrates’ method of communication in such high esteem,
-and this is probably true. But there seems to be no
-information which could help us to determine whether the
-order of the dialogues was influenced by Socrates. It
-seems better to postpone this question until the next
-chapter, where we take up the doctrines of the dialogues,
-and the influence of Socrates’ thought on Plato's doctrine.
-
-It might be noted in anticipation that Plato does
-
-
-give several hints, through the Parmenides, Theatetus, and
-
-
-in the whole group of late dialogues, of the extent to
-which the doctrines of these dialogues are "beyond"
-Socrates, that is, ask the sort of questions which Socrates
-probably would not have asked.
-
-Let us pass, then, to a discussion of Plato's
-Seventh Letter, which reveals in some detail how Plato's
-Sicilian experiences influenced him. Such information will
-be useful in understanding some of the passages in the late
-dialogues.
-IV. The Letters
-
-J. Harward °° has made a very useful compendium
-
-
-which contains an impressive amount of material on the
-
-
-NE PIN SE IE TE ESI IT IT I I SE TS TC EIT OT DFAT I LEED TENE EEE
-
-
-50 J, Harward, The Platonic Epistles (Cambridge:
-The University Press, 1932).
-
-
-L a
-
-
-
-Letters. He cites a number of ancients who regarded the i
-whole collection of Plato's letters as authentic, including
-Diogenes Laertius, Plutarch, Lucian, Cicero, and Aristophanes the grammarian of Alexandria.o? Although Jowett 58
-followed Karsten 99 into the opinion that the entire lot
-was spurious, Harward says that the increasingly wide use
-of stylistic criteria soon dissipated the influence of their
-opinions. The stylists were thus able to overcome the views
-of Jowett and Karsten 60 which were that the letters were
-written in too lowly a style for them to be regarded as
-Plato's own, that the philosophical doctrine of the letters
-differs too widely from Plato's theory or Ideas, and that
-there are no sources from which we may conclude that Plato
-was actually ever in Sicily.©! Wilamowitz was particularly
-strong in asserting the letters to be genuine, and his
-criteria were largely stylistic, that is, he was able to
-conclude that the satyle of the letters was not too lowly
-tor Plato, but was in fact written with many or the idioms
-
-
-and phrases which Plato favored in his late years.
-
-
-57 Harward, op, cit., p. 60.
-
-
-58 B. Jowett, e Dialogues of Plato (3rd ed.; New
-York: Scribner, Armstrong, Oe, 1 » preface.
-
-
-59 H.T. Karaten, De Epistolis quae feruntur
-Platonicis (Utrecht: 1864), in Harvard, Op, cit., Pp. 61.
-
-60 Harward, op. cit., pp. 71, 72.
-
-61 Field, op, git., p. 16.
-
-
-
-Thus, there are few scholars today who would reject
-all the letters, although some scholars reject some of then,
-as we shall see. But in the main, the wave of scepticism
-has subsided. Thus, Harward is able to compile a list of
-scholars and tabulate which scholars accept which of the
-letters.
-
-
-The Seventh Letter in particular, has been accepted by
-
-
-Taylor, Burnet, Ritter, Hackforth, Wilamowitz, Souilhe,
-Bury, and Field.©2 These scholars were able to agree
-largely because of the stylistic criteria as applied to
-the letters. Harward discusses these criteria in some
-detail. He divides them into four groups, which include
-the following:
-1. choice of words, including neologisms and
-expressions Known to be current in certain
-years by reference to other authors.
-2. word order, including inversions of normal
-word order, hiatus, elision, the use of clausulae
-3. sentence structure, including extra paranthetic
-clauses, hanging nominatives, a string of terse,
-clipped unmodified verbs, following intuitional
-rather than strictly logical order.
-4. circuitous mannerisms and tautologous phrases 63
-One notices that the foregoing criteria are neither
-atrictly stylistic nor strictly stylometric. In order to
-make use of them i1t would be necessary to be a "trained
-observer" as Ritter says, and, in addition to noticing the
-
-
-presence of these devices of style, one could, if so
-
-
-62 Harward, ope cit., p. 76.
-63 Ibid., pp. 86-96.
-
-
-
-inclined, make tables and count the frequency with which
-these mannerisms occurred. But the deeper point is that
-the most reputable Platonic scholars were able to agree
-on the basis of these criteria that the Seventh Letter was
-both genuine and late. Harward says "...the stylistic
-
-
-features in common (between the Seventh Letter and the
-
-
-Laws) are so striking that they stare the reader in the
-
-
-face, "64 Ritter makes a similar comment when he says, "On
-
-
-any unprejudiced reader it (the Seventh Letter) cannot
-
-
-fail to produce the impression of the natural outspokenness
-of a narrative of personal experience. "65 Cicero himself
-says, "praeclara epistula Platonis ad Dionis propinquos..."66
-To these, Harward adds his own views since Plato regarded
-Kallipos as a "fiend incarnate," and since it was Kallipos
-who had Dion murdered, and since Kallipos wrote to Plato
-
-of the death of Dion in 354, and since the death of Dion
-
-4s recorded in the letter, but the letter does not record
-the death of Kallipos, which occurred a year later, it is
-probable that the letter was written between 354 and 353,67
-From all of these probabilities, Harward concludes that the
-
-
-64 Ipia., p. 86.
-
-
-65 Ritter, Neue Untersuchungen uber Platon, p. 408.
-66 Tusc, Disp. V, 35, in Harward, op. cit., p. 189.
-67 Harward, op, cit., p. 192.
-
-
-
-letter was composed after the Sicilian journeys and before :
-the Laws. This places the letters in a setting which is
-either immediately before or contemporaneous with the
-
-
-Timaeus. As we shall see after a discussion of the Seventh
-
-
-Letter in detail, it is probable that it precedes the
-Timaeus.
-
-
-Having shown on the basis of reputable scholarship
-
-
-the authenticity of the Seventh Letter and its late
-
-
-composition, I would like now to summarize its contents,
-in order to point out certain experiences Plato had
-relevant to the doctrine of the Timaeus.
-
-Plato begins by telling that his motive for visiting
-Sicily as the desire to see the people there freed by the
-best laws for the situation, and, in addition, he will
-recount in the letter the process in which he reached the
-formation of his opinions on the matter (324b).
-
-He describes his youthful aspiration for a political
-career and recounts that some of his relatives, (Critias
-and Charmides) were members of the Thirty, and that they
-had asked him to rule with them (324 b,c). But he declines
-because he sees that their rule, like most revolutionary
-regimes new in power, suffered excesses. These were
-particularly visible in these attempt to send Socrates on
-a dishonorable mission (324 6). It was finally certain,
-when Socrates was sentenced to death at the hands of this
-regime (325 c). Plato notes sadly that the older he gets
-the more he realizes the extreme difficulty of handling
-
-
-
-public matters (325 a). He noticed that not only the
-written but the unwritten laws were extremely inflexible
-and therefore hard to mold. As a matter of fact, those in
-Athens struck him as incurable, and for the time, nothing
-could be done (326 a). |
-
-We then read a small recapitulation of the Republic
-doctrine of the philosopher-king. Plato tells his readers
-that the situation in Sicily, like the one in Athens, is
-so difficult that there will be no peace for the sons of
-men until either philosophers are kings or those in power
-lay hold to some philosophical illumination (326 b). It
-was with these expectations that Plato first arrived in
-Sicily. He is repelled by the life of vice and court
-debauchery which he finds there, and says that here as
-elsewhere such immorality will inevitably lead to a
-succession of tyranny, oligarchy, and democracy (326 d).
-
-However, while there, he instructs the young Dion
-who is extraordinarily adept at this sort of learning, and
-Dion resolves to "live for the future" which of course
-makes him terribly unpopular at the court (327 b,c)
-However it is his hope that Dionysius will learn too, and
-in this way peace and happiness will be introduced (327 d).
-This fitea in with Plato's desires not to be "only a man
-of words" (328 aec) and, in addition, helps Plato to
-prove to himself that he does no dishonor to philosophy by
-inaction (329 a). However, Dionysius does not devote himself to philosophy. Moreover, Dion is perceived as a
-
-
-
-threat and is expelled from the court. Plato becomes a
-prisoner of the court (329 ced). Dionysius flatters Plato,
-but Plato is aware that it is his status and not his
-philosophy which Dionysius desires (330 a).
-
-Plato reflects on these experiences for his readers,
-and tells them an allegory to the effect that the physician
-is to his patient as the philosopher is to the state, and
-that, just as the physician prescribes diet, so the
-philosopher prescribes laws and constitutions which will
-eventuate in a good state (330 d-33!1 e). This too is
-reminiscent of the Republic. Again we are told that the
-good governor is he who frames good laws (332 b). To do
-80, @ man must have loyal friends, and there is no surer
-test of vice than a man without friends (332 c). Such a
-man is Dionysius, whose early years were hungry for want
-of education and proper training. Thus he was raised
-discordantly, and, beyond the fact that he is wrecking
-Sicily, the greatest poverty arises from his lack of
-harmony with himself (332 a). Nevertheless, a way must be
-found to free Sicily by the introduction of just laws (334c).
-A way might be found if only Dionysius can be brought to
-harmony with himself. If it is not possible to introduce
-order through Dionysius, then other means must be sought,
-for the source of light is the soul at harmony within the
-man (335 aed). Plato's hope is high and his desire is
-strong, but the worst crime is comitted: Dionysius
-
-
-refuses (335 e).
-
-
-
-- Thus the second venture ends worse than the first,
-due to a "fiendish" ignorance of matters of the soul and
-of philosophy on the part of Dionysius (336 bec).
-
-We are reminded of the early lesson of the letter,
-i.e., that a period of temperance after a revolution is
-as rare as it is necessary. Perhaps it follows that this
-is the time when just laws should be enacted but it is
-unfortunately true that this is also the time when such
-an enactment is least possible. Perhaps this task will
-remain for the future (356 e).
-
-How should such laws come to be? Plato answers his
-own question by saying that only the best men can make
-the best laws, and actually goes into the proportion of
-men to the population (337 c).
-
-The motive for Plato's third trip to Sicily is
-given. We are informed that Dionysius is eager to have
-Plato return, and that he has made progress in his study
-of philosophy. Archytas and his Tarentine circle of
-Pythagoreans implore Plato by letter, and one, Archydemos,
-even accompanies the trireme which is sent to supply
-Plato's passage. In order not to betray Dion and his other
-Tarentine friends, Plato allows himself to be convinced( 339
-a-e).
-
-There follows what one writer (Ritter) calls a
-philosophical digression into the nature of the process
-wherein philosophy is "imparted" so that the student will
-
-
-_gsee a "marvellous road" open before him (340 b,c). Here
-
-
-
-we have a recapitulation of some of the thoughts Plato
-
-
-had set down in the Phaedo and in the Republic, where he
-
-
-described how the soul, reflecting on herself, sees a
-whole new realm (340 d).
-
-"There neither is nor ever will be a treatise of
-mine on the subject" says Plato, in what seems at first
-to be a deep paradox. What can a philosopher mean whose
-Magnificent dramatic dialogues are revered as perhaps
-the highest insights ever written? Is it all a game? The
-key to this, is to be found in the Seventh Letter, which
-
-
-explains to the friends of Dion that Plato never fell from
-honor and was not among the murderers of Dion nor among
-the followers or participants in the horrible rule of
-Dionysius who had him killed. Plato is not addressing a
-learned academy nor an audience of philosophers but a
-group of friends and former associates of Dion who cannot
-understand how the great Plato and his philosophy could
-not save Dion from an unjust fate.
-
-To the claim of Dionysius that he was learning
-philosophy from the one lesson Plato had given him and
-that he was in fact producing learned treatises of originality and brilliance, Plato responds not only that his
-philosophy can't be taught in a few lessons, but that its
-deepest meanings cannot be taught at all, but must be
-experienced as a fire which is enkindled in the soul
-after an arduous preliminary regimen in the company of
-
-
-\.
-
-
-
-
-teachers who have been so inflamed (341 d,e).
-
-If philosophy cannot be taught as a series of learnable propositions, how can one expect to learn it in
-writings and disquisitions? To bolster this argument and to
-derive it from higher knowledge, Plato launches into a
-short essay on the steps and stages on the way to philosophical insight. There are, he says, three preliminary
-steps and two later stages through which philosophical
-knowledge is imparted (342 a), o8
-
-the "instruments" of this process are names, definitions, and images (eidola). Names are notoriously flighty
-and subject to the winds of change and fashion. Definitions
-are frequently contradictory and refer to aspects which
-shift. Images may be drawn and fashioned at will but what
-images attempt to convey is not necessarily subject to
-these inconsistancies (342 b,c). More proximate but still
-very distant is knowledge of the thing and closest is the
-thing itself as it is. If somehow one does not go through
-the first three, (names, definitions, and images) one
-cannot even aspire to the fourth, (knowledge of the thing)
-much less the fifth. It is much the same with the Good,
-the Beautiful, the Just, Bodies, even Characters of the
-
-
-65 not learned. Plato is talking about the
+Gompers it was Anniceria (Gompers, op. cit., p. 261).}
+\defpnote{1.45}{Field, op. cit., p. 18.}
+\defpnote{1.46}{Gompers, op, cit., p. 261.}
+\defpnote{1.47}{Ritter,
+\bt{The Essence of Plato's Philosophy},
+pp. 21--22.}
+\defpnote{1.48}{Ibid., p. 22.}
+\defpnote{1.49}{Ibid., p. 23.}
+\defpnote{1.50}{Ibid.}
+\defpnote{1.51}{Ibid., p. 24.}
+\defpnote{1.52}{Ibid., p. 25.}
+\defpnote{1.53}{Ibid., pe 26.}
+\defpnote{1.54}{Ibid., p. 27.}
+\defpnote{1.55}{Ritter op. cit., pp. 329 ff.;
+\bt{Untersuchungen uber Platon}
+(Stutheeres 1888), pp. 88 ff.}
+\defpnote{1.56}{J. Harward, \bt{The Platonic Epistles} (Cambridge:
+The University Press, 1932).}
+\defpnote{1.57}{Harward, op, cit., p. 60.}
+\defpnote{1.58}{B. Jowett,
+\bt{The Dialogues of Plato}
+(3\tss{rd} ed.; New York: Scribner, Armstrong, \& Co., 1878) preface.}
+\defpnote{1.59}{H.T. Karsten,
+\bt{De Epistolis quae feruntur Platonicis}
+(Utrecht: 1864), in Harward, op, cit., p. 61.}
+\defpnote{1.60}{Harward, op. cit., pp. 71--72.}
+\defpnote{1.61}{Field, op. cit., p. 16.}
+\defpnote{1.62}{Harward, op. cit., p. 76.}
+\defpnote{1.63}{Ibid., pp. 86--96.}
+\defpnote{1.64}{Ibid., p. 86.}
+\defpnote{1.65}{Ritter,
+\bt{Neue Untersuchungen uber Platon}, p. 408.}
+\defpnote{1.66}{\bt{Tusc, Disp.} V, 35, in Harward, op. cit., p. 189.}
+\defpnote{1.67}{Harward, op. cit., p. 192.}
+\defpnote{1.68}{Not \e{learned.} Plato is talking about the
communication of philosophy, not the stating of it, nor
the acquisition of it, but the process in which, so to
-speak, philosophy happens.
-
-
-
-'soul, and with all that is done or suffered (342 e). :
-
-Plato distrusts the fixity and unchangeable character
-of language as he hesitates to put down in words which
-seem firm and clear what cannot be grasped so easily (343 a).
-Words, definitions, and images contain much that is
-opposite to the things themselves (343 b). Philosophy is so
-hard that men satisfy themselves with images. ©9 Most men
-cannot study philosophy, and even those who do, find it
-hard if not impossible to speak of. Perhaps, after the
-preliminaries of words, definitions, and images, a birth
-will take place but unless the preparatory steps are
-taken, naught will avail the ambitious, such as Dionysius.
-In addition, if there is no "natural inclination," even
-these steps will lead nowhere (344 a).
-
-What is needed is a "sudden flash" which will arrive
-only occasionally and then only after long preperation (344b).
-Therefore, Plato warns his audience, do not expect to plumb
-the deepest meanings of philosophy too rapidly. And, even
-if a treatise on Laws, written by a great writer, should
-cross your attention, do not think that you see there the
-most precious thought of their writer; you do not. These,
-he implies, are images drawn for your information, but
-they are not philosophy, in its deepest sense (344 c).
-
-Moreover, Plato tells his readers that his reverence
-
-
-for the truth is such that he will not entrust it to
-
-
-69 See the Cave Allegory of the Republic 507. F
-
-
-
-vehicles. That which is inexpressibly beautiful should not
-be dragged down in homely expression. The inner harmony of
-philosophy will not mix with the discordant decadence of
-Dionysian politics. On the other hand, once truths of this
-sort have been experienced, there is no need to write them
-down because there is no danger of forgetting them. Once
-posessed, they live on (344d). So ends the "philosophical
-digression."
-
-Plato returns to his history of the events of his
-third stay in Sicily. He is implored to stay on by
-Dionysius’ promise to restore Dion's property and income.
-Plato is asked to remain for a while to consider the plan,
-but while he does so, the last trade ships leave and the
-season for travel comes to an end. (He has been tricked)
-(346). After the ships are gone, Dionysius sells Dion's
-property (347). Plato is told that Herakleides will not be
-harmed, even though he led a guard's revolt for higher pay,
-but again Dionysius goes back on his promise. Plato is
-ousted from the palace gardens on the pretext that they are
-needed for a festival (349).
-
-Plato begins to realize that his friendship for Dion
-4s disadvantageous, that he no longer shares the tyrant's
-confidence, that he is no longer useful, either to himself
-or to the tyrant, and that his friends at the court are
-gradually being arrested.
-
-He sends for help to Archytas (350). A trireme of
-
-
-_thirty oars is sent, with Lamiskos, a Pythagorean, in
-
-
-
-command. Plato is taken to Dion, who immediately plots
-revenge against Dionysius II. This time, Plato pleads not
-to be included, because of his advanced age, and because
-Dion is plotting to injure someone, and Plato will not be
-a party to violence (350 c).
-
-Plato gives out another allegory. Like the brave
-captain of a good vessel who underestimates the brutal
-ferocity of a storm, it became Dion's fate to die at the
-hands of Dionysius' forces, but it was a death with honor.
-
-Plato ends the letter by saying that he felt it was
-necessary to explain the paradoxical turn of events in
-Sicily, and he hopes he has done so (352).
-
-Since reputable scholars have agreed that the
-Seventh Letter is Plato's own, and since, in all probability
-it was written between 354 and 353, we must place it in the
-late period. We should expect the extraordinary experiences
-of Plato's Sicilian travels to have a marked influence on
-the doctrine of those dialogues written after the travels
-
-
-which the Seventh Letter record.
-
-
-However, in order to show what influences these
-
-
-experiences had on the doctrine of the Timaeus, it is
-
-
-first necessary to pass in review the doctrines of the
-
-dialogues between the Republic and the Timaeus. This task
-is the burden of the following chapter. It is possible at
-this point only to anticipate how the Seventh Letter leads
-
-
-us to expect that the Timaeus will reveal the influence of
-
-
-_Plato's Sicilian experiences.
-
-
-
-Thus, there is confirmatory evidence to be derived
-
-
-from the Seventh Letter for the view that the Timaeus is a
-
-
-late dialogue. This is indicated in the statement (at 344c)
-that even if a great writer were to write a treatise on
-laws and if such a treatise were to come to the attention
-of the Sicilians, it should not be regarded as philosophy
-but as a set of images. The fact that this statement is
-put in the hypothetical future seems to indicate that the
-Laws have not yet been written (at least, not completed).
-If the Laws is Plato's last effort, and if the Timaeus
-
-
-is as closely related to the Laws as the stylistic criteria
-
-
-indicate, this statement would seem to indicate that the
-
-
-letter itself was written before both the Timaeus and the
-
-
-Laws. We have already cited evidence for this view.
-
-It 18 the business of the next chapter to spell out
-the doctrinal criteria on which this same conclusion can
-be reached. There, the relevence of the doctrinal points
-of the Seventh Letter will be introduced.
-
-Perhaps it is not inexcusable to ask the reader to
-recall at this point that the division of the initial
-hypothesis into two methodological procedures, has, at
-this point, only dealt with one half of the argument, and
-that both halves are necessary to establish the hypothesis.
-Thus, one concludes from this chapter that the external
-sources, individually and collectively, point to the
-Timaeus as a late work. It now needs to be demonstrated
-ithat the doctrine of the Timaeus is a late doctrine.
-
-
-
-Thereafter, it will be shown that in the doctrine of the
-
-
-Timaeus we find not only a later doctrine than its
-
-
-predecessors, but a more developed doctrine, consisting of
-@ culmination and synthesia of the themes of eternity,
-image, and time.
-
-
-V__Conclusion
-
-
-I conclude this chapter with the conviction that the
-Timaeus is a late dialogue, probably written after Plato's
-Sicilian adventures. It is difficult to fix a precise date
-for its composition. It is certainly after the first two
-Sicilian adventures and certainly before 347, the year of
-Plato's death. /° stylistic criteria place it in the same
-age grouping as the Laws. This makes it probable that the
-Laws and the Timaeus occupied Plato's attention alternately
-
-
-during the same set of years. This means that the Timaeus
-trilogy and the Laws were both written in the last years
-of Plato's life. I think it is probable that the Timaeus
-
-
-was written after the third Sicilian adventure, after
-Plato's indebtedness to the Tarentine Pythagoreans had
-increased a great deal. I feel no need to separate the
-Laws, the Seventh Letter, and the Timaeug more precisely
-because I think that work on all three of them could have
-proceded together, yet I feel it is probable that the
-
-
-Seventh Letter precedes the completion of the Laws and
-
-
-70 4.e., it 48 in all probability not a posthumous
-edition.
-
-
-Ln
-
-
-
-
-
-the Timaeus. Cornford's hypothesis that Plato stopped in
-
-
-the middle of the Critias in order to complete the Laws is
-
-
-especially attractive.
-
-
-
-
+speak, philosophy happens.}
+\defpnote{1.69}{See the Cave Allegory of the \bt{Republic} 507.}
+\defpnote{1.70}{i.e., it is in all probability not a posthumous
+edition.}
CHAPTER III
THE DOCTRINE OF THE DIALOGUES
@@ -9757,7 +8046,7 @@ American Catholic Sociological Review. XXII, No. 2,
Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1961, pp. 143 ff.
-Gomperz, Theodor. Greek Thinkers. trans. G.G. ery.
+Gompers, Theodor. Greek Thinkers. trans. G.G. ery.
Londons John Murray, 1! °