1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
1001
1002
1003
1004
1005
1006
1007
1008
1009
1010
1011
1012
1013
1014
1015
1016
1017
1018
1019
1020
1021
1022
1023
1024
1025
1026
1027
1028
1029
1030
1031
1032
1033
1034
1035
1036
1037
1038
1039
1040
1041
1042
1043
1044
1045
1046
1047
1048
1049
1050
1051
1052
1053
1054
1055
1056
1057
1058
1059
1060
1061
1062
1063
1064
1065
1066
1067
1068
1069
1070
1071
1072
1073
1074
1075
1076
1077
1078
1079
1080
1081
1082
1083
1084
1085
1086
1087
1088
1089
1090
1091
1092
1093
1094
1095
1096
1097
1098
1099
1100
1101
1102
1103
1104
1105
1106
1107
1108
1109
1110
1111
1112
1113
1114
1115
1116
1117
1118
1119
1120
1121
1122
1123
1124
1125
1126
1127
1128
1129
1130
1131
1132
1133
1134
1135
1136
1137
1138
1139
1140
1141
1142
1143
1144
1145
1146
1147
1148
1149
1150
1151
1152
1153
1154
1155
1156
1157
1158
1159
1160
1161
|
\newcommand{\action}[1]{[\textit{#1}]}
\newcommand{\speaker}[1]{\vskip 0.2em \textsc{#1}: }
\newcommand{\speakermod}[2]{\vskip 0.2em \textsc{#1} \textit{(#2)}: }
\chapter{Philosophy of Concept Art (1987)}
{ \centering \itshape
An interview with Henry Flynt \\
by Christer Hennix \\
Dec. 6, 1987 \par }
\speaker{FLYNT} I'm going to give a summary of how I originated Concept Art
in order to bring it up to the point where it's understandable why I
speak of you (Catherine Christer Hennix) as my only successor in the genre.
Summarizing briefly, I see two things coming together. One of them
was my involvement with the modern music community of the time---Stockhausen,
Cage, LaMonte Young---and the other aspect was that I
had been a mathematics major at Harvard and already knew that I
thought of myself primarily as a philosopher---that my intention had
been when I was very young, when I didn't understand the situation
that I was in---my intention had been to become a philosopher with
nevertheless a specialization in mathematics. Of course, many people
actually did that.
So, having said that, one of the things that I began to notice about
the modern music of that time was this extremely strong pseudo-
intellectual dimension in Stockhausen---Stockhausen's theoretical
journal \journaltitle{die Reihe}---the impression that they were doing science
actually---for example Stockhausen had a long essay on how the
duration of the notes had to correspond to the twelve pitches of the
chromatic scale \ldots
\speaker{HENNIX} "\ldots\ how time passes\ldots"\footnote{\journaltitle{die Reihe 3}}
\speaker{FLYNT} Yes, and what is more, the other rhythms had to correspond to
the overtone structure above those frequencies as fundamentals.
\speaker{HENNIX} Yes, I'm quite familiar with that.
\speaker{FLYNT} Yes, I would expect you would be. I remember Bo
Nilson---you will like this---in 1958 at the same time I saw Stockhausen's
score---he went even one step further than Stockhausen because he
used fractional amplitude specifications---so this is even more than
Stockhausen, and so forth and so on.
Cage took a considerable step further in the sense that in Cage this
kind of play with structure is carried to the point where there is an
extreme dissociation between what the composer sees and what the
performer sees in terms of the structure of the piece and what the
audience knows. They are completely divorced from one another. Cage
would compose a piece on a graph in which the time that a note begins
is on one axis and the length of the note is on another axis. What he
would do was to superimpose that on some picture like from a star
catalogue---
\speaker{HENNIX} \opustitle{Atlas Eclipticalis}---
\speaker{FLYNT} Yeah, well, that's the particular piece. I'm making up a
composite of his compositional techniques but the result is that when you
break up a sequential event in that way, it's not like a pitch-time graph
where there's an intuitive recognition of the way the process unfolds.
He would have one structure for beginnings and another structure for
durations. Well at any rate, already in Cage's music there was a kind of
ritual aspect to performing classical music. I mean in Cage's piece,
which is actually all silence---the only thing the pianist does is open and
close the lid of the piano or something like that.
Then LaMonte Young comes along. His word pieces were the first
that I ever saw, composed in mid-1960. I saw them in December
1960.\footnote{Other composers have earlier dates, but for me,
Young crystallized the genre. [H.F., note added]}
It was a very different kind of structural game. It was no longer like
twelve-tone organization and so forth but rather it was like playing
with paradoxes---it was nearer to making a paradox than making some
kind of complicated network.
And I felt that matters had reached the point where there was
some kind of inauthenticity here because the point of the work of art
had become some kind of structural or conceptual play, and yet it was
being realized under the guise of music so that the audience had no
chance of really seeing what was supposed to be the point of the
piece---the audience was actually prevented from seeing. Certainly
Cage's methods had exactly that effect. The audience receives an
experience which simply sounds like chaos but in fact what they are
hearing is not chaos but a hidden structure which is so hidden that it
cannot be reconstructed from the performed sound. It's so hidden that
it can't be reconstructed but nevertheless Cage knows what it is. So I
felt that the confusion between whether they were doing music or
whether they were doing something else had reached a point where I
found that disturbing or unacceptable.
At the same time at that period there was a great fascination in sort
of taking the Stockhausen attitude and looking back at the history of
music from that point of view. Stockhausen's analysis in \journaltitle{die Reihe 2} of
Webern's \opustitle{String Quartet [Op. 28]} tried to show that Webern was
composing total serial music and not just twelve tone music. That was
the attitude, they were rewriting the history of music, trying to show
that all previous important figures were essentially preoccupied with
structure, that they had been complete structuralists.
\speaker{HENNIX} Really? I thought it was only Webern that was given that
treatment.
\speaker{FLYNT} Well, they were digging up all these composers from the
Middle Ages, the isorhythmic motet and everything like that---they
were sort of dredging that up because that was the previous
period---the medieval scores in the form of a circle and the use of insertion
syncopation,\footnote{My term for the rhythmic feature common to Magister Zacharias' \opustitle{Sumite Karissimi} and \opustitle{Klavierst\"{u}uck XI}. See Willi Apel, \booktitle{The Notation of Polyphonic Music} (4th ed.), p. 432 for \opustitle{Sumite Karissimi}. [H.F., note added]}
it appears with the red notes ina medieval score and then
it reappears in Stockhausen's \opustitle{Klavierst\"{u}ck XI}. They were just jumping,
they were dismissing what we would call the baroque, classical and
romantic periods periods as completely worthless. In other words, the
last music before Stockhausen was in the 14th century, this is the way
the history of music was being rewritten. And LaMonte was getting
into Leonin and Perotin and all that kind of stuff. Well, anyway, that's
quite an excursion.
At any rate there is in music, there is this preoccupation with---it
may be a kind of quasi-Pythagoreanism, I don't know\ldots
\speaker{HENNIX} The way I looked at it was that they saw in Webern, first of
all the harmony was going away. And they saw in Webern a way of
determining the note more and more precisely, in terms of all of its
parameters, pitch, duration, timbre and all that. What was left was that
timbre was not serialized yet. And that, as far I see it, was what the
Darmstadt school did---they added---
\speaker{FLYNT} Stockhausen's \opustitle{Kontra-Punkte}---
\speaker{HENNIX} Yeah. And they all considered Webern the god of the new
music---
\speaker{FLYNT} Yes---
\speaker{HENNIX} ---and also a little bit Messiaen---
\speaker{FLYNT} Yes.
\speaker{HENNIX} It was Webern and Messaien that determined the entire
fifties in Darmstadt. In other words, they were saying that Cage was no
good. He was just looking in \booktitle{I Ching}---it was a random thing. And you
cannot recover the structure, it's hidden, as you said. The problem was
that Stockhausen, when he played his \opustitle{Klavierst\"{u}ck XI}, you couldnt
recover the structure either. It was so complex now. So the complexity
of the serialist music became exactly the complexity of Cage. Cage
looked his numbers up in random number tables; the others were
sitting calculating rows of numbers. But in addition to that they also
had to fake it. Because---you find that yourself when you do serial
music---the music moves too slowly. So you change the numbers to get
the music up a little bit.
\speaker{FLYNT} Yes. We're taking longer on this than I meant to\ldots
\speaker{HENNIX} But I wanted to say this. The completely deterministic com-
position technique and the completely random, aleatoric technique,
gave exactly the same results. And that was the complete breakdown of
the Darmstadt school. That's when they started to improvise in Darm-
stadt. Not before that was there improvisation in Darmstadt.
\speaker{FLYNT} When they first tried to serialize duration, they tried to pick a
fundamental unit and use multiples of it; in other words, that's not the
way you serialize pitch. You don't take one cycle per second and then
use two cycles per second, up to twelve. That's not what you do. But
that's what they did with duration. And that's what produced the
Boulez pieces that move so slowly. In other words if you treat rhythm as
multiples of like a whole note then it was moving too slowly for them.
But Cage was for them what was wrong with America or something.
I mean, the center of what Stockhausen was doing was the
concept of scientificity. In other words at that time I fantasized the
composer appearing as performer, on the stage in a lab coat carrying a
slide rule---there were no electronic calculators at that time, it would
have to have been a slide rule---but that seemed completely approp-
riate. In other words, a composition was a laboratory experiment. I
mean they viewed Cage as a typical American---coming in a vacuum---
American superficiality---a vacuum with no scientificity. But Cage was
actually not using a random number table, he was flipping coins, he
was using the \booktitle{I Ching}. Yet it was not even that---what Cage was doing
was much more whimsical than using a random number book. He
would just copy a leaf---in the \opustitle{Concert for Piano and Orchestra} he just
put the staff over a leaf and then the main points defining the shape of
the leaf he just copied them on and he ended up with a circle or not a
circle, but a group of notes in cyclic shape, and so the pianist was
supposed to play around the circle. This was completely whimsical
actually and yes, I remember very well these debates that they had, the
one and the other\footnote{Serial vs. chance.}---I didn't have any idea that I was going to spend
this much time competing with the music critic of the \journaltitle{New York Times}
about who remembers the 1950s the best.
At any rate\ldots\ There is of course a larger tradition in art which has
a kind of quasi-scientific involvement in structure that does go very
much to the Renaissance, for example. Althought I was not so conscious
of that---I looked that up much later. But it was certainly there.
So, on the one hand concept art came from the idea of lifting
structure off and makinga separate art form out of it. The structure or
conceptual aspect, and making a separate art form out of it. The other
thing that was coming---the development of my philosophical thinking
---I have to explain first that the version of mathematics that I received
at Harvard in the 1950s in which Quine was the head of the department
and editor of the \journaltitle{Journal of Symbolic Logic} and so forth and the
hottest thing in philosophy was considered to be Quine's debate with
Carnap. And I was a schoolmate of Kripke, Solovay, Goodman \etc\
\etc, \etc. I'm just mentioning that to locate the period of time. Actually
my conversations with them were insignificant as far as the philosophy
of mathematics was concerned, there was no discussion between me
and them on any of that but it will locate the time frame that I'm talking
about.*
\footnote{I'm being too diffident. I had quite significant discussions with Kripke and Goodman in 1961. [H.F,, note added]}
But observing what was going on at that time, I picked up the idea
that the most plausible explanation of what mathematics is, is that it is
an activity analogous to chess, or in other words that chess captures the
characteristic features of mathematics, even though, as I have told you
privately many times, everybody knew who Brouwer was and what the
intutionist school was, but nobody studied it, and from my point of
view looking at it and knowing what it was, I felt no inclination to
pursue it further.
The reason why this chess game explanation of mathematics
seemed so plausible---you know, at the end of the nineteenth century
they found themselves with three geometries---this is not Henry Flynt
saying this, this is the canard, the story in the text books. There were
three geometries; one of them fit the real world. They thought it was
Euclidean, but it might not be. It might be one of the others like elliptic,
for example; nevertheless, all three were consistent. Now what was the
epistemological status of the two out of the three geometries that were
true without having any correspondence to the real world, while one of
them did have a correspondence to the real world and was also true?
But what of the other two---the ones that were called true even thought
they had nothing to with the world? You know presumably Hilbert
wrote \essaytitle{Foundations of Geometry} as the original answer to that
question.
Although---I can't pursue this here, it is much too technical---this
is now an open question for me. It has never been an open question in
the past. I just accepted what I was told---that Hilbert solved this by
seeing that a system of mathematics that has no relation to the real
world---in what does its truth consist? Its consistency as an uninterpreted
calculus as they would say---axioms, proofs, formation rules,
transformation rules. Certainly it was clear in the early twentieth
century that the concept of an abstract space was established. This was
what geometry was about. Geometry did not attempt---in Kant's time it
was assumed that when you were talking about geometry you were
talking about the geometry of the real world. That's the only geometry
that there was. The idea that there was a different agenda for geometry
other than the real world---how Kant could have moved geometry into
the constitutive subject and said that it was congenital to the mind---Euclidean geometry.
In hindsight that seems to be one of the biggest
mistakes he made, tremendously embarrassing, because by the mid-twentieth
century it was completely taken for granted that the job of the
mathematician was to study structures which do not have any reality.
And that from time to time you will give an interpretation to one or the
other of these structures, like a physical interpretation, and then it may
be found to be true or false in reality or not. Meanwhile, you have
another sense of the word "interpretation" which has to do with relative
consistency proofs by something having a model.
This is now a completely open question for me, what they thought
they were doing. In other words what Hilbert thought that he was
doing---he interpreted one or another non-Euclidean geometry---what
was the interpretation that he used? It was a denumerable domain of
algebraic numbers.\footnote{Foundations of Geometry, pp. 27--30}
\speaker{HENNIX} I think his ideas go back to Klein's models---which are
Euclidean in the center of the circle and then at the periphery they have
turned non-Euclidean (in the complex plane).
\speaker{FLYNT} You had to have an explanation of how mathematics could be
true in any sense whatsoever even though any claim of a connection
with the real world had been completely severed, and it was being
pursued in some kind of vacuum. What does mathematics mean in that
case? And the answer that Hilbert gave was that it does not have to
mean anything.
That's the answer. So it's a chess game. And the only difference
between mathematics and a chess game is that there are additional
complications created in mathematics by the fact that it deals with
infinitary games. By the way, I completely overlooked that aspect at
that time. You know, I can only see it now, kind of like two superimposed
pictures, because I see what I know now and compare it with what I knew then.
\speaker{HENNIX} Yeah, the same for myself. I didn't know that this idea of
Hilbert's was forced by Frege until later. Frege was the one who said
that either the parallel axiom is true, or it's not. Which way do you want
it? And so he caused the big stir in the foundations of geometry in the
end of the nineteenth century and that's why he became enemies with
Hilbert. They were life enemies.
\speaker{FLYNT} The reason I see it like two superimposed transparencies---
\speaker{HENNIX} But even today this debate with Frege---you have to go to a
single volume in Frege's posthumous writings---it is not mentioned in
any textbook---no lecture mentions it, and, so far, nobody has
explained it properly.\footnote{\booktitle{Nachgelassene Schriften und Wissenschaftlicher Briefwechsel}, vol. 2, Felix Meiner, Hamburg: 1976. (Gottlob Frege, The Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence, University of Chicago Press: 1980)}
\speaker{FLYNT} Yes, yes, yes. You're talking about an obscure origin of something
and what I'm talking about is a kind of consensus that had grown
up, since everybody agreed that mathematics should study unreal structures.
\speaker{HENNIX} But that consensus was forced on us, that that was what we
were supposed to do.
\speaker{FLYNT} The problem then---I thought mathematics was like chess.
What I understand now is that even a good formalist would not agree
with that. A good formalist would say that when you have a finite game
like chess, the problems of validity and soundness become transparent
or intuitively ascertainable, therefore a finite game is too trivial to be a
proxy for mathematics. At that time I did not understand that distinction.
I've read in many books since then that mathematics is the science
of infinity---that is the way mathematics is defined now in half of the
books that I look at. But at that point I did not understand. I thought
the finite game was already, I mistakenly thought, a complex enough
problem to stand for mathematics. Or that the reliability of a finite
game was sufficiently complicated to stand for mathematics so I basically
focused just on a finite game.
\speaker{HENNIX} By the way, this was exactly the late Wittgenstein's view of
the philosophy of mathematics---it's not a complete misunderstanding,
that is to say, other people thought of it that way too.
\speaker{FLYNT} The question then arose of even the soundness, the reliability,
the consistency of a finite game---this then is the problem for example
whether it is possible to follow a very simple rule correctly or not. The
other thing that was feeding into everything that was going on was that
Wittgenstein's \essaytitle{Remarks on The Foundations of Mathematics} was in
the Harvard Bookstore when I walked in as a freshman my very first
day there---so in other words I was looking at Wittgenstein's Remarks
on The Foundations of Mathematics from 1957---
\speaker{HENNIX} Ten years before me---
\speaker{FLYNT} ---but very cursorily. Because I had a philosophical
agenda---I passed over this material in a very cursory way because I had a
philosophical agenda. I was not involved in the distinction between a
finite and an infinite structure. I was not involved in that.
\speaker{HENNIX} You thought there was no such distinction?
\speaker{FLYNT} Well no, I thought that---it didn't seem that there was very
much point in worrying about that when there were much more
extreme problems to be worried about. But Wittgenstein wrote a lot
about the possibility of following very simple rules. And I assumed that
if there were epistemological questions for mathematics that this game
interpretation---this chess interpretation---had displaced the question
of the soundness and reliability of the mathematics to the possibility of
understanding a very simple rule like writing the series "plus 2".
And having gathered that this was the way that I should picture
mathematics---I mean we understood very well that there were other
pictures of mathematics, but we thought they were philosophically
obsolete. In other words the person who believed that mathematics was
a description of a real supra-terrestrial structure, and certainly there
were people like that---
\speaker{HENNIX} Still today.
\speaker{FLYNT} ---we thought that this was a philosophy that had been
exposed as superstitious by Positivism and possibly even by Ockham
several centuries earlier. So it was not that we didn't know about that. I
drew a personal conclusion that that position could not be defended by
any arguments that are acceptable by modern standards. What I really
meant was by Carnap's standards. That's what modern standards
meant to me.
In my philosophy I was not concerned with the specifics of
mathematics; I was concerned with the problem of how I knowa world
beyond my immediate sensations. That was actually the question that I
began with---the question of propositions of material fact, like "it is raining"
or "the \textsc{Empire State Building} is at Fifth Avenue and 34th Street."
I had read a very simplified exposition---it was actually some
lectures that Carnap gave in England in the 1930s on what Positivism
was.\footnote{R. Carnap, \booktitle{Philosophy and Logical Syntax} (1935).}
They were very simple lectures and very different from his actual
published books with all this supposed apparatus and symbols and so
forth but a very simple exposition of what it is for a proposition to be
meaningful---that it must be empirically testable and so forth and so on
and the solution of questions of metaphysics that make assertions that
are not testable are therefore meaningless---the possibility of solving
questions of what is real by declaring if there is no way of deciding them
they are therefore meaningless. That seemed to me to be, at the time, a
stunning contribution. Because I come out of a background---I was in
high school reading Kant and so forth and so on. And Carnap's
solution was much more attractive to me than trying to participate with
Kant, to experience his question and try to take one side or the other
when he already said it's not really answerable; I solve it by simply
having faith or something like that, which is what he said about the
famous God freedom and immortality---I found it immensely attractive
when Carnap came along and said that there is no way of answering
these questions; therefore, words are being used nonsensically.
I went through a process of thinking about that without ever
having seen Carnap's \booktitle{The Logical Structural of The World}. When I
was in Israel Scheffler's philosophy of science class, I tried to write a
text which in effect gave my own empiricist constructions of what it
means to say that A causes B and so forth, to give empiricist constructive
definitions of those---which is, I suppose, in the spirit of Carnap's
program, even though I hadn't actually seen what he had written, and if
I had it would have confused me---no, I wouldn't say "confused"; I
would say it would have discredited him completely. I wouldn't say
"confused" because that's too modest.
\speaker{HENNIX} No, I wouldn't think "confused," I would think it would
have upset you\ldots
\speaker{FLYNT} No, I wouldn't say "confused." I would say he had been
discredited.
I very quickly passed to the position that the propositions of
natural science were meaningless metaphysics.
\speaker{HENNIX} On what basis? Can you pin that down? A little bit, only.
\speaker{FLYNT} This is something I want to compress---it says a little bit about
this in \booktitle{Blueprint for a Higher Civilization}\footnote{H. Flynt, Blueprint for a Higher Civilization (Milan, 1975). Recently reissued and an expanded and corrected edition by \textsc{Salitter Workings}}---like
the proposition, "this key is made of iron" or something like that, I comment on that in the
essay \essaytitle{Philosophical Aspects of Walking Through Walls}.
\speaker{HENNIX} I didn't recall the example actually.
\speakermod{FLYNT}{reading} "The natural sciences must certainly be dismantled.
In this connection it is appropriate to make a criticism about the logic
of science as Carnap rationalized it. Carnap considered a proposition
meaningful if it had any empirically verifiable proposition as an
implication. But consider an appropriate ensemble of scientific propositions
in good standing, and conceive of it as a conjunction of an infinite
number of propositions about single events (what Carnap called
protocol-sentences). Only a very small number of the latter propositions
are indeed subject to verification. If we sever them from the entire
conjunction, what remains is as effectively blocked from verification as
the propositions which Carnap rejected as meaningless. This criticism
of science is not a mere technical exercise. A scientific proposition is a
fabrication which amalgamates a few trivially-testable meanings with
an infinite number of untestable meanings and inveigles us to accept the
whole conglomeration at once. It is apparent at the very beginning of
\booktitle{Philosophy and Logical Syntax} that Carnap recognized this quite
clearly; but it did not occur to him to do anything about it."
The only point that I'm trying to make here is that I began to move
very quickly when I was still very young towards a position of extreme
disillusionment and cognitive extremism. I moved very quickly. This
was not a slow process. I just immediately took Carnap's critique of
metaphysics, decided that it applied directly to natural science---you
dismiss natural science as meaningless. The problem: is there an object
that is beyond my experience, is there a glass which is beyond what they
would call the "scopic" glass, the "tactile" glass \action{gestures toward the
glass from which he has been drinking}---is there a glass other than
those glasses---when you first think about it, that question seems to
have exactly the status of the propositions about God, freedom, and
immortality that Kant said are unanswerable and that Carnap said are
meaningless. However, there is one additional step for people who are
interested in the history of philosophy. Kant, in the second edition of
\booktitle{Critique of Pure Reason}, added this notorious refutation of idealism to
prove the existence of the real world independent of my sense
impressions---you may not know about this---this was the basis of
Husserl's phenomenology---Husserl's phenomenology was invented in
this passage and it also tremendously preoccupied Heidigger. It was
one of the sources which causes Heidigger to say that the essence of
Being is Time. Kant said that essentially it is the passage of time which
proves that there must be an external world. This is notorious in the
history of philosophy. Because on the one hand it is so deeply
influential for later thinkers; and on the other hand, for example,
Schopenhauer said it was a complete disgrace---it was such an obvious sophistry
that it was just disgusting---that it had the effect of ruining the
\booktitle{Critique of Pure Reason}.
Actually this refutation of idealism is distributed throughout the
\booktitle{Critique of Pure Reason}, it's not in any one place---a foot note here,
a preface there, another passage somewhere else. In one of the footnotes
Kant makes the same point. In order to ask the question whether
there is a glass beyond my sense impression of it---I cannot ask that
question\ldots
\speaker{HENNIX} Oh you mean the \term{ding an sich} question.
\speaker{FLYNT} Well that's what Kant would have been talking about but I
don't want to fit that narrowly into Kant's controlling the terms of the
discussion. I'm trying to ask it as someone who has embraced
Logical Positivism and is now turning around to question Logical
Positivism---you see the point that I was just making there---when
you say that this key is made of iron, which is Carnap's favorite
example---and then a protocol sentence, for example
"if I hold a magnet near this key, the key will be attracted to the magnet"---it
is not clear where Carnap stands on
the question whether only my sense impressions are real---just talking
about this situation---only my sense impressions are real---or is there
supposed to be a substantial key?
By the way, I don't know Carnap's work that well. I passed over
these people in a very offhand way, so much so that many times I've
talked to people and they've concluded in their own mind that I dont
really know philosophy because I seem to have just glanced at these
people---picked up one or two points---the reason for that is that I was
moving so quickly to my own terminus---I only needed to see the
slightest symptom from these people to know that they were spending
all their time worrying about something that it was a waste of time to
worry about since it could only be a secondary issue. Here is Carnap
with this key made of iron---while I'm trying to ask is there a key other
than the scopic key, the tactile key \emph{now}---since the past and the future
are beyond immediate experience. I mean they cannot be cited as
evidence---or whether they are evidence or not, is the same problem.
Should I believe in the past and the future even though they are not
immediates? Should I believe in the glass, even though what I
presumably have is a scopic glass---at this very moment, a visual glass
apparition, from that should I conclude a glass?
The first reaction to that question for somebody who is coming
from Kant and Carnap and who does not mind how extreme his
answer is---that's the key thing. In other words, if I came to a
conclusion that was completely untenable as far as social circumstances---that
didn't bother me at all. At first the question whether there is a real glass
beyond the apparition would seem to be an unanswerable
question---one of Kant's metaphysical questions---but then you think---that if you
know what the question means, then there must be a realm beyond
experience, because otherwise it is unclear how the question could be
understandable.
From my point of view---if you want to make an issue out of
semantics---this is the profound issue. What the mathematical philosophers
and philosophers of mathematics were doing, talking about
semantics, interpreting geometry as an algebra and algebra as a
geometry---really for the purposes of relative-consistency proofs or
because they found they could solve problems by using a machinery
developed in another branch of mathematics by seeing these structural
similarities---but to confuse that with what I thought the bona fide
semantic question is: how would I understand the question whether
there is a substantial glass other than the scopic glass---you know the
conclusion---I can't tell you the exact breakdown---but I am talking
now about the 1961 manuscript, \essaytitle{Philosophy Proper}\footnote{Published in \booktitle{Blueprint for a Higher Civilization}. This book.}
---I may have
already come to the conclusion at that time---that the question itself
forces a yes answer. This does not mean that a proof of the existence of
the external world has been given. It meant that the proposition of the
existence of the external world would verify itself even if it were false!
\speaker{HENNIX} I find this extremely interesting and rewarding, what you are
saying now, because I never heard you say it this way before. I just want
to ask you one question before you go on: namely, I see something for
the first time which I hadn't seen before---but before you go on I just
want to ask you one leading question: the simple existential statement,
"there is a glass on the table." You include that also in what will be
doubtable here. In other words not just "there is a glass on the table"
but "there exists a glass," the existential statement. I guess I wasn't very
clear now.
\speaker{FLYNT} No, the thing is, the approach that I'm taking doesn't break it
down the way that you're talking about. Let me tell you. You may not
be \emph{sympatico} with empiricism. When you are trying to deal with
philosophy at all---you have to make some allowance for the
fact---you have to understand that the philosopher may be carving up
problems in a way that is temperamentally alien to you.
\speaker{HENNIX} Yeah\ldots
\speaker{FLYNT} You have to understand that. This is why somebody like
Carnap would read Hegel and say it's not saying anything. Actually,
Hegel is saying something. In fact, you might go so far as to make a case
that Hegel is actually rebutting Carnap, becaue if you understand what
Hegel is doing you realize even more than one would realize anyway
that Carnap has an untenable position---that he's sort of---that he
wants what he cannot have. He has made a set of rules that does not
allow him to have the thing that he demands to have. Hegel would have
seen that immediately. Carnap thinks that the problem of a logic of
consistency is an easy problem and a solved problem. In effect, Hegel
was saying there is something very misleading in thinking that that is a
solved problem. I'm trying to give you a sense of misunderstandings
between philosophers that are the results of temperamental incompatibilities.
\speaker{HENNIX} What you are giving me is a two-step way to skepticism. You
ask a certain question---is there something beyond this perception of
the glass? And you say the answer "yes" is forced on me, but then you
realize this was a meaningless question.
\speaker{FLYNT} No, it's the other way around.
\speaker{HENNIX} Oh, okay, but here's where you have to explain in detail
because here's where I miss you.
\speaker{FLYNT} Let me go through the series of steps again. The series of steps
was\ldots\ I'll have to doit all at the same time. You have to understand---I
don't think that you even understand what an empiricist is. It's a
peculiar attitude. And one of the reasons why you have very little
training in this attitude is because people who claim to be
empiricists---it's always a fraud. All people who appear in public and say they are
empiricists, they are all lying all of the time. The reason that they're
lying is that they have this doctrine of the construction of the world
from sense impressions. That is their doctrine. But they do not stay with
that doctrine. And the reason why they do not stay with that doctrine is
because in addition to having the doctrine of the construction of the
world from sense impressions, they also want to have things like
science---
\speaker{HENNIX} Ethics\ldots
\speaker{FLYNT} No, not ethics---one of the characteristics of the twentieth-
century philosopher was the appearance of the tough-guy philosopher
who rejects all of ethics as meaningless, which Carnap certainly did and
people who are close to him like A.J. Ayer---no, they did not want
ethics. But they wanted science. And the problem with wanting the
construction of the world from sense impressions on the one hand and
wanting science on the other is that the two finally have nothing to do
with each other at all---and when they said that the two were the same
thing as Carnap did---he was lying---I made a hero out of Carnap---I
derived some kind of positive impulse from him or something like that
without---I never actually read---my serious reading of Carnap was like
three or four pages of excerpts in a paperback popularization. I owned,
I had in my library Carnap's so-called real books, like
\booktitle{Logical Foundations of Probability} and \booktitle{Meaning and Necessity} and all the rest of them
and I never read them.\footnote{Again I'm being too diffident. I thoroughly studied portions of the
Carnap books I owned---beginning with \booktitle{The Logical Structure of Language},
which I bought while in high school [H.F., note added].}
And in hindsight that was good, because I took
his slogan seriously and assumed that he meant what he said and drew
the necessary consequences of it. If I had actually read his books I
would have been thrust into this massive hypocrisy, and I must say
stupidity, because the man did not realize that his answers were not
adequate, did not realize how preposterous his constructions of the
world were---
\speaker{HENNIX} I would say vulgar.
\speaker{FLYNT} Yes, yes. And\ldots\ what is even worse about empiricism is, in the
case of somebody like Mach, not only does he want to have his sense
impressions and does he want to have his science, but he wants to have
science explain sense impressions! And nevertheless it was supposed to
be the sense impressions that were primary, not the science. Mach is
seriously telling you, I will tell you why you see a blue book---because
the frequency of blue light is---and then he gives some uncountable
number, I mean some number that is pragmatically infinite, or something
like that. And how do you know that blue light is exactly
$3.2794835\mathrm{e}{15}$ and not one more or less---? Well,
certainly not by just looking, I'll guarantee you that! You have to go
into a laboratory with a few million dollars' worth of equipment or
something. But that's what it is to see that the book is blue.
I'm trying to give you the sense of what it would be to be an
authentic empiricist. You ask does a glass exist; an authentic empiricist
would have to say that he already has a problem with that---that he has
to regard that as an undefined question or statement. It's undefined,
because if you are asking me if at this moment I quote unquote
have---interesting word there, "have"---that is what our ordinary
language gives us as the idiom for this.
\speaker{HENNIX} Or "suffer!"
\speaker{FLYNT} Yes, "have" or "suffer," that's right. I have or I suffer a scopic
glass or visual glass apparition---then that is identically true. That is
identically true. If you express any surprise at that, we have a problem
here. I have a scopic glass. If I say I have an apparitional glass, would
that be okay?---I mean from this point of view the sense impression is
not open to dispute. It's meaningless to dispute it. It's an impression, an
apparition---the sense impression is that for which seeming and being
are identical. For the empiricist the phase of the world or range of the
world for which seeming and being are identical is the sense impression.
If that seems strange to you then maybe I can make it less strange by
pointing out to you to make this as clear as possible---for the empiricist
to say that I have an apparitional glass is to say nothing about Reality
with a capital R at all! This is the so-called subjective psychological
moment---although an empiricist would never say that---the reason an
empiricist would never say that is that even to call it subjective is
already much too strong because that implies that you can guarantee
an objectivity to compare it to. And a bona fide empiricist would not
agree that my sense impression is subjective---subjective in comparison
to \emph{what}?
\speaker{HENNIX} So an empiricist would be a person who would not doubt
whether he had a toothache or not. In other words, if he had a
toothache\ldots
\speaker{FLYNT} You would regard it as being a mistake to do what? I'm not
sure about the word "toothache"---if you mean that he would not
doubt whether he had a toothache sensation. Whether there is an
organic---in the language of medicine---whether there is an organic
substrate for the toothache impression---this in a medical sense is a
question of what is called hysteria or something like that\ldots
\speaker{HENNIX} Suppose I have a toothache. But now I'm an empiricist so I
say I'm doubting this impression. I probably don't have a toothache.
\speaker{FLYNT} No, no\ldots
\speaker{HENNIX} I have to accept the toothache?
\speaker{FLYNT} No, you don't have---
\speaker{HENNIX} The glass you said was---I couldn't doubt the perception of
the glass. You said that was beyond doubt, in some sense, for the
empiricist.
\speaker{FLYNT} It would be some kind of logical mistake to think that there
was anything there to be doubted.
\speaker{HENNIX} Okay. And the same with the toothache.
\speaker{FLYNT} Yes, yes. I mean the point is not so much that we have come
into an area in which the empiricist is prepared to have faith---that
would be completely missing the point. No faith is required---that's the
point. The point is that it would be some kind of logical error. Once you
understand what a sense impression is, the terminology of doubt does
not apply to that level.
\speaker{HENNIX} I see. Just that was my question.
\speaker{FLYNT} The terminology of doubt does not apply to apparitions. It
doesn't make sense to doubt subjective apparitions. The empiricist is
already nervous when you ask does a glass exist. If you are asking
whether I have a "scopic" glass, it's identically true. Wait, wait. There
are already problems there. I'll come back to them. But when you
say---it sounds like what you're asking me is whether the fact that I see a
glass is sufficient to prove an objective glass---that sounds like \ldots
\speaker{HENNIX} No, no, that's not what---
\speaker{FLYNT} Well, ok. Most people when they say:
"do you concede that there is a glass on the table---I'm sitting here looking at it," what they
mean is: "do you concede that from your visual glass apparition you should conclude an objective glass, a substantial glass?" I'm taking it for
granted that you know enough about philosophy to have a sense of the
full weight those two words "substantial" and "objective" have in
philosophy.
\speaker{HENNIX} Yes.
\speaker{FLYNT} That at great length is my reaction to your question about
doubting "there is a glass on the table" versus doubting "there exists a glass."
A bona fide empiricist would say, "Why are you asking me this?"
The scopic glass is simply here for me. As far as concluding that an
objective glass exists from the existence of that apparition---the traditional
problem of concluding whether the apparition is a symptom of
some transcendent world---I think the word "transcendent" is sometimes
used in that sense in philosophy---the world beyond any sense
impression---
\speaker{HENNIX} This is why I used the example of the pain---because it
would be senseless for me to claim that \emph{I} can have \emph{your} toothache!
\speaker{FLYNT} Now just a minute. An empiricist---what you're really getting
at what you're sort of squeezing out of me here---I'm glad to have it
squeezed out of me---I have no embarrassment about this---is that with
empiricism either you must be prepared immediately to depart
absolutely from the conventional world view, or else you will just plunge
yourself into a quicksand of hypocrisy. When you're asking me, can l
have your toothache\ldots\ A good empiricist would say,
\textquote{I have not established so-called other people except the other-people apparitions
that occur for me from time to time in waking life \emph{as they do in my
dreams!} And are you now going to ask me can I have the toothache of a
person who appears to me in a dream?} Then the spotlight would be
turned on you---what kind of an issue are you trying to make there?
What do you believe is the reality status of the furniture in my dreams?
For the empiricist, nothing remotely like that question has arisen yet,
because I haven't got outside of my own quote unquote head yet.
Maybe you're just squeezing more and more. Either the empiricist
must be a "madman" or else he must be insincere. I took the alternative
of the madman. This is important not for me but for the general public
to be told---something which the general public has never been
told---and I know why they have never been told---maybe it is necessary to
complete this point. The point is that empiricism was contrived to
paper over a kind of---I mean there was sort of this
epistemological---Science epistemologically was resting on some sort of very shaky
foundation---they saw that. They brought in this empiricism in the
hope that it would solve a problem, that it would substantiate science
while at the same time it would cut away the common-sense notion of
causality as being unnecessary to science. Empiricism was going to give
you a more sophisticated science that did not need the traditional
metaphysical or common-sense notion of causality. It told you how to
get along without that, but at the same time it validated everything that
the scientist needed. And, at the same time, empiricism was supposed to
be---in the case of Neurath---he wanted to make some kind of unification
of empiricism with Marxism and make it like a complete demythified view of society.
\speaker{HENNIX} There was even an attempt to bring ethics into it.
\speaker{FLYNT} Well, in Neurath's case, yes.
\speaker{HENNIX} Schlick too, I think---Schlick, I recall, did something in
ethics.\bootnote{\booktitle{Fragen der Ethik}, Vienna, 1930.}
\speaker{FLYNT} I was talking about why empiricism is not portrayed honestly
in the general picture that exists of philosophy---the public picture of
philosophy---it was brought in to solve the problem of what is a base
for science---namely, sense impressions are going to be taken as
elemental. Science is going to arise from sense impressions by construction.
Nevertheless it is required that both scientific knowledge and the
common-sense social world be produced by this approach---
\speaker{HENNIX} Neurath, you mean.
\speaker{FLYNT} No, no. Well, Carnap did not deny the existence of other
people. All of the positivists\ldots
\speaker{HENNIX} Rather, he had nothing to say about it.
\speaker{FLYNT} I didn't say ethics---I said the common-sense social world. I
wasn't talking about anything ethical\ldots
\speaker{HENNIX} The existence of tables and cars and---
\speaker{FLYNT} Well, what I'm saying is that the existence of other people is on
the same level as the existence of tables and automobiles. And what is
even worse than that is that the ones who were scientists in fact wanted
to see perception itself as the product of the abstract and quantified
sequence that the biophysicist or the psychophysicist sees---the light,
the lens, the retina, the optic nerve, the visual cortex, and so forth and
so on---they wanted to have that as prior to the sense impression but at
the same time they wanted to have all that constructed up from the
sense impressions. Why would this remain in place? Because it was a
more palatable---it's just like why would formalism remain in place?
Everybody learns that formalism died with Godel's incompleteness
theorems---it certainly didn't die for me; it isn't even clear what the
incompleteness theorems are supposed to have done or not to have
done---the fact remains that if you don't explain mathematics as an
uninterpreted calculus, then for us there was nothing left but
superstition. Those are the choices that you are given. If you don't explain that
science is constructed up froma ground of sense impressions, then how
do you want it to be constructed, down from God? You see, we don't
take that \emph{seriously} anymore.
As a matter of fact Hume wrote two philosophical works and in
the first work\footnote{\booktitle{Treatise on Human Nature}}
there is the notorious passage in which he himself
understands what it means to be a genuine empiricist.\footnote{Book I, Part IV, VII "Conclusion"}
He says, \textquote{I feel that I am an outcast from the human race,} and so forth in this famous
passage---he says,
"I do not know if the glass continues to exist after I've looked away from it."
That line in Hume should have told you
whatever you wanted to know about the existence of the glass. You
should be able to ascertain the appropriate answer to your question.
Hume says: "I do not know if the glass exists when I look away from it."
Hume's second book\footnote{\booktitle{An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding}},
when he was trying to vindicate himself,
when he had dropped the whole business of being a madman, it was
much nearer to what empiricism means today: an attempt to construct
science from a more meager inventory of elements, namely sense
impressions. And that is where Hume presents his doctrine that science
does not need and should not invoke metaphysical causation, that it
should replace the old-fashioned causation with some sort of construction
which is more flat or more network-like.
Well, at any rate, I'm going into this long thing---this is why it's
never dealt with in public in a sincere way---the only time it was was by
the guy who invented it, Hume, in the book that he wrote when he was
twenty-three years old. That's the only honest version of it and everything
after that is a fraud.
The way it goes is this: I ask the question whether there is a
substantial glass, an objective glass, a material glass, something that is
over and above the visual glass of the moment. When first considered
this seems to be a question which I have no method of answering. That
would seem to place it like a Kantian metaphysical question which
doesn't have a provable solution, though interestingly enough Kant
thought that the existence of the external world in general could be
proved but only in the second edition. And in that second edition in
those little passages, Kant did really get into the existence of this
individual thing like a unicornand how that would or would not fit into
the general proof of the existence of the world and also the question of
how dreams would affect the validity of the proof. He touches on all of
those in a way which is just awful. It's a disgraceful performance. But he
had the issue there, actually.
Well, your first reaction is, "I have no way of answering this." Your
second reaction is, that \emph{if I understand the question}, then there must be
an external world. So it would seem that I have actually proved the
external world---that's what Kant actually said. Or he came very near
to saying something like that. The third step is the realization that the
statement would validate itself not only if it's true---but if it's false it
validates itself equally well!
\speaker{HENNIX} Given this method of understanding the question. And the
method remained unspecified so far---as far as I know nobody has been
able to do very well at specifying it.
\speaker{FLYNT} What? Do you mean if somebody asks whether there is an
external world---my last remark is a comment about semantics---the
genuine semantic issue, as I said, and it's very different from the sort of
thing that Tarski is going on about which I think is just ridiculous.
Maybe I'd better stop and tell you why I think it's ridiculous. It's
because I'm now talking about things which are exactly the fundamen-
tal issues. If Tarski thinks that he can talk about the theory of chess
before the question of whether the universe exists or not has been
answered---they are deliberately creating specialized problems which in
their minds do have answers and then they are proceeding to answer
them. The larger question of whether the work has any meaning at
all---it's like somebody spending his whole life working on the King's
Indian defense in chess or something like that, and thinking that
somehow that makes it unnecessary to answer such questions as does
the chess board exist or is it only apparitional? If it's only apparitional
then there is no guarantee of the continuity of the position of the pieces
in the absence of moves. What happens is that people treat those basic
questions as if they are so basic that it's sort of preposterous to make an
issue of them. Kripke said very clearly in his book on Wittgenstein that
once the question, "Does language exist?" has been asked, not to give
an affirmative answer is "insane and intolerable."\footnote{S. Kripke,
\booktitle{Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language}, p.60}
It's the same reaction as there is to solipsism---that solipsism is the philosophy of the
man in the lunatic asylum.
The thing that may come before all the discussion so far is the
question of \emph{what is my position on being classified as insane} is the
beginning This of philosophy for me.
\speaker{HENNIX} Well, this is the classical beginning of philosophy.
\speaker{FLYNT} Because if you're not willing to face up to being classified as
insane---if you want to avoid that confrontation---you can't be a
philosopher. That confrontation is at the center of bona fide philosophy.
\speaker{HENNIX} Or was\ldots
\speaker{FLYNT} Yes. At any rate, I had reached this point in something like
1961. I had not yet done \essaytitlte{The "Is There Language?" Trap}. But I had reached
the point of saying that to claim the existence of a world beyond
experience is untenable. However I understood very well that it begins
to create problems for me to say, \textquote{I have a visual glass apparition,}
because there is a lot of structure in that sentence. And it's not clear
what is supporting that structure after the world has been cut away.
Even the use of the idioms like "have" and "suffer." The use of the word
"I"---after the objective world has been cut away it's unclear what is the
basis for all of that. And this is the point I had reached in 1961 and this is
the point when I did \essaytitle{Concept Art}.
On the one hand you have an art which is about structure and
conceptual things. On the other hand this art is not going to \emph{affirm}
traditional doctrines of structuredness and conceptualization. It is
deliberately in every case going to violate them. It is going to express the
fact that there has been a philosophical discovery made. I would have
said chess is not a sound game. It's not well founded. It can't be. The
whole problem of Wittgenstein's famous question---what is the meaning
of a rule? My answer would be it doesn't have one. When you look
at it from the standpoint of Hume when he says I have become a
monster, I am outside the human race---the standpoint of the person
who chooses insanity as opposed to intellectual dishonesty!
The person who chooses being a madman---even chess doesn't
work. The whole question of its consistency. The point of Concept Art
is on the one hand to transmit the tradition from the isorhythmic motet
and the five Platonic solids, in Leonardo---and on the other it's to blow
it up because each work of concept art must be a counter-example to
that tradition. And at the same time to say that it is art means---when I
passed to \essaytitle{Concept Art} I left behind many things that traditionally
would have been considered crucial features of art, like sentiment, for
example. Let me just leave it at that.
When the Renaissance people did study geometry and art, they
developed perspective to paint people, not to paint abstractions. And
you know I have to admit quite bluntly, my Concept Art was already
the product of the acceptance of an abstract art. And now, many years
later I can see that that was an historical juncture, to consider it
tolerable that art should break with sentiment and with the representation
of people. It's like moving toward an Islamic view of art. And then
saying, now however, in the future, instead of Mosque decoration we
will do a piece that has the visual, sensuous delectation, but it's completely
abstract. But whereas Islamic art was trying to express the
\emph{truth} of a certain theorem in group theory, Concept Art must express
that you can't have that---that that theorem fails. Now I'm formulating
an unsolved problem---I never did a concept piece the purpose of which
was to rebut the symmetry involved in a visual pattern, with that as the
opponent to be hit. I mean I very well could and perhaps should.
All of my pieces were uninterpreted calculi. Because I accepted
that that was the only way of explaining what mathematics is: that it
consists of a body of truth about a world that does \emph{not} exist, and
explicitly so. And that all of the traditional explanations of mathematical
content are now seen to be anachronistic superstitions. They are just
indefensible in the modern world. Put those two things together and
mathematics becomes a chess game, an uninterpreted calculus.
All of my Concept pieces are using the terminology of Carnap's
\booktitle{Logical Syntax of Language}---the formation rule, the transformation
rule---but in each case they wish to express the violation, the failure of
some traditional organizing principle of these uninterpreted calculi,
For instance there is one where, among other things, the very notation
itself has an undisplaced active interaction with the subjectivity of the
quote unquote reader.\footnote{dated 6/19/61---later titled "Illusions."}
And that determines the structure of the derivation, the proof.
It was pointed out to me many years later that it's not
just that you don't get this in schoolbook mathematics---this is what
they are most concerned to exclude.
I had another one, in which there was no general transformation
rule.\footnote{\essaytitle{Transformations}, retitled \essaytitle{Implications} in the second edition.}
There were only completely nominalistic transformation rules,
In other words, for each step you are told, for that step only and for this
moment only, what the transformation rule is. And by the time you are
ready to take the next step, that rule is forgotten and inoperative.
\speaker{HENNIX} This is the \essaytitle{Energy Cube Organism}?
\speaker{FLYNT} No, no. \essaytitle{The Energy Cube Organism} was not Concept Art at
all. No, no. It was a different genre. That one was the piece called
\essaytitle{Transformations}.
\essaytitle{The Energy Cube Organism} and the \essaytitle{Perception-Dissociator} in my
own classification are not Concept Art. Only the pieces labeled
"Concept Art" are Concept Art. And I only did four of them until 1987.
Three of them are in \booktitle{An Anthology}, and the fourth was published in
\journaltitle{dimension 14} (1963). \essaytitle{The Energy Cube Organism} and the
\essaytitle{Perception-Dissociator} were in other genres. I drew these distinctions of genre
rather narrowly, actually.
This is the one \action{pointing to 6/19/61 in \booktitle{An Anthology}} where there
is, in an uninterpreted calculus, interaction between notation and the
subjectivity of the quote unquote reader.
This is \essaytitle{Transformations.} You are just taking these objects, you
are burning them, melting them, doing all sorts of things to them. The
point of this is that each step in the proof---you have to think of it as a
proof---you see it has the tree structure of a proof. This is my nominalistic
transformation rules, because each rule is stipulated only at that
step, and then it is thrown away. The point that I was trying to express
was that's what they do in all of it---even in chess, when you move the
pawn to King's Bishop 3, you think that you are conforming to a
general rule written in Heaven. But in fact there isn't any general rule,
and when you move the pawn to Bishop 3, you're just making up what
you are doing right at that moment, and there isn't any general rule.
\speaker{HENNIX} You would label this ad hoc?
\speaker{FLYNT} That's right. That would be perhaps a better word for it. All
transformation rules and probably even all formation rules are ad hoc,
yes, yes.
I said "nominalistic" because they are only there individually.
They do not add up to any general---
\speaker{HENNIX} System of rules?
\speaker{FLYNT} No---not that---they do not add up to any generality, to a
general rule that covers all cases of a certain class.
What is inadequate about this---and I realized very quickly that
it's inadequate---is that this does not actually give some profound
reason in concrete practice for questioning chess. That's what the
inadequacy of the original Concept Art pieces is. That they don't really
give you some kind of operative situation where you can see that
following the chess rules is failing. I don't provide that. I only provide
something that's ritualistic. Saying this is how you would behave if you
realized that following any rule is ad hoc.
A conventional mathematician would say, you have not proved
that the world that this is designed for is the world that I have to live in.
\textsc{That}'s the inadequacy. He would say that I am only ritualizing the
world of impoverishment or disorganization. I'm not showing that
that's the world that people in general have to live in because it's in
force. That's the difference between then and now. The reason that I
want meta-technology would be to give a situation where somebody
can actually see that you \textsc{Can't} play a game of chess---or that you want
to play one and that I, by putting it in the appropriate context, make it
clear that the general rules on which playing it depends are not in fact
available.
But to show that in a serious way. From the prevailing point of
view I would be talking about contriving a miracle. In other words, to
actually substantiate any of these---what is interesting is not so much
\essaytitle{Transformations}---but it would be some situation that would substantiate
that the conventional view is actually unavailable. And to do
that you have to violate what are considered today to be the soundest
laws of science. I'd need a miracle to manifest that I'm right, so to
speak. So by the time I get to meta-technology I'm in the job of
constructing miracles, I mean constructing situations that are
absolutely physically impossible (or in some cases logically impossible) by
currently accepted scientific and commonsense views of what is the real
world.
\essaytitle{Innperseqs} is the one that is visually sensuously the best. You are
making a rainbow halo that you can get by breathing on your glasses
and looking at a point light---you get a rainbow halo around the light.
Eventually I will set it up so that you don't need glasses or anything so
that the whole business of seeing the rainbow halo is moved out and
does not require any special preparation by the spectator. The rainbow
halo is the sensuous delectation. The derivation, the proof, the
specification of propositions, is something that you do as the halo is fading.
You have to quickly specify---I never analyzed exactly what was going
on there but it was as if---you have a notation which is externally
changing, and therefore the quote unquote reading of a mathematical
system has to be a process that is taking place in experienced time.
By acts of attention you have to choose sentences, to choose
implications---it's a display. You are given an external display which is
changing out there, not in your head. And you have to place a structure
on it by specified rules.
You know another point that can be made is, that \essaytitle{Innperseqs} is
philosophically inconsistent with \essaytitle{Transformations}---that these pieces
are mocking each other.
At the time that I did this, I did not have the kind of maturity that I
would have today to put it together in a strong way. These were
gestures. And they are not even uniform ona question like whether a
rule exists or not. Well actually, frequently I'm too hard on myself. I
think that in the essay \essaytitle{Concept Art} I do say something like, objective
language doesn't exist, but I'm still free to work with what you think the
text says---I can use that in \emph{art}: this is \emph{art}!
There are three ways that the art part comes in. One is the visual
display, the delectation. The second way the art part comes in is---well,
if LaMonte Young's Word Pieces are art, then this is art too. But the
third thing is that this does not claim to have objective truth. It is a
construction for the world-hallucination or the world-apparition or
even a construction for the private world-apparition.
\speaker{HENNIX} You are actually extending the world by new constructions.
\speaker{FLYNT} But it's the world-apparition. In a sense if I believed that these
rules were objectively established, then it would almost indicate that I
had not learned the lesson of the very piece which sits beside it on the
page!\footnote{\essaytitle{Innperseqs} versus \essaytitle{{Transformations,} second edition.}
And what am I doing talking about a page and a text? So the
answer is that I have abandoned the provision of truth as the purpose of
this activity and I have moved to the provision of experiences where the
possibility of these experiences is a surprise.
\speaker{HENNIX} And you don't have to be an empiricist to be surprised.
\speaker{FLYNT} Yes. Yes. But the truth claim that you would have from a
Kripke or a Goodman has been dropped. The meaning of the text is the
meaning that the reader associates to it. And the thing is, that in
conventional intellectual work that's an unacceptable answer, because
usually you are trying to get independent of the reader's
distortion---that's the whole hope---that you can make something that is
independent of the reader's distortion of it. This is a different game. This is not
classical mathematics; it's not classical science. It's like giving a
Rorschach blot. Then I don't mind if you have a unique subjective reaction.
If my purpose is to make Rorschach blots, then I do not object, I have
not failed, if you have a unique personal reaction.
These pieces are designed for the individual reaction rather than in
spite of it.
The only other Concept Art piece---in \journaltitle{dimension 14}---\enquote{one just
has to guess whether this piece exists and if it does what its definition
is.} That was the piece. And that was a response to Cage's dissociation
of what the composer sees, the performer sees, the audience sees.
Starting from that, going through all the games that LaMonte had
played with the idea of performance, where we were performing pieces
first and composing them second, maybe many months later. So finally
with the Concept Art piece, even whether the piece exists is completely
indeterminate, but I meant for people to try to take that seriously. I was
having a joke with the person who thinks that concepts form an
objective world, which the individual who cognizes only discovers bit
by bit. In effect, 1am giving him this: thank you for believing that there
is a piece here---I'm leaving it to you to find it. I wash my hands of that
Problem---\emph{you} find it!
Well, there's a natural pause that comes here because I think that
I've summarized perhaps fairly thoroughly where I was when I did the
work published in 1963. The entire subsequent career of the label
Concept Art, its misapplication to Word Pieces and all the rest of it, we
have not begun with. After that, we can go on to the discussion of your
visual pieces of the 70s and how they resume the genre of Concept Art.
|