summaryrefslogtreecommitdiffstats
path: root/essays/some_objections.tex
diff options
context:
space:
mode:
Diffstat (limited to 'essays/some_objections.tex')
-rw-r--r--essays/some_objections.tex159
1 files changed, 159 insertions, 0 deletions
diff --git a/essays/some_objections.tex b/essays/some_objections.tex
new file mode 100644
index 0000000..1954d9e
--- /dev/null
+++ b/essays/some_objections.tex
@@ -0,0 +1,159 @@
+\chapter{Some Objections to My Philosophy}
+
+
+\textbf{A.} The predominant attitude toward philosophical questions in
+educated circles today derives from the later Wittgenstein. Consider the
+philosopher's question of whether other people have minds. The
+Wittgensteinian attitude is that in ordinary usage, statements which imply
+that other people have minds are not problematic. Everybody knows that
+other people have minds. To doubt that other people have minds, as a
+philosopher might do, is simply to misuse ordinary language. (See
+Philosophical Investigations, \S 420.) Statements which imply that other
+people have minds works perfectly well in the context for which they were
+intended. When philosophers find these statements problematic, it is because
+they subject the statements to criticism by logical standards which are
+irrelevant and extraneous to ordinary usage. (\S \S 402, 412, 119, 116.)
+
+For Wittgenstein, the existence of God, immortal souls, other minds,
+and the Empire State Building (when I am not looking at it) are all things
+which everybody knows; things which it is impossible to doubt "in a real
+case." (\S 303, Iliv. For Wittgenstein's theism, see Norman Malcolm's
+memoir.) The proper use of language admits of no alternative to belief in
+God; atheism is just a mistake in the use of language.
+
+
+In arguing against Wittgenstein, I will concentrate on the real reason
+why I oppose him, rather than on less fundamental technical issues. We read
+that in the Middle Ages, people found it impossible not to believe that they
+would be struck by lightning if they uttered a blasphemy; just as
+Wittgenstein finds the existence of God impossible to doubt "in a real case."
+Yet even Wittgenstein does not defend the former belief; while the Soviet
+Union has shown that a government can function which has repudiated the
+latter belief. There is a tremendous discovery here: that beliefs which were as
+inescapable---as impossible to doubt in a real case---as any belief we may have
+today, were subsequently discarded. How was this possible? My essay \essaytitle{The
+Flaws Underlying Beliefs} shows how. Further, it shows that the belief that
+the Empire State Building exists when I am not looking at it, or the belief
+that I would be killed if I jumped out of a tenth story window, are no
+different in principle from beliefs which we have already discarded. It Is
+perfectly possible to project a metaphysical outlook on experience which is
+totally different from the beliefs Wittgenstein inherited, and it is also
+possible not to project a metaphysical outlook on experience at all. Let us be
+absolutely clear: the point is not that we do not know with one hundred per
+cent certainty that the Empire State Building exists; the point is that we
+need not believe in the Empire State Building at all. \essaytitle{The Flaws Underlying
+Beliefs} shows that factual propositions, and the propositions of the natural
+sciences, involve outright self-deception.
+
+These discoveries have consequences far more important than the
+technical issues involved. It is by no means trivial that I do not have to pray,
+or to fast, or to accept the moral dictates of the clergy, or to give money to
+the Church. Because the Church prohibited the dissection of human
+cadavers, it took an atheist to originate the modern subject of anatomy. In
+analogy with this example, the rest of my writings are devoted to exploring
+the consequences of rejecting beliefs that Wittgenstein says are impossible to
+doubt in a real case, as in my essay \essaytitle{Philosophical Aspects of Walking
+Through Walls.} I oppose Wittgenstein because he descended to extremes of
+intellectual dishonesty in order to prevent us from discovering these
+consequences.
+
+A reply to the Wittgensteinian attitude which is technically adequate
+can be provided in short order, for when Wittgenstein's central philosophical
+maneuver is identified, its dishonesty becomes transparent. It is not
+necessary to enumerate the fallacies in the Wittgensteinian claim that logical
+connections and logical standards are extrinsic to the natural language, or in
+the aphorism that "the meaning is the use" (as an explication of the natural
+language). In other words, there is no reason why I should bandy descriptive
+linguistics with Wittgenstein. Wittgenstein was wrong at a level more basic
+than the level on which his philosophical discussions were conducted.
+
+Wittgenstein held that philosophical or metaphysical controversies
+literally would not arise if it were not for bad philosophers. They would not
+arise because there is nothing problematic about sentences, expressing
+Wittgenstein's inherited beliefs, in ordinary usage. This rhetorical maneuver
+is the inverse of what it seems to be. Wittgenstein doesn't prove that the
+paradoxes uncovered by "bad" philosophers result from a misuse of ordinary
+language; he defines the philosophers' discussions as a misuse of ordinary
+language because they uncover paradoxes is ordinary language propositions.
+Wittgenstein waits to see whether a philosopher uncovers problems in
+ordinary language propositions; and if the philosopher does so, then
+Wittgenstein defines his discussion as improper usage. Wittgenstein waits to
+see whether evidence is against his side, and if it is, he defines it as
+inadmissible.
+
+Consider the philosopher's question of how I know whether the \textsc{Empire
+State Building} continues to exist when I am not looking at it. The
+Wittgensteinian position on this question would be that it is problematic
+because it is a misuse of ordinary language; and because there is no
+behavioral context which constitutes a use for the question. According to
+this position, we would not encounter such problems if we would use
+ordinary language properly. But what does this position amount to? The
+philosopher's question has not been proved improper; it has been defined as
+improper because it leads to problems. The reason why "the proper use of
+ordinary language never leads to paradoxes" is that Wittgenstein has defined
+proper use as use in which no paradoxes are visible. Wittgenstein has not
+resolved or eliminated any problems; he has just refused to notice them.
+Wittgenstein attempts to pass off, as a discovery about philosophy and
+language, a gratuitous definition to the effect that certain portions of the
+natural language which embarrass him are inadmissible, a gratuitous ban on
+certain portions of the natural language which embarrass him. His purpose is
+to make criticism of his inherited beliefs impossible, to give them a spurious
+inescapability. Wittgenstein's maneuver is the last word in modish
+intellectual dishonesty.
+
+\gap
+
+\textbf{B.} In philosophy, arguments which start from an immediate which
+cannot be doubted and attempt to prove the existence of an objective reality
+are called transcendental arguments. Typically, such an argument says that if
+there is experience, there must be subject and object in experience; if there
+are subject and object, subject and object must be objectively real; and thus
+there must be objectively real mind and matter. Clearly, the belief which
+leaps the gap from the immediate to the objectively real is smuggled into the
+middle of the argument by a play on the words \enquote{subject} and \enquote{object.}
+
+When the sophistry is cleared away, it becomes apparent that the
+attempt to attain the trans-experiential or extra-experiential within
+experience faces a dilemma of overkill. If the attempt could succeed, it
+would have only collapsed objective reality to my subjectivity. If it could be
+"proved" that I know the distant past, other minds, God, angels, archangels,
+etc. from immediate experience, then all these phenomena would be
+trivialized. If other minds were given in my experience, they would only be
+my mind. The interest of the notion of objective reality is precisely its
+otherness and unreachability. If it could be reached from the immediate, it
+would be trivial. We ask how I know that the Empire State Building exists
+when I am not looking at it. If the answer is that I know through immediate
+experience, then objective reality has been collapsed to my subjectivity. The
+dilemma for transcendental arguments is that they propose to overcome the
+gap between the appearance of a thing and the thing itself, yet they do not
+want to conclude that appearances exhaust reality.
+
+There are two special assumptions which are smuggled into supposedly
+assumptionless transcendental arguments. First, there is the belief that there
+is an objective relationship between descriptive words and the things they
+describe, an objective criterion of the use of descriptive words. Secondly,
+there is the belief that correlations between the senses have an objective
+basis. (It is claimed that this belief cannot be doubted, but the claim is
+controverted by intersensory illusions such as the touching of a pencil with
+crossed fingers.)
+
+Transcendental arguments are secular theology, because they are
+addressed to a reader who wants only philosophical analyses that have
+conventional conclusions. A transcendental argument will contain a step
+such as the following, for example. We can have "real knowledge" of
+particular things only if there is an objective relationship between descriptive
+words and the things they describe; thus there must be such a relationship.
+This argument is plausible only if the reader can be trusted to overlook the
+alternative that we don't have this "real knowledge."
+
+In the way of supplementary remarks, we may mention that
+transcendental arguments typically commit the ontological fallacy: inferring
+the existence of a thing from the idea or name of the thing. Finally,
+transcendental arguments share a confusion which originates in the
+empiricism they are directed against: the confusion between doing
+fundamental philosophy and doing the psychology of perception. Many
+transcendental arguments are similar to current doctrines in scientific
+psychology. But they fail as philosophy, because scientific psychology takes
+as presuppositions, and cannot prove, the very beliefs which transcendental
+arguments are supposed to prove.
+