summaryrefslogtreecommitdiffstats
diff options
context:
space:
mode:
-rw-r--r--blueprint.tex7701
-rw-r--r--essays/down_with_art.tex2
-rw-r--r--essays/letters.tex16
3 files changed, 59 insertions, 7660 deletions
diff --git a/blueprint.tex b/blueprint.tex
index 543868d..bf286d3 100644
--- a/blueprint.tex
+++ b/blueprint.tex
@@ -1,4 +1,4 @@
-\documentclass[10pt,twoside]{memoir}
+\documentclass[10pt,twoside,draft]{memoir}
\usepackage{salitter}
\usletterlayout
@@ -11,8 +11,12 @@
\usepackage{xfrac}
\usepackage{ulem}
+% fonts
\coelfont
+% \usepackage{cabin}
+% \newfontfamily{\specialheadersfont}{Cabin}
+
\newcommand{\speech}[1]{
\textquote{\emph{#1}}}
@@ -71,7683 +75,78 @@
\includegraphics[width=1em]{img/cubedown}}
\begin{document}
-
+\frontmatter
\graphicspath{{img/}}
\pagestyle{ruled}
\chapterstyle{tandh}
\openany
-{
+% Title
\thispagestyle{empty}
-\img{creep.png}
-
-Henry Flynt presents "Creep" lecture in Adam Hovre upper common room, Harvard
-University, May 15, 1962
-
-
-(photo by Tony Conrad)
-\clearpage
-}
-
-\tableofcontents*
-
-\mainmatter
-
-\chapter{Introduction}
-
-
-This essay is the third in a series on the rationale of my career. It
-summarizes the results of my activities, the consistent outlook on a whole
-range of questions which I have developed. The first essay,
-\essaytitle{On Social Recognition}, noted that the official social philosophy of practically every
-regime in the world says that the individual has a duty to serve society to the
-best of his abilities. Social recognition is supposed to be the reward which
-indicates that the individual is indeed serving society. Now it happens that
-the most important tasks the individual can undertake are tasks (intellectual,
-political, and otherwise) posed by society. However, when the individual
-undertakes such tasks, society's actual response is almost always persecution
-(Galileo) or indifference (Mendel). Thus, the doctrine that the'individual has
-a duty to serve society is a hypocritical fraud. I reject every social
-philosophy which contains this doctrine. The rational individual will obtain
-the means of subsistence by the most efficient swindle he can find. Beyond
-this, he will undertake the most important tasks posed by society for his
-own private gratification. He will not attempt to benefit society, or to gain
-the recognition which would necessarily result if society were to utilize his
-achievements.
-
-The second essay, \essaytitle{Creep}, discussed the practices of isolating oneself;
-carefully controlling one's intake of ideas and influences from outside; and
-playing as a child does. I originally saw these practices as the effects of
-certain personality problems. However, it now seems that they are actually
-needed for the intellectual approach which I have developed. They may be
-desirable in themselves, rather than being mere effects of personality
-problems.
-
-I chose fundamental philosophy as my primary subject of investigation.
-Society presses me to accept all sorts of beliefs. At one time it would have
-pressed me to believe that the earth was flat; then it reversed itself and
-demanded that I believe the earth is round. The majority of Americans still
-consider it "necessary" to believe in God; but the Soviet government has
-managed to function for decades with an atheistic philosophy. Thus, which
-beliefs should I accept? My analysis is presented in writings entitled
-\essaytitle{Philosophy Proper}, \essaytitle{The Flaws Underlying Beliefs}, and
-\essaytitle{Philosophical Aspects of Walking Through Walls}.
-The question of whether a given belief is valid
-depends on the issue of whether there is a realm beyond my "immediate
-experience." Does the Empire State Building continue to exist even when I
-am not looking at it? If such a question can be asked, there must indeed be
-a realm beyond my experience, because otherwise the phrase 'a realm
-beyond my experience' could not have any meaning. (Russell's theory of
-descriptions does not apply in this case.) But if the assertion that there is a
-realm beyond my experience is true merely because it is meaningful, it
-cannot be substantive; it must be a definitional trick. In general, beliefs
-depend on the assertion of the existence of a realm beyond my experience,
-an assertion which is nonsubstantive. Thus, beliefs are nonsubstantive or
-meaningless; they are definitional tricks. Psychologically, when I believe that
-the Empire State Building exists even though I am not looking at it, I
-imagine the Empire State Building, and I have the attitude toward this
-mental picture that it is a perception rather than a mental! picture. The
-attitude involved is a self-deceiving psychological trick which corresponds to
-the definitional trick in the belief assertion. The conclusion is that al! beliefs
-are inconsistent or self-deceiving. It would be beside the point to doubt
-beliefs, because whatever their connotations may be, logically beliefs are
-nonsense, and their negations are nonsense also.
-
-The important consequence of my philosophy is the rejection of truth
-as an intellectual modality. I conclude that an intellectual activity's claim to
-have objective value should not depend on whether it is true; and also that
-an activity may perfectly weil employ false statements and still have
-objective value. I have developed activities which use mental capabilities that
-are excluded by a truth-oriented approach: descriptions of imaginary
-phenomena, the deliberate adoption of false expectations, the thinking of
-contradictions, and meanings which are reversed by the reader's mental
-reactions; as well as illusions, the deliberate suspension of normal beliefs, and
-phrases whose meaning is stipulated to be the associations they evoke. It
-must be clear that these activities are not in any way whatever a return to
-pre-scientific trrationalism. My philosophy demolishes astrology even more
-than it does astronomy. The irrationalist is out to deceive you; he wants you
-to believe that his superstitions are truths. My activities, on the other hand,
-explicitly state that they are using non-true material. My intent is not to get
-you to believe that superstitions are truths, but to exploit non-true material
-for rational purposes.
-
-The other initial subject of investigation I chose was art. The art which
-claims to have cognitive value is already demolished by my philosophical
-results. However, art at its most distinctive does not need to claim cognitive
-value; its value is claimed to be entertainmental or amusemental. What about
-art whose justification is simply that people like it? Consider things which
-are just liked, or whose value is purely subjective. I point out that each
-individual already has experiences, prior to art, whose value is purely
-subjective. (Call these experiences "brend.") The difference between brend
-and art is that in art, the thing valued is separated from the valuing of it and
-turned into an object which is urged on other people. Individuals tend to
-overlook their brend, and they do so because of the same factors which
-perpetuate art. These factors include the relation between the socialization
-of the individual and the need for an escape from work. The conditioning
-which causes one to venerate "great art" is also a conditioning to dismiss
-one's own brend. If one can become aware of one's brend without the
-distortion produced by this conditioning, one finds that one's brend is
-superior to any art, because it has a level of personalization and originality
-which completely transcends art.
-
-Thus, I reject art as an intellectual or cultural modality. In rejecting
-truth, I advocated in its place intellectual activities which have an objective
-value independent of truth. In rejecting art, I do not propose that it be
-replaced with any objective activity at all. Rather, I advocate that the
-individual become aware of his just-likings for what they are, and allow them
-to come out. If I succeed in getting the individual to recognize his own
-just-likings, then I will have given him infinitely more than any artist ever
-can.
-
-We are not finished with art, however. Ever since art began to
-disintegrate as an institution, modern art has become more and more of a
-repository for activities which represent pure waste, but which counterfeit
-innovation and objective value. A two-way process is involved here. On the
-one hand, the modern artist, faced with the increasing gratuitousness of his
-profession, desperately incorporates superficial references to science in his
-products in the hope of intimidating his audience. On the other hand, art
-itself has become an institution which invests waste with legitimacy and even
-prestige; and it offers instant rewards to people who wish to play the game.
-What is innovation in modern art? You take a poem by Shelly, cut it up into
-little pieces, shake the pieces up in a box, then draw them out and write
-down whatever is on them in the order in which they are drawn. If you call
-the result a "modern poem," people will suddenly be awed by it, whereas
-they would not have been awed otherwise. This sort of innovation is utterly
-mechanical and superficial. When artists incorporate scientific references in
-their products, the process is similarly a mechanical, superficial
-amalgamation of routine artistic material with current gadgets.
-
-Now there may be some confusion as to what the difference is between
-the products which result from this attempt to "save" art, and activities in
-the intellectual modality which I favor. There may be a tendency to confuse
-activities which are neither science nor art, but have objective value, with art
-products which are claimed to be "scientific" and therefore objectively
-valuable. To dispel this confusion, the following questions may be asked
-about art products.
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item If the product were not called art, would it immediately be seen to be
-worthless? Does the product rely on artistic institutions to "carry" it?
-
-\item Suppose that the artist claims that his product embodies major scientific
-discoveries, as in the case of a ballet dancer who claims to be working in the
-field of antigravity ballet. If the dancer really has an antigravity device,
-why can it only work in a ballet theater? Why can it
-only be used to make dancers jump higher? Why do you have to be able to
-perform "Swan Lake" in order to do antigravity experiments?
-\end{enumerate}
-To use a phrase from medical research, I contend that a real scientist would seek to
-isolate the active principle---not to obscure it with non-functional mumbo-jumbo.
-
-Both of these sets of questions make the same point, from somewhat
-different perspectives. Given an individual with a product to offer, does he
-actively seek out the lady art reporters, the public relations contracts, the
-museum officials, or does he actively dissociate himself from them? Does he
-seek artistic legitimation of his product, or does he reject it? The objective
-activities which I have developed stand on their own feet. They are not art,
-and to construe them as art would make it impossible to comprehend them.
-
-A definition of the intellectual modality which I favor is now in order.
-Until now, this modality has involved the construction of ideas such that the
-very possibility of thinking these ideas is a significant phenomenon. In other
-words, the modality has consisted of the invention of mental abilities. The
-ideas involve physical language, that is, language which occurs in beliefs
-about the physical world. Such language is philosophically meaningless, but
-it has connotations provided by the psychological trick involved in believing.
-The connotations are what are utilized; factual truth is irrelevant. Then, the
-ideas cannot be reduced to the mechanical manipulation of marks or
-counters---unlike ordinary mathematics. Also, logical truth, which happens to
-be discredited by my philosophical results, is irrelevant to the ideas.
-
-But the defining requirement of the modality is that each activity in it
-must have objective value. The activity must provide one with something
-which is useful irrespective of whether one likes it; that is, which is useful
-independently of whether it produces emotional gratification.
-
-We can now consider the following principle. "spontaneously and
-without any prompting to sweep human culture aside and to carry out
-elaborate, completely self-justifying activities." Relative to the social context
-of the individual's activities, this principle is absurd. We have no reason to
-respect the eccentric hobbyist, or the person who engages in arbitrary
-antisocial acts. If an action is to have more than merely personal significance,
-it must have a social justification, as is explained in On Social Recognition.
-In the light of The Flaws Underlying Beliefs and the brend theory, however,
-the principle mentioned above does become valid when it is interpreted
-correctly, because it becomes necessary to invent ends as well as means. The
-activity must provide an objective value, but this value will no longer be
-standardized.
-
-The modality I favor is best exemplified by \essaytitle{Energy Cube Organism},
-\essaytitle{Concept Art}, and the \essaytitle{Perception-Dissociator Model}.
-\essaytitle{Energy Cube Organism} is a perfect example of ideas such that the very
-possibility of thinking them is a significant phenomenon. It is also a perfect example of an
-activity which is useful irrespective of whether it provides emotional
-gratification. It combines the description of imaginary physical phenomena
-with the thinking of contradictions. It led to \essaytitle{Studies in Constructed
-Memories}, which in turn led to \essaytitle{The Logic of Admissible Contradictions}.
-With this last writing, it becomes obvious that the activity has applications
-outside itself.
-
-\essaytitle{Concept Art}\footnote{published in An Anthology ed. LaMonte Young, 1963}
-uses linguistic expressions which are changed by the reader's mental
-reactions. It led to \essaytitle{Post-Formalism in Constructed Memories}, and this led
-in turn to \essaytitle{Subjective Propositional Vibration}.
-
-The \essaytitle{Perception-Dissociator Model}\footnote{published in I-KON, Vol. 1, No. 5}
-was intended to exploit the realization that humans are the most
-advanced machines (or technology) that we have. I wanted to build a model
-of a machine out of humans, using a minimum of non-human props. Further,
-the machine modelled was to have capabilities which are physically
-impossible according to present-day science. I still think that the task as I
-have defined it is an excellent one; but the model does not yet completely
-accomplish the objective. The present model uses the deliberate suspension
-of normal beliefs to produce its effects.
-
-\essaytitle{Post-Formalism in Constructed Memories} and \essaytitle{Studies in
-Constructed Memories} together make up \booktitle{Mathematical Studies} (1966). In
-this monograph, the emphasis was on extending the idea of mathematics as
-formalistic games to games involving subjectivity and contradiction. In two
-subsequent monographs, the material was developed so as to bring out its
-potential applications in conjunction with science.
-\essaytitle{Subjective Propositional Vibration} investigates the logical
-possibilities of expressions which are changed by the reader's mental responses.
-\essaytitle{The Logic of Admissible Contradictions} starts with the experiences
-of the logically impossible which
-we have when we suffer certain perceptual illusions. These illusions enable us
-to imagine certain logical impossibilities just as clearly as we imagine the
-logically possible. The monograph models the content of these illusions to
-obtain a system of logic in which some (but not all) contradictions are
-"admissible." The theory investigates the implications of admitting some
-contradictions for the admissibility of other contradictions. A theory of
-many-valued numbers is also presented.
-
-The \essaytitle{Perception-Dissociator Model} led to
-\essaytitle{The Perception-Dissociation of Physics.} Again, here is an essay whose
-significance lies in the very possibility of thinking the ideas at all. The essay
-defines a change in the pattern of experience which would make it
-impossibie for physicists to "construct the object from experience." Finally,
-\essaytitle{Mock Risk Games} is the activity which involves the deliberate adoption of
-false expectations. It is on the borderline of the intellectual modality which I
-favor, because it seems to me to have objective value, and yet has not
-generated a series of applications as the other activities have.
-
-To summarize my general outlook, truth and art are discredited. They
-are replaced by an intellectual modality consisting of non-true activities
-having objective value, together with cach individual's brend. Consider the
-individual who wishes to go into my intellectual modality. What is the
-significance to him of the academic world, professional occupations, and the
-business of scholarships, fellowships, and grants? From the perspective of
-the most socially important tasks, these institutions have always rewarded
-the wrong things, as I argued in \essaytitle{On Social Recognition}. But in addition, the
-institutions as now organized are obstacles specifically to my intellectual
-modality. In fact, society in general has the effect of a vast conspiracy to
-prevent one from achieving the kind of consequential intellectual play which
-I advocate. The categories of thought which are obligatory in the official
-intellectual world and the media are categories in which my outlook cannot
-be conceived. And here is where the creep practices mentioned at the
-beginning of this essay become important. Isolation from society is
-presumably not inherent in my intelectual modality; but under present
-social conditions isolation is a prerequisite for its existence.
-
-
-\part{Philosophy}
-
-
-\chapter{The Flaws Underlying Beliefs}
-
-
-We begin with the question of whether there is a realm beyond my
-"immediate experience." Does the Empire State Building continue to exist
-even when I am not looking at it? If either of these questions can be asked,
-then there must indeed be a realm beyond my experience. If I can ask
-whether there is a realm beyond my experience, then the answer must be
-yes. The reason is that there has to be a realm beyond my experience in
-order for the phrase "a realm beyond my experience" to have any meaning.
-Russell's theory of descriptions will not work here; it cannot jump the gap
-between my experience and the realm beyond my experience. The assertion
-\speech{There is a realm beyond my experience} is true if it is meaningful, and that
-is precisely what is wrong with it. There are rules implicit in the natura!
-language as to what is semantically legitimate. Without a rule that a
-statement and its negation cannot simultaneously be true, for example, the
-natural language would be in such chaos that nothing could be done with it.
-Aristotle's \booktitle{Organon} was the first attempt to explicate this structure formally,
-and Supplement D of Carnap's \booktitle{Meaning and Necessity} shows that hypotheses
-about the implicit rules of a natural language are well-defined and testable.
-An example of implicit semantics is the aphorism that \enquote{saying a thing is so
-doesn't make it so.} This aphorism has been carried over into the semantics
-of the physical sciences: its import is that there is no such thing as a
-substantive assertion which is true merely because it is meaningful. If a
-statement is true merely because it is meaningful, then it is too true. It must
-be some kind of definitional trick which doesn't say anything. And this is
-our conclusion about the assertion that there is a realm beyond my
-experience. Since it would be true if it were meaningful, it cannot be a
-substantive assertion.
-
-The methodology of this paper requires special comment. Because we
-are considering ultimate questions, it is pointless to try to support our
-argument on some more basic, generally accepted account of logic, language,
-and cognition. After all, such accounts are being called into question here.
-The only possible pproach for this paper is an internal critique of common
-sense and the natural language, one which judges them by reference to
-aspects of themselves.
-
-As an example of the application of our initial result to specific
-questions of belief, consider the question of whether the Empire State
-Building continues to exist when I am not looking at it. If this question is
-even meaningful, then there has to be a realm in which the nonexperienced
-Empire State Building does or does not exist. This realm is precisely the
-realm beyond my experience. The question of whether the Empire State
-Building continues to exist when I am not Jooking at it depends on the very
-assertion, about the existence of a realm beyond my experience, which we
-found to be nonsubstantive. Thus, the assertion that the Empire State
-Building continues to exist when I am not looking at it must also be
-considered as nonsubstantive or meaningless, as a special case of a
-definitional trick.
-
-We start by taking questions of belief seriously as substantive questions,
-which is the way they should be taken according to the semantics implicit in
-the natural language. The assertion that God exists, for example, has
-traditionally been taken as substantive; when American theists and Russian
-atheists disagree about its truth, they are not supposed to be disagreeing
-aboui nothing. We find, however, that by using the rules implicit in the
-natural language to criticize the natural language itself, we can show that
-belief-assertions are not substantive.
-
-Parallel to our analysis of belief-assertions or the realm beyond my
-experience, we can make an analysis of beliefs as mental acts. (We
-understand a belief to be an assertion referring to the realm beyond my
-experience, or to be the mental act of which the assertion is the verbal
-formulation.) Introspectively, what do I do when I believe that the Empire
-State Building exists even though I am not looking at it? I imagine the
-Empire State Building, and I have the attitude toward this mental picture
-that it is a perception rather than a mental picture. Let us bring out a
-distinction we are making here. Suppose I see a table. I have a so-called
-perception of a table, a visual table-experience. On the other hand, I may
-close my eyes and imagine a table. Independently of any consideration of
-"reality," two different types of experiences can be distinguished,
-non-mental experiences and mental experiences. A belief as a mental act
-consists of having the attitude toward a mental experience that it is a
-non-mental experience. The "attitude" which is involved is not a
-proposition. There are no words to describe it in greater detail; only
-introspection can provide examples of it. The attitude is a self-deceiving
-psychological trick which corresponds to the definitional trick in the
-belief-assertion.
-
-The entire analysis up until now can be carried a step farther. So far as
-the formal characteristics of the problem are concerned, we find that
-although the problem originally seems to center on "nonexperience," it
-turns out to center on "language." Philosophical problems exist only if there
-is language in which to formulate them. The flaw which we have found in
-belief-assertions has the following structure. A statement asserts the
-existence of something of a trans-experiential nature, and it turns out that
-the statement must be true if it is merely meaningful. The language which
-refers to nonexperience can be meaningful only if there is a realm beyond
-experience. The entire area of beliefs reduces to one question: are linguistic
-expressions which refer to nonexperience meaningful? We remark
-parenthetically that practically all language is supposed to refer to
-nonexperiences. Even the prosaic word "table" is supposed to denote an
-object, a stable entity which continues to exist when I am not looking at it.
-Taking this into account, we can reformulate our fundamental question as
-follows. Is language meaningful? Is there a structure in which symbols that
-we experience (sounds or marks) are systematically connected to objects, to
-entities which extend beyond our experience, to nonexperiences? !n other
-words, is there language? (To say that there is language is to say that half of
-all belief-assertions are true. That is, given any belief-assertion, either it is
-true or its negation is true.) Thus, the only question we need to consider is
-whether language itself exists. But we see immediately, much more
-immediately than in the case of "nonexperience," that this question is
-caught in a trap of its own making. The question ought to be substantive. (Is
-there a systematic relation between marks and objects, between marks and
-nonexperiences? Is there an expression, "Empire State Building," which is
-related to an object outside one's experience, the Empire State Building, and
-which therefore has the same meaning whether one is looking at the Empire
-State Building or not? ) However, it is quite obvious that if one can even ask
-whether there is language, then the answer must be affirmative. Further, the
-distinction of language levels which is made in formal languages will not help
-here. Before you can construct formal languages, you have to know the
-natural language. The natural language is the infinite level, the container of
-the formal languages. If the container goes, everything goes. And this
-container, this infinite level language, must include its own semantics. There
-is no way to "go back before the natural language." As we mentioned
-before, the aphorism that "saying a thing is so doesn't make it so" is an
-example of the natural language's semantics in the natural language.
-
-in summary, the crucial assertion is the assertion that there is language,
-made in the natural language. This assertion is true if it is meaningful. It is
-too true; it must be a definitional trick. Beliefs stand or fal! on the question
-of whether there is language. There is no way to get outside the definitional
-trick and ask this question in a way that would be substantive. The question
-simply collapses.
-
-\chapter{Philosophical Aspects of Walking Through Walls}
-
-
-We read that in the Middle Ages, people found it impossible not to
-believe that they would be struck by lightning if they uttered a blasphemy.
-Yet I utterly disbelieve that I will be struck by lightning if I utter a
-blasphemy. Beliefs such as the one at issue here will be called fearful beliefs.
-Elsewhere, I have argued that all beliefs are self-deceiving. I have also
-observed that there are often non-cognitive motives for holding beliefs, so
-that a technical, analytical demonstration that a belief is self-deceiving wil!
-not necessarily provide a sufficient motive for renouncing it. The question
-then arises as to why people would hold fearful beliefs. It would seem that
-people would readily repudiate beliefs such as the one about blasphemy as
-soon as there was any reason to doubt them, even if the reason was abstract
-and technical. Yet fearful beliefs are held more tenaciously than any others.
-Further, when philosophers seek examples of beliefs which one cannot
-afford to give up, beliefs which are not mere social conventions, beliefs
-which are truly objective, they invariably choose fearful beliefs.
-
-Fearful beliefs raise some subtle questions about the character of beliefs
-as mental acts. If I contemplate blasphemy, experience a strong fear, and
-decide not to blaspheme, do I stand convicted of believing that I will be
-punished if I blaspheme, or may I claim that I was following an emotional
-preference which did not involve any belief? Is there a distinction between
-fearful avoidance and fearful belief? Can the emotion of fear be
-self-deceiving in and of itself? Must a belief have a verbal, propositional
-formulation, or is it possible to have a belief with no linguistic representation
-whatever?
-
-It is apparent that fearful beliefs suggest many topics for speculation.
-This essay, however, will concentrate exclusively on one topic, which is by
-far the most important. Given that people once held the belief about
-blasphemy, and that I do not, then I have succeeded in dispensing with a
-fearful belief. Two beliefs which are exactly analogous to the one about
-blasphemy are the belief that if I jump out of a tenth story window I will be
-hurt, and the belief that if I attempt to walk through a wali I wil! bruise
-myself. Given that I am able to dispense with the belief about blasphemy, it
-follows that, in effect, I am able to walk through walls relative to medieval
-people. That is, my ability to blaspheme without being struck by lightning
-would be as unimaginable to them as the ability to walk through walls is
-today. The topic of this essay is whether it is possible to transfer my
-achievement concerning blasphemy to other fearful beliefs.
-
-\visbreak
-
-I am told that \enquote{if you jump out of a tenth story window you really will
-be hurt.} Yet the analogous exhortation concerning blasphemy is not
-convincing or compelling at all. Why not? I suggest that the nature of the
-"evidence" implied in the exhortation should be examined very closely to
-see if it does not represent an epistemological swindle. In the cases of both
-blasphemy and jumping out of the window, I am told that if I perform the
-action I will suffer injury. But do I concede that I have to blaspheme, in
-order to prove that I can get away with it? Actually, I do not blaspheme; I
-simply do not perform the action at all. Yet I do not have any belief
-whatever that it would be dangerous to do so. Why should anyone suppose
-that because I do not believe something, I have to run out in the street,
-shake my fist at the sky, and curse God in order to validate may disbelief?
-Why should the credulous person be able to put me in in the position of
-having to accept the dare that "you have to do it to prove you don't believe
-it's dangerous"? Could it not be that this dare is some sort of a swindle?
-The structure of the evidence for the supposedly unrelinquishable belief
-should be examined very closely to see if it is not so much legerdemain.
-
-The exhortation continues to the effect that if I did utter blasphemy I
-really would be struck by lightning. I stil! do not find this compelling. But
-suppose that I do see someone utter a blasphemy and get struck by lightning.
-Surely this must convert me. But with due apologies to the faithful, I must
-report that it does not. There is no reason why it should make me believe. I
-do not believe that blaspheming will cause me to be struck by lightning, and
-the evocation of frightful images---or for that matter, something that I
-see---would provide no reason whatever for sudden credulity. There is an
-immense difference between seeing a person blaspheme and get struck by
-lightning, and believing that if one blasphemes, one will get struck by
-lightning. This difference should be quite apparent to one who does not hold
-the belief.\footnote{In more conventional terms, the civilization in which I tive is so
-profoundly secular that its secularism cannot be demolished by one
-"sighting."}
-
-In general, the so-called evidence doesn't work. There is a swindle
-somewhere in the evidence that is supposed to make me accept the fearful
-belief. Upon close scrutiny, each bit of evidence misses the target. Yet the
-whole conglomeration of "evidence" somehow overwhelmed medieval
-people. They had to believe something that I do not believe. I can get away
-with something that they could not get away with.
-
-It is not that I stand up in a society of the faithful and suddenly
-blaspheme. It is rather that the whole medieva! cognitive orientation had
-been completely reoriented by the time it was transmitted to me. Or in other
-words, the medieval cognitive orientation was restructured throughout
-during the modern era. In the process, the compelling conglomeration of
-evidence was disintegrated. Isolated from their niches in the old orientation,
-the bits of evidence no longer worked. Each bit missed the target. I do not
-have a head-on confrontation with the medieval impossibility of
-blaspheming. I slip by the impossibility, where they could not, because I
-structure the entire situation, and the evidence, differently.
-
-The analysis just presented, combined with analyses of beliefs which I
-have made elsewhere, assures me that the belief that "if I try to walk
-through the wall I wil! fail and will bruise myself" is also discardable. I am
-sure that I can walk through walls just as successfully as I can blaspheme.
-But to do so will not be trivial. As I have shown, escaping the power of a
-fearful belief is not a matter of head-on confrontation, but of restructuring
-the entire situation, of restructuring evidence, so that the conglomeration of
-evidence is disintegrated into isolated bits which are separately powerless.
-Only then can one slip by the impossibility. I cannot exercise my freedom to
-walk through walls until the whole cognitive orientation of the modern era is
-restructured throughout.
-
-The project of restructuring the modern cognitive orientation is a vast
-one. The natural sciences must certainly be dismantled. In this connection it
-is appropriate to make a criticism about the logic of science as Carnap
-rationalized it. Carnap considered a proposition meaningful if it had any
-empirically verifiable proposition as an implication. But consider an
-appropriate ensemble of scientific propositions in good standing, and
-conceive of it as a conjunction of an infinite number of propositions about
-single events (what Carnap called protocol-sentences). Only a very small
-number of the latter propositions are indeed subject to verification. If we
-sever them from the entire conjunction, what remains is as effectively
-blocked from verification as the propositions which Carnap rejected as
-meaningless. This criticism of science is not a mere technical exercise. A
-scientific proposition is a fabrication which amalgamates a few trivially
-testable meanings with an infinite number of untestable meanings and
-inveigles us to accept the whole conglomeration at once. It is apparent at the
-very beginning of \booktitle{Philosophy and Logical Syntax} that Carnap recognized this
-quite clearly; but it did not occur to him to do anything about it. For us,
-however, it is essential to be assured that science can be dismantled just as
-the proof can be dismantled that I will be struck by lightning if I blaspheme.
-
-We can suggest some other approaches which may contribute to
-overcoming the modern cognitive orientation. The habitual correlation of
-the realm of sight and the realm of touch which occurs when we perceive
-"objects" is a likely candidate for dismantling.\footnote{The psychological jargon for
-this correlation is "the contribution of intermodal organization to the
-object Gestalt."}
-
-From a different traditon, the critique of scientific fact and of
-measurable time which is suggested in Luk\'{a}cs' \booktitle{Reification and the
-Consciousness of the Proletariat} might be of value if it were developed.\footnote{Lulkacs also implied that scientific truth would disappear in a communist
-society---that is, a society without necessary labor, in which the right to
-subsistence was unconditional. He implied that scientific quantification and
-facticity are closely connected with the work discipline required by the
-capitalist mode of production; and that like the price system, they constitute
-a false objectivity which we accept because the social economic institutions
-deprive us of subsistence if we fail to submit to them. Quite aside from the
-historical unlikelihood of a communist society, this suggestion might be
-pursued as a thought experiment to obtain a more detailed characterization
-of the hypothetical post-scientific outlook.}
-
-Finally, I may mention that most of my own writings are offered as
-fragmentary beginnings in the project of dismantling the modern cognitive
-orientation.
-
-Someday we will realize that we were always free to walk through
-walls. But we could not exercise this freedom because we structured the
-whole situation, and the evidence, in an enslaving way.
-
-\chapter{Philosophical Reflections I}
-
-\begin{enumerate} % TODO letters, sub numbers
-\item If language is nonsense, why do we seem to have it? How do these
-intricate pseudo-significant structures arise? If beliefs are self-deceiving, why
-are they there? Why are we so skilled in the self-deceptive reflex that I find
-in language and belief? Why are we so fluent in thinking in self-vitiating
-concepts? Granting that language and belief are mistakes, are mistakes of
-this degree of complexity made for nothing? Is not the very ability to
-concoct an apparently significant, self-vitiating and self-deceiving structure a
-transcendent ability, one that points to something non-immediate? Do not
-these conceptual gymnastics, even if self-vitiating, make us superior to the
-mindless animals?
-
-Such questions tempt one to engage in a sort of philosophical
-anthropology, using in part the method of introspection. Beliefs could be
-explained as arising in an attempt to deal with experienced frustrations by
-denying them in thought. The origin of Christian Science and magic would
-thereby be explained. Further, we could postulate a primal anxiety-reaction
-to raw experience. This anxiety would be lessened by mythologies and
-explanatory beliefs. The frustration and the anxiety-reaction would be
-primal non-cognitive needs for beliefs.
-
-Going even farther, we could suppose that a being which could
-apprehend the whole universe through direct experience would have no need
-of beliefs. Beliefs would be a rickety method of coping with the limited
-range of our perception, a method by which our imperfect brains cope with
-the world. There would be an analogy with the physicist's use of phantom
-models to make experimental observations easier to comprehend.
-
-However, there are two overwhelming objections to this philosophical
-anthropology. First, it purports to study the human mind as a derivative
-phenomenon, to study it from a God-like perspective. The philosophical
-anthropology thus consists of beliefs which are subject to the same
-objections as any other beliefs. It is on a par with any other beliefs; it has no
-privileged position. Specifically, it is in competition not only with my
-philosophy but with other accounts of the mind-reality relation, such as
-behaviorism, Platonism, and Thomism. And my philosophy provides me with
-no basis to defend my philosophical! anthropology against their philosophical
-anthropologies. My philosophy doesn't even provide me with a basis to
-defend my philosophical anthropology against its own negation.
-
-In short, the paradoxes which my philosophy uncovers must remain
-unexplained and unresolved.
-
-The other objection to my philosophical anthropology is that its
-implications are unnecessarily conservative. An explanation of why people
-do something wrong can become an assertion that it is necessary to do wrong
-and finally a justification for doing wrong. But just because I tend, for
-example, to construe my perceptions as confirmations of propositions about
-phenomena beyond my experience does not mean that I must think in this
-way. To explain the modern cognitive orientation by philosophical
-anthropology tends to absolutize it and to conceal its dispensability.
-
-\item There are more legitimate tasks for the introspective "anthropology"
-of beliefs than trying to find primal non-cognitive needs for beliefs.
-Presupposing the analysis of beliefs as mental acts and self-deception which I
-have made elsewhere, we need to examine closely the boundary line between
-beliefs and non-credulous mental activity.
-
-Is my fear of jumping out of the window a belief? Strictly speaking,
-no. In psychological terms, a conditioned reflex does not require
-propositional thought.
-
-Is my identification of an object in different spatial orientations
-(relative to my field of vision) as "the same object" a belief? Apparently,
-but this is very ambiguous.
-
-Is my identification of tactile and visual "pencil-perceptions" as aspects
-of a single object (identity of the object as it is experienced through
-different senses) a belief? Yes.
-
-It is possible to subjectively classify bodily movements according to
-whether they are intentional, because drunken awkwardness, adolescent
-awkwardness, and movements under ESB are clearly unintentional. Then
-does intentional movement of my hand require a belief that I can move my
-hand? Definitely not, although in rare cases some belief will accompany or
-precede the movement of my hand. But believing itself will not get the hand
-moved!
-
-Is there any belief involved in identifying my leg, but not the leg of the
-table at which I am sitting, as part of my body? Maybe---another ambiguous
-case.
-
-Are my emotions of longing and dread beliefs in future time? Is my
-emotion of regret belief in past time? Philosophical anthropology: these
-temporal feelings precede and give rise to temporal beliefs. (?)
-
-How can I introspectively analyze my dread as dread of future injury if
-my belief in the existence of the future is invalid to begin with? Easily---the
-object of the fear is a belief or has a belief associated with it.
-
-\gap
-
-\item At one point Alten claimed that his dialectical approach does not
-take any evidence as being more immediate, more primary, than any other
-evidence. Our "immediate experience" is mediated; it is a derived
-phenomenon which only subsists in an objective reality that is outside our
-subjective standpoint.
-
-\begin{enumerate}
-
-\item But Alten does not seriously defend the claim that he does not
-distinguish between immediate and non-immediate. The claim that there is
-no distinction would be regarded as demented in every human culture. Every
-culture supposes that I may be tricked or cheated: there is a realm, the
-non-immediate or non-experienced, which provides an arena for surreptitious
-hostility to me. Every culture supposes that it is easier for me to tell what I
-am thinking than what you are thinking. Every culture supposes that I will
-hear things which I should not accept before I go and see for myself. Alten is
-simply not iconoclastic enough to reject these commonplaces. What he
-apparently does is, like the perceptual psychologist, to accept the distinction
-between immediate and non-immediate, and to accept the former as the only
-way of confirming a model, but to construct a model of the relation between
-the two in which the former is analyzed as a derivative phenomenon.
-
-\item Alten proposes to analyze his own awareness as a derivative
-phenomenon, to take a stance outside all human awareness. But this is the
-pretense of the God-like perspective. He postulates both his own limitedness
-and his ability to step outside it! This is an overt contradiction. Indeed, it is
-the archetype of the overt self-deception in beliefs which my philosophy
-exposes. "I can tell the Empire State Building exists now even though I
-cannot now perceive it."
-\end{enumerate}
-
-\item In my technical philosophical writings, I call attention to certain
-self-vitiating "nodes" in the logic of common sense. These nodes include the
-concept of non-experience and the assertion that there is language. I often
-find that others dismiss these examples as jokes that can be isolated from
-cognition or the logic of common sense, rather than acknowledging that they
-are self-vitiating nodes in the logic of common sense. As a result, I have
-concluded that it is probably futile to debate the abstract validity of my
-analysis of these nodes. It does indeed appear as if I am debating over an
-abstract joke, and it is not apparent why I would attribute such great
-importance to a joke.
-
-\essaytitle{Philosophical Aspects of Walking Through Walls} represents my
-present approach. The advantage of this approach is that it makes
-unmistakable the reason why ! attribute so much importance to these
-philosophical studies. I am not merely debating the abstract validity of a few
-isolated linguistic jokes; I seek to overthrow the life-world. The only
-significance of my technical philosophical writings is to offer an explanation
-of why the life---world is subject to being undermined.
-
-When I speak of walking through walls, the mistake is often made of
-trying to understand this reference within the framework of present-day
-scientific common sense. Walking through walls is understood as it would be
-pictured in a comic-book episode. But such an understanding is quite beside
-the point. What I am advocating---to skip over the intermediate details and go
-directly to the end result---is a restructuring of the whole modern cognitive
-orientation such that one doesn't even engage in scientific hypothesizing or
-have "object perceptions," and thus wouldn't know whether one was
-walking through a wail or not.
-
-At first this suggestion may seem like another joke, a triviality. But my
-genius consists in recognizing that it is not, that there is a residue of
-non-vacuity and non-triviality in this proposal. There may be only a
-hair's-breadth of difference between the state I propose and mental
-incompetance or death---but still, there is all of a hair's-breadth. I magnify
-this hair's-breadth many times, and use it as a lever to overturn civilization.
-
-\item I am often asked in philosophical discussion how it is that we are
-now talking if language is vitiated. Let me comment that merely pointing
-over and over to one of the two circumstances which create a paradox does
-not resolve the paradox. Indeed, a paradox arises when there are two
-circumstances in conflict. The "fact" that we are talking is one of the two
-circumstances which conjoin in the paradox of language; the other
-circumstance being the self-vitiating "nodes" I have mentioned. To repeat
-over and over that we are now talking does not resolve any paradoxes.
-
-Contrary to what the question of how it is that we are now talking
-suggests, we do not "see" language. (That is, we do not experience an
-objective relation between words and things.) The !anguage we "see" is a
-shell whose "transcendental reference" is provided by self-deception.
-
-\item Does the theory of amcons show that the contradiction exposed in
-\essaytitle{The Flaws Underlying Beliefs} is admissible and thus loses its philosophical
-force? No. An amcon is between two things that you see, e.g. stationary
-motion. It is between two sensed qualities, the simultaneous experiencing of
-contradictory qualities. (But "He left an hour ago" begins to be a borderline
-case. Here the point is the ease with which we swallow an expression which
-violates logical rules. Also expansion of an arc: a case even more difficult to
-classify.) The contradiction in \essaytitle{The Flaws Underlying Beliefs} has to do first
-with the logic of common sense, with the logical rules of language. It has to
-do, secondly, with the circumstance that you don't see something, yet act as
-if you do. Amcons should not be used to justify self-deception in the latter
-sense, to rescue every cheap superstition.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-
-{
-5/15/1962
-
-
-Comments from the audience
-(photo by Tony Conrad)
-
-
-"Creep" lecture, May 15, 1962
-}
-
-\clearpage
-
{
-5/15/1962
+ \centering\sffamily
+ \plainbreak{3}
-Comments from the audience
-(photo by Tony Conrad)
+ { \Large
+ Blueprint for a Higher Civilization \par}
+ \plainbreak{3}
-"Creep" lecture, May 15, 1962
+ { \large Henry Flynt \par}
}
\clearpage
+\newcommand{\photopage}[3]{
+ \begin{figure}[!hp]
+ \centering
+ \includegraphics[width=4in]{#1}
+ \caption{#2 (photo by #3)}
+ \end{figure}}
-\chapter{Instructions for the Flyntian Modality}
-
-\begin{enumerate}
-
-\item \textsc{ Stop all \enquote{gross believing,} such as belief in other minds, causality, and the phantom entities of science (atoms, electrons, \etc).}
-
-\item \textsc{Stop thinking in propositional language.}
-
-\item \textsc{Stop all scientific hypothesizing. Do not consider your "sightings" of the empire state building as confirmations that it is there when you are not looking at it --- or for that matter, as confirmations that it is there when you \emph{are} looking at it.}
-
-\item \textsc{Stop organizing visual experiences and tactile experiences into object-gestalts. Stop organizing so-called "different spatial orientations or different touched surfaces of objects" into object-gestalts. That is, stop having perceptions of objects.}
-
-\item \textsc{Stop believing in past and future time. That is, live out of time. Stop feeling longing, dread, or regret.}
-
-\item \textsc{Stop believing that you can move your body.}
-
-\item \textsc{Stop believing that these instructions have any objective meaning.}
-
-\item \textsc{You are now free to walk through walls (if you can find them).}
-\end{enumerate}
-
-\chapter{Some Objections to My Philosophy}
-
-
-\textbf{A.} The predominant attitude toward philosophical questions in
-educated circles today derives from the later Wittgenstein. Consider the
-philosopher's question of whether other people have minds. The
-Wittgensteinian attitude is that in ordinary usage, statements which imply
-that other people have minds are not problematic. Everybody knows that
-other people have minds. To doubt that other people have minds, as a
-philosopher might do, is simply to misuse ordinary language. (See
-Philosophical Investigations, \S 420.) Statements which imply that other
-people have minds works perfectly well in the context for which they were
-intended. When philosophers find these statements problematic, it is because
-they subject the statements to criticism by logical standards which are
-irrelevant and extraneous to ordinary usage. (\S \S 402, 412, 119, 116.)
-
-For Wittgenstein, the existence of God, immortal souls, other minds,
-and the Empire State Building (when I am not looking at it) are all things
-which everybody knows; things which it is impossible to doubt "in a real
-case." (\S 303, Iliv. For Wittgenstein's theism, see Norman Malcolm's
-memoir.) The proper use of language admits of no alternative to belief in
-God; atheism is just a mistake in the use of language.
-
-
-In arguing against Wittgenstein, I will concentrate on the real reason
-why I oppose him, rather than on less fundamental technical issues. We read
-that in the Middle Ages, people found it impossible not to believe that they
-would be struck by lightning if they uttered a blasphemy; just as
-Wittgenstein finds the existence of God impossible to doubt "in a real case."
-Yet even Wittgenstein does not defend the former belief; while the Soviet
-Union has shown that a government can function which has repudiated the
-latter belief. There is a tremendous discovery here: that beliefs which were as
-inescapable---as impossible to doubt in a real case---as any belief we may have
-today, were subsequently discarded. How was this possible? My essay \essaytitle{The
-Flaws Underlying Beliefs} shows how. Further, it shows that the belief that
-the Empire State Building exists when I am not looking at it, or the belief
-that I would be killed if I jumped out of a tenth story window, are no
-different in principle from beliefs which we have already discarded. It Is
-perfectly possible to project a metaphysical outlook on experience which is
-totally different from the beliefs Wittgenstein inherited, and it is also
-possible not to project a metaphysical outlook on experience at all. Let us be
-absolutely clear: the point is not that we do not know with one hundred per
-cent certainty that the Empire State Building exists; the point is that we
-need not believe in the Empire State Building at all. \essaytitle{The Flaws Underlying
-Beliefs} shows that factual propositions, and the propositions of the natural
-sciences, involve outright self-deception.
-
-These discoveries have consequences far more important than the
-technical issues involved. It is by no means trivial that I do not have to pray,
-or to fast, or to accept the moral dictates of the clergy, or to give money to
-the Church. Because the Church prohibited the dissection of human
-cadavers, it took an atheist to originate the modern subject of anatomy. In
-analogy with this example, the rest of my writings are devoted to exploring
-the consequences of rejecting beliefs that Wittgenstein says are impossible to
-doubt in a real case, as in my essay \essaytitle{Philosophical Aspects of Walking
-Through Walls.} I oppose Wittgenstein because he descended to extremes of
-intellectual dishonesty in order to prevent us from discovering these
-consequences.
-
-A reply to the Wittgensteinian attitude which is technically adequate
-can be provided in short order, for when Wittgenstein's central philosophical
-maneuver is identified, its dishonesty becomes transparent. It is not
-necessary to enumerate the fallacies in the Wittgensteinian claim that logical
-connections and logical standards are extrinsic to the natural language, or in
-the aphorism that "the meaning is the use" (as an explication of the natural
-language). In other words, there is no reason why I should bandy descriptive
-linguistics with Wittgenstein. Wittgenstein was wrong at a level more basic
-than the level on which his philosophical discussions were conducted.
-
-Wittgenstein held that philosophical or metaphysical controversies
-literally would not arise if it were not for bad philosophers. They would not
-arise because there is nothing problematic about sentences, expressing
-Wittgenstein's inherited beliefs, in ordinary usage. This rhetorical maneuver
-is the inverse of what it seems to be. Wittgenstein doesn't prove that the
-paradoxes uncovered by "bad" philosophers result from a misuse of ordinary
-language; he defines the philosophers' discussions as a misuse of ordinary
-language because they uncover paradoxes is ordinary language propositions.
-Wittgenstein waits to see whether a philosopher uncovers problems in
-ordinary language propositions; and if the philosopher does so, then
-Wittgenstein defines his discussion as improper usage. Wittgenstein waits to
-see whether evidence is against his side, and if it is, he defines it as
-inadmissible.
-
-Consider the philosopher's question of how I know whether the \textsc{Empire
-State Building} continues to exist when I am not looking at it. The
-Wittgensteinian position on this question would be that it is problematic
-because it is a misuse of ordinary language; and because there is no
-behavioral context which constitutes a use for the question. According to
-this position, we would not encounter such problems if we would use
-ordinary language properly. But what does this position amount to? The
-philosopher's question has not been proved improper; it has been defined as
-improper because it leads to problems. The reason why "the proper use of
-ordinary language never leads to paradoxes" is that Wittgenstein has defined
-proper use as use in which no paradoxes are visible. Wittgenstein has not
-resolved or eliminated any problems; he has just refused to notice them.
-Wittgenstein attempts to pass off, as a discovery about philosophy and
-language, a gratuitous definition to the effect that certain portions of the
-natural language which embarrass him are inadmissible, a gratuitous ban on
-certain portions of the natural language which embarrass him. His purpose is
-to make criticism of his inherited beliefs impossible, to give them a spurious
-inescapability. Wittgenstein's maneuver is the last word in modish
-intellectual dishonesty.
-
-\gap
-
-\textbf{B.} In philosophy, arguments which start from an immediate which
-cannot be doubted and attempt to prove the existence of an objective reality
-are called transcendental arguments. Typically, such an argument says that if
-there is experience, there must be subject and object in experience; if there
-are subject and object, subject and object must be objectively real; and thus
-there must be objectively real mind and matter. Clearly, the belief which
-leaps the gap from the immediate to the objectively real is smuggled into the
-middle of the argument by a play on the words \enquote{subject} and \enquote{object.}
-
-When the sophistry is cleared away, it becomes apparent that the
-attempt to attain the trans-experiential or extra-experiential within
-experience faces a dilemma of overkill. If the attempt could succeed, it
-would have only collapsed objective reality to my subjectivity. If it could be
-"proved" that I know the distant past, other minds, God, angels, archangels,
-etc. from immediate experience, then all these phenomena would be
-trivialized. If other minds were given in my experience, they would only be
-my mind. The interest of the notion of objective reality is precisely its
-otherness and unreachability. If it could be reached from the immediate, it
-would be trivial. We ask how I know that the Empire State Building exists
-when I am not looking at it. If the answer is that I know through immediate
-experience, then objective reality has been collapsed to my subjectivity. The
-dilemma for transcendental arguments is that they propose to overcome the
-gap between the appearance of a thing and the thing itself, yet they do not
-want to conclude that appearances exhaust reality.
-
-There are two special assumptions which are smuggled into supposedly
-assumptionless transcendental arguments. First, there is the belief that there
-is an objective relationship between descriptive words and the things they
-describe, an objective criterion of the use of descriptive words. Secondly,
-there is the belief that correlations between the senses have an objective
-basis. (It is claimed that this belief cannot be doubted, but the claim is
-controverted by intersensory illusions such as the touching of a pencil with
-crossed fingers.)
-
-Transcendental arguments are secular theology, because they are
-addressed to a reader who wants only philosophical analyses that have
-conventional conclusions. A transcendental argument will contain a step
-such as the following, for example. We can have "real knowledge" of
-particular things only if there is an objective relationship between descriptive
-words and the things they describe; thus there must be such a relationship.
-This argument is plausible only if the reader can be trusted to overlook the
-alternative that we don't have this "real knowledge."
-
-In the way of supplementary remarks, we may mention that
-transcendental arguments typically commit the ontological fallacy: inferring
-the existence of a thing from the idea or name of the thing. Finally,
-transcendental arguments share a confusion which originates in the
-empiricism they are directed against: the confusion between doing
-fundamental philosophy and doing the psychology of perception. Many
-transcendental arguments are similar to current doctrines in scientific
-psychology. But they fail as philosophy, because scientific psychology takes
-as presuppositions, and cannot prove, the very beliefs which transcendental
-arguments are supposed to prove.
-
-\chapter{Philosophy Proper (\enquote{Version 3,} 1961)}
-\subsection*{Chapter 1: Introduction (Revised, 1973)}
-
-This monograph defines philosophy as such---philosophy proper---to be
-an inquiry as to which beliefs are "true," or right. The right beliefs are
-tentatively defined to be the beliefs one does not deceive oneself by holding.
-Although beliefs will be regarded as mental acts, they will be identified by
-their propositional formulations. Provisionally, beliefs may be taken as
-corresponding to non-tautologous propositions.
-
-Philosophy proper is an ultimate activity in the sense that no belief or
-supposed knowledge is conceded to be above philosophical examination. It is
-also an unavoidable activity in the sense that the notion of a belief, and the
-notion of judging the truth of a belief, are intrinsic to common sense and the
-natural language. Philosophers may not have achieved convincing results in
-philosophy proper; but the question of which beliefs are right is
-continuously posed for us even if we do not respect the way in which
-philosophers have dealt with it.
-
-All of the obstacles to philosophy proper arise because beliefs are
-normally held in order to satisfy non-cognitive needs. It will be heipful to
-examine this situation at some length. However, nothing can be done here
-beyond examining the situation. It is already clear that the interest of this
-monograph in beliefs is cognitive. It would be inappropriate to try to gain
-approval for philosophy proper by appealing to the values of those who hold
-beliefs in order to satisfy non-cognitive needs.
-
-it is implicit in beliefs that they correspond to cognitive claims, that
-they are subject to being judged true or false, and that their value rests on
-their truth. Nevertheless, beliefs can and do satisfy non-cognitive needs,
-quite apart from whether they are true. In order for a belief to satisfy some
-non-cognitive need, it is not necessary for the belief to be true; it merely has
-to be held. Concern with the ultimate philosophical validity of beliefs is rare.
-Concern with beliefs is normally concern with their ability to satisfy
-non-cognitive needs.
-
-To be specific, the literature of credulity contains remarks such as "I
-could not stand to live if I did not believe so-and-so," or "Even if so-and-so is
-true I don't want to know it." These remarks manifest the needs with which
-we are concerned. To take note of these remarks is already to uncover a level
-of self-deception. It is important to realize that this self-deception is explicit
-and self-admitted. To recognize it has nothing to do with imputing
-subconscious motives to behavior, as is done in psychoanalysis. Further, to
-recognize it is by no means to advance a theory of the ultimate origin of
-beliefs, a theory which would presuppose a judgment as to the philosophical
-validity of the beliefs. To theorize that the ultimate origin of beliefs lies in
-the denial of frustrating experiences, or in primal anxieties which are
-alleviated by mythological inventions, would be inappropriate when we have
-not even begun our properly philosophical inquiry. The only self-deceptions
-being considered here are admitted self-deceptions.
-
-A partial classification of the circumstances in which beliefs are held for
-non-cognitive reasons follows.
-
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item Beliefs may be directly tied to one's morale. "I couldn't stand to live if I didn't believe in God." "If President Nixon is guilty I don't want to know it."
-
-\item One may believe for reasons of conformity. The conversion of Jews to Catholicism in late medieval Spain was an extreme example.
-
-\item The American philosopher Santayana said that he believed in Catholicism for esthetic reasons.
-
-\item Moral doctrines are sometimes justified on the grounds of their efficacy in maintaining public order, rather than their philosophical validity.
-
-\item A more complicated and more interesting situation arises when one
-who claims to be engaged in a cognitive inquiry somehow circumscribes the
-inquiry so as to ensure in advance that it will yield certain preferred results.
-Such a circumscribed inquiry will be called "theologizing," in recognition of
-the archetypal activity in this category.
-
-When we raise the question of whether the natural sciences are
-instances of theologizing, it becomes apparent that the issue of non-cognitive
-motives for beliefs is no light matter. According to writers on the scientific
-method such as A. d'Abro, the scientist is compelled to operate as if he
-believed in the "real existence of a real absolute objective universe---a
-common objective world, one existing independently of the observer who
-discovers it bit by bit." The scientist holds this belief, even though it is a
-commonplace of college philosophy courses that it is unprovable, because he
-must do so in order to get on to the sort of results he considers desirable.
-The scientist claims to be engaged in a cognitive inquiry; yet the inquiry
-begins with an act of faith which it is impermissible to scrutinize. It follows
-that science is an instance of theologizing. If scientists cannot welcome a
-demonstration that their "metaphysical" presuppositions are invalid, then
-their interest in science cannot be cognitive.
-
-The scientist's non-cognitive motive for believing differs from the
-non-cognitive motives described earlier in one notable respect. Each of the
-non-cognitive needs described earlier required a given belief, and could not
-be satisfied by that belief's negation. But inside a science's circumscribed
-area of inquiry, the scientist can welcome the establishment of either of two
-contradictory propositions; in other words, his non-cognitive need can be
-satisfied by either proposition. It is in this sense that he can impartially test
-or decide between two propositions, or make new discoveries. On the other
-hand, with regard to the metaphysical presuppositions of science, only a
-single alternative is welcome.
-
-\item Academicians will readily acknowledge that they are not interested
-in scholarly work by unknown persons with no academic credentials. To
-academic mathematicians and biologists, whether Galois and Mendel had
-made valid discoveries was irrelevant. Thus, academicians as academicians
-circumscribe their purported interest in the cognitive in two ways---once as
-scientists; and once for reasons of personal gain and prestige.
-
-\item The strangest instance of a non-cognitive need for a belief is
-provided by the person who holds a fearful! belief which is widely considered
-to be superstitious, such as belief in Hell. As always, the test of whether the
-motive for the belief is cognitive is the question of whether the person would
-welcome a demonstration that the belief is invalid. There is reason to suspect
-that persons who cling to fearful beliefs would not welcome such a
-demonstration, perverse as their attitude may seem. After all, they take no
-comfort in the widespread rejection of the belief as superstitious. Thus, it
-seems that a masochistic need for fearful beliefs must be recognized.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-This examination of non-cognitive motives for beliefs is, to repeat,
-limited to circumstances in which there is explicit self-deception, or
-self-deception that can be demonstrated directly from internal evidence. The
-examination cannot be carried further unless we become able to judge
-whether the beliefs referred to are, after all, valid. Thus, we will now turn to
-our properly philosophical inquiry, which will occupy the remainder of this
-monograph.
-
-\signoffnote{(Note: Chapters 2-7 were written in 1961, at a time when I used
-unconventional syntax and punctuation. They are printed here without
-change.)}
+\photopage{img/creep}{Henry Flynt presents "Creep" lecture in Adam Hovre upper common room, Harvard University, May 15, 1962}{Tony Conrad}
-\section{The Linguistic Solution of Properly Philosophical Problems}
-\subsection*{Chapter 2 : Preliminary Concepts}
-
-In this part of the book I will be concerned to solve the problem of
-philosophy proper, the problem of which beliefs are right, by discussing
-language, certain linguistic expressions. To motivate what follows I might
-tentatively say that I will consider beliefs as represented by statements,
-formulations of them (for example, \formulation{Other persons have minds} as
-representing the belief that other persons have minds), so that the problem
-will be which statements are true. Actually, to solve this problem we will be
-driven far beyond answers to the effect that given statements are true (or
-false).
-
-To make this book as engaging as possible, I would like to start right
-into the solution of the problem, to begin with the material in the next
-chapter. However, it effects, I think, a considerable clarification and
-simplification of the presentation of the solution if I first introduce certain
-concepts in an extended discussion. Then, when they enter into the solution
-they won't have to be just suggested in a condensed explanation which has
-to be repeated over and over. Thus, this chapter will be a properly
-philosophically neutral introduction of the concepts, an introduction which
-doesn't in itself say anything about the rightness of given beliefs (or the
-truth of given statements). The chapter is as a result not so interesting as the
-others, but I hope the reader will bear with me through it.
-
-The first concept is a new one, that of "explication". Explication of a
-familiar linguistic expression is what might traditionally be said to be finding
-a definition of the expression; it amounts partly to determining what it is
-wanted that the expression "mean". To explain: I will be discussing
-philosophically important expressions, familiar to the reader, such that their
-"meaning" needs clarifying, such that it is not clear to him how he wants to
-use them. I will be concerned with the suggestion of expressions, of which
-the "meanings", uses, are clear, which will be acceptable to the reader as
-replacements for the expressions of which the uses are obscure; that is,
-which have the uses that, it will turn out, the expressions of which the uses
-are obscure are supposed to have. Since the expressions which are to be
-replacements can be equivalent as expressions (sounds, bodies of marks) to
-the expressions they are to replace, it can also be said that I will be
-concerned with the suggestion of clear uses, of the expressions of which the
-uses are obscure, which are, it will turn out, the uses the reader wants the
-expressions to have. To be more specific about the conditions of
-acceptability of such replacements, if the familiar expressions (expressions of
-which the uses were obscure) were supposed to be names, have referents
-(and non-referents), then the new: expressions must clearly have referents.
-Further, the new expressions must deserve (by having appropriate referents
-in the case of names) the principal connotations of the familiar expressions,
-especially the distinctive, honorific connotations of the familiar expressions.
-(I will not say here just how I use "connotation". What the connotations of
-an expression are will be suggested by giving sentences about, in the case of a
-supposed name for example, what the referents of the expression are
-supposed to be like.) "Finding", or constructing, an expression (with its use)
-supposed to be acceptable to oneself as.a replacement, of the kind described,
-for an expression familiar to oneself, will be said to be "explicating" the
-expression familiar to oneself. The expression to be replaced wil! be said to
-be the "explicandum", and the suggested replacement, the "explication".
-Incidentally, if clarification shows that the desired use of the explicandum is
-inconsistent, then it can't have an explication at all acceptable, or what is the
-same thing, any explication will be as good as any other.
-
-I should mention that my use of "explication" is different from that of
-Rudolph Carnap, from whom I have taken the word rather than use the very
-problematic "definition". For him, explication is a scientist's, or philosopher
-of science's, devising a new precise concept, useful in natural science,
-suggested by a vague, unclear common concept (for example, that of
-"work"); whereas for me it is in effect constructing (if possible) that precise,
-clear concept which is the nearest equivalent to an unclear common concept.
-
-Here is an example in the acceptability of explications. Suppose that an
-expression is suggested, as an explication for "thing having a mind" (if
-supposed to be a name, have referents), which has as referents precisely the
-things which have certain facial expressions, or talk, or have certain other
-"overt" behavior, or even certain brain electricity. Then I expect that this
-expression will not be acceptable to the reader as an explication for "thing
-having a mind", since "thing having a mind" presumably has the connotations
-for the reader "that having a mind is not the same as, is very different from,
-higher than, having certain facial expressions, talking, certain other overt
-behaving, or having certain brain electricity---the mind is observable only by
-the thing having it", and the explication doesn't deserve these connotations:
-the connotations of the explicandum are exclusive of the referents of the
-proposed explication. It doesn't make any difference if there's a causual
-connection between having a mind and the other things, because the
-expression 'thing having a mind' itself, and not the supposed effects of
-having a mind, is what is under discussion.
-
-As the reader can tell from the example, I will, in evaluating
-expressions, have to speak of what I assume the connotations of words are
-for the reader. If any of my assumptions are incorrect, the book will be
-slightly less relevant to the reader's philosophical problems than it would be
-otherwise. Even so, the reader should get from this part the method of
-finding good explications, and its use in solving properly philosophical
-problems.
-
-Especially important in deciding whether an explication for a supposed
-name is good is the check of the referents of the explication against the
-connotations of the explicandum. Traditional philosophers, in the rare cases
-when they have suggested explications for expressions in dealing with
-philosophical problems, have suggested absurdly bad ones, which can quickly
-be shown up by such a check. Examples which are typically horrible are the
-explications for "thing having a mind" mentioned above.
-
-The second concept I will discuss is that of true statement. As I will be
-discussing the "truth" of formulations of beliefs, statements, in the next two
-chapters, and as the concept of true statement is quite obscure (making it a
-good example of one needing explication), it will be helpful for me to clarify
-the concept beforehand, to give a partial explication for "true statement".
-(Partial because the explication, although much clearer than the
-explicandum, will itself have an unclear word in it.)
-
-Well, what is a "statement"? How do what are usually said to be
-"statements" state? Take a book and look through it, a book in a language
-you don't read, so you won't assume that it's obvious what it means. What
-does the book, the object, do? How does it work? Note that talking just
-about the marks in the book, or what seem (!) to be the rules of their
-arrangement, or the like, won't answer these questions. In fact, I expect that
-when the reader really thinks about them, the questions won't seem easy
-ones to answer. Now to begin answering them, one of the most important
-connotations of "true statement", and, more generally, of "statement", as
-traditionally and commonly used, is that a "statement" is an "assertion
-which has truth value" (is true or false) (or "has content", as it is sometimes
-said, rather misleadingly). That is, the "verbal" part of a statement is
-supposed to be related in a certain way to something "non-verbal", or at
-least not in the language the verbal part of the statement is in. Further, a
-statement is supposed to be "true" or not because of something having to do
-with the non-verbal thing to which the verbal part of the statement is
-related. (The exceptions are the "statements" of formalist logic and
-mathematics, which are not supposed to be assertions; they are thus
-irrelevant to statements of the kind ordinary persons and philosophers are
-interested in.) Thus, if "true statement" is to be explicated, "assertion having
-truth value" and "is true" (and "has content" in a misleading use) have to be
-explicated, as they are obscure, and as it must be clear that the explication
-for "true statement" deserves the connotations which were suggested with
-"assertion having truth value" and "is true". One important conclusion from
-these observations is that although "sentences" (the bodies of sound or
-bodes of marks such as "The man talks") are often said to be "statements",
-would not be sufficient (to say the least) to explicate "statement" by simply
-identifying it with "sentence" (in my sense); something must be said about
-such matters as that of being an assertion having truth value. For the same
-reason, it is not sufficient (to say the least) to simply identify "statement"
-with "sentence", the latter being explicated in terms of the ("formal") rules
-for the formation of (grammatical) sentences, as these rules have no
-reference to such matters as that of being an assertion having truth value.
-
-In explicating "true statement" I will use the most elegant approach, one
-relevant to the interest in such matters as that of being an assertion having
-truth value. This is to begin by describing a simple, if not the simplest, way
-to make an assertion. As an example, I will describe the simplest way to
-make the assertion that a thing is a table. The way is to "apply" \term{table} to
-the thing. It is supposed that \term{table} has been "interpreted", that is, that it is
-"determinate" to which, of all things, applications of \term{table} are (to be said
-to be) "true". (It is good to realize that it is also supposed that it is
-"determinate" which, of all things (events), are "occurrences of the word
-"table", are expressions "equivalent to" "table".) The word "determinate" is
-the intentionally ambiguous one in this explication; I don't want to commit
-myself yet on how an expression becomes interpreted. As for 'apply', one
-can "apply" the word to the thing by pointing out "first" the word and
-"then" the thing. 'point out' is restricted to refer to "ostension", pointing
-out things in one's presence, things one is perceiving, and not to "directing
-attention to things not in one's presence" as well. The assertion is 'true', of
-course, if and only if the thing to which 'table' is applied is one of the things
-to which it is determinate that the application of 'table' is (to be said to be)
-"true", otherwise "false". It should be clear that such a pointing out of a
-"first" thing and a "second", the first being an interpreted expression, is an
-assertion of a simple kind, does have truth value and so forth. Let me further
-suggest 'interpreted expression' as an explication for 'name'; with respect to
-this explication, the things to which equivalent names ("occurances of a
-name") may be truthfully applied are the referents of the equivalent names,
-other things being non-referents. (Incidentally, I could have started with the
-concept of a name and its referents, and then said how to make a simple
-assertion using a name.) Then what I have intentionally left ambiguous is
-how a name has referents; I have not said, for example, whether the relation
-between name and referents is an "objective, metaphysical entity", which
-would be getting into philosophy proper.
-
-The point of describing this simple way of making an assertion is that
-what one wants to say are "statements", namely sentences used in the
-context of certain conventions, can be regarded as assertions of the "simple"
-kind; thus an explication for 'true statement' can be found. To do so, first
-let us say that the "complex name" gotten by replacing a sentence's "main
-verb" with the corresponding participle is the "associated name" of the
-sentence. For example, the associated name of 'Boston is in Massachusetts' is
-'Boston being in Massachusetts'. In the case of a sentence with coordinate
-clauses there may be a choice with respect to what is to be taken as the main
-verb, but this presents no significant difficulty. Example: sentence: \said{The
-table in the room will have been black only if it had been pushed by one
-man while the other man talked}; main verb: 'will have been' or 'had been
-pushed'. Also, English may not have a participle to correspond to every verb,
-but this is in theory no difficulty; the lacking participle could obviously be
-invented. Now what we would like to say one does, in using a sentence to
-make a statement, is to so to speak "assert" its associated name; this
-"asserted name" being "true" if and only if it has a referent. However, one
-doesn't assert names; names just have referents---it is statements that one
-makes, "asserts", and that are "true" or "false". How, then, do we explicate
-this "asserting" of a name? By construing it as that assertion, of the simple
-kind, which is the application of 'having a referent' to the name. In other
-words, from our theoretical point of view, to use a sentence to make a
-statement, one begins with a name (the sentence's associated name), and
-puts it into the sentence form, an act equivalent by convention to applying
-'having a referent' to it. For example, the sentence 'Boston is in
-Massachusetts' should be regarded as the simple assertion which is the
-application of 'having a referent' to 'Boston being in Massachusetts'.
-
-Now this approach may seem "unnatural" or incomplete to the reader
-for several reasons. First there is the syntactical oddity: the sentence is
-replaced by a statement "about" it (or to be precise its associated name).
-Well, all I can say is that this oddity is the inevitable result of trying to
-describe explicitly all that happens when one uses a sentence to make a
-statement; I can assure the reader that the alternate approaches are even
-more unnatural. Secondly, it may seem natural enough to speak of
-interpreting "simple names" (Fries' Class 1 words), but not so natural to
-speak of interpreting complex names (what could their referents be?). Of
-course, this is because complex names are to be regarded as formed from
-simpler names by specified methods; that is, their interpretations (and thus
-referents) are in specified relations to those of the simple names from which
-they are formed. The relations are indicated by the words, in the complex
-names, which are not names, and by the order of the words in the complex
-names. An example worth a comment is associated names containing such
-words as 'the'; in making statements, these names have to be in the context
-of additional conventions, understandings, to have significance. It will be
-clear that what these relations (and referents) are, the explication of these
-relations, is not important for my purposes. Thirdly, I have not said anything
-about what the "meaning" (intension), as opposed to the referents (and
-non-referents), of a name is. (I might say that a thing can't have an intension
-unless it has referents or non-referents.) This matter is also not important for
-my purposes (and gets into philosophy proper). Finally, my approach tells
-the reader no more than he already knew about whether a given statement is
-true. Quite so, and I said that the discussion would be properly
-philosophically neutral. In fact, it is so precisely because of the ambiguous
-word 'determinate', because I haven't said anything about how names get
-referents. Even so, we have come a long way from blank wonder about how
-one (sounds, marks) could ever state anything, a long way towards
-explicating how asserting works. (And to the philosopher of language with
-formalist prejudices, the discussion has been a needed reminder that if
-language is to be assertional, say something, then names and referring in
-some form must have the central role in it.)
-
-"Statements", then, can be regarded as assertions of the 'simple' kind
-which are made in the special, conventional way, involving sentences, I have
-described. I could thus explicate 'true statement' as referring to those true
-"simple" assertions made in the special way, and it should be clear that this
-would be a good explication. However, as the connotations of 'true
-statement' having to do with the method of apptying the first member to the
-second are, I expect, of secondary importance compared to those having to
-do with such matters as being an assertion having truth value, it ts more
-elegant to explicate 'true statement' as referring to all true assertions of the
-"simple" kind. For the purposes of this book it is not important which of
-the two explications the reader prefers.
-
-So much for the preliminaries.
-
-\subsection*{Chapter 3 : "Experience"}
-
-I will introduce in this chapter some basic terminology, as the main step
-in taking the reader from ordinary English and traditional philosophical
-language to a language with which my philosophy can be exposited. This
-terminology is important because one of the main difficulties in expositing
-my philosophy (or any new philosophy) is that current language is based on
-precisely some of the assumptions, beliefs, I intend to question. It will, I
-think, be immediately clear to the reader at all familiar with modern
-philosophy that the problems of terminology I am going to discuss are
-relevant to the problem of which beliefs are right.
-
-First, consider the term 'non-experience'. Although the concept of a
-non-experience is intrinsically far more "difficult" than the concept of
-"experience" which I will be discussing presently, it is, I suppose,
-presupposed in all "natural languages" and throughout philosophy, is so
-taken for granted that it is rarely discussed in itself. Thus, the reader should
-have no difficulty understanding it. Examples of non-experiences are
-perceivable objects---for example, a table (as opposed to one's perceptions of
-it), existing external to oneself, persisting when one is not perceiving it; the
-future (future events); the past; space (or better, the distantness of objects
-from oneself); minds other than one's own; causal relationships as ordinarily
-understood; referental relationships (the relationships between names and
-their referents as ordinarily understood; what I avoided discussing in the
-second chapter); unperceivable "things" (microscopic objects (of course,
-viewing them through microscopes does not count as perceiving them),
-essences, Being); in short, most of the things one is normally concerned with,
-normally thinks about, as well as the objects of uncommon knowledge. (To
-simplify the explanation of the concept, make it easier on the reader, I am
-speaking as if I believed that there are non-experiences, that is, introducing
-the concept in the context of the beliefs usually associated with it.)
-Non-experiences are precisely what one has beliefs about. One believes that
-there are microscopic living organisms, or that there are none (or that one
-can not know whether there are any---this is not a non-belief but a complex
-belief about the relation of the realm where non-experiences could be to the
-mind). Incidentally, that other minds, for example, are non-experiences is
-presumably a connotation of 'other minds' for the reader, as explained in the
-second chapter.
-
-In the history of philosophy, the concept of non-experience comes first.
-Then philosophers begin to develop theories of how one knows about
-non-experiences (epistemological theories). The concept of a perception, or
-experience of something, is introduced into philosophy. The theory is that
-one knows about non-experiences by perceiving, having experiences of, some
-of them. For example, one knows that there is a table before one's eyes
-(assuming that there is) by having a visual perception or experience of it, by
-having a "visual-table-experience". The theory goes on to say that these
-perceptions are in the mind. Then, if one has a visual-table-experience in
-one's mind when there is no table, one is hallucinated. And so forth. Now
-there are two sources of confusion in all this for the naive reader. First,
-saying that perceptions of objects are in one's mind is not saying that they
-are, for example, visualizations, imaginings, such as one's visualization of a
-table with one's eyes closed. Perceptions of objects do not seem "mental".
-The theory that they are in the mind is a belief. This point leads directly to
-the second source of confusion. Does the English word 'table', as ordinarily
-used to refer to a table when one is looking at it, refer to the table, an entity
-external to one's perceptions which persists when not perceived, or to one's
-perception of it, to the visual-table-experience? If distinguishing between
-the two, and the notion that the table-experience is in his mind, seem silly to
-the reader, then he probably uses 'table', 'perceived table', and
-'table-experience' as equivalent some of the time. The distinction, however,
-is not just silly; anyone who believes that there are tables when he is not
-perceiving them must accept it to be consistent. At any rate there is this
-confusion, that it is not always clear whether English object-names are being
-used to refer to perceived non-experiences or to experiences, the
-perceptions.
-
-Now let us ignore for a moment the connotations that experiences are
-experiences, perceptions, of non-experiences, and are in the mind. The term
-'experience' is important here because with it philosophers finally made a
-start at inventing a term for the things one knows directly, unquestionabiy
-knows, or, better, which one just has, or are just there (whether they are
-experiences, perceptions, of non-experiences or not). A traditional
-philosopher would say that if one is having a table-experience, one may not
-know whether it's a true perception of a table, whether there's an objective
-table there; or whether it's an hallucination; but one unquestionably knows,
-has, the table-experience. And of course, with respect to one's experiences
-not supposed to be perceptions of anything, such as visualizations, one
-unquestionably knows, has them too. A better way of putting it is that there
-is no question as to whether one has one's experiences or what they are like.
-One doesn't believe (that one has) one's experiences; to try to do so would
-be rather like trying to polish air. In fact, "thinking" that one doesn't have
-one's experiences, if this is possible, is a belief, a wrong one (as will be
-shown, although it should already be obvious if the reader has the slightest
-idea of what I am talking about), and in fact a perfectly insane one. Now the
-reader must not think that because I say experiences are unquestionably
-known I am talking about tautologies, or about beliefs which some
-philosophers say can be known by intuition even though unprovable, or say
-cannot really be doubted without losing one's sanity (for example, some
-philosophers say this about the belief that other persons have minds). In
-speaking of experiences I am not trying to trick the reader into accepting a
-lot of beliefs I am not prepared to justify, as many philosophers do by
-appealing to intuition or sanity or what not, a reprehensible hyprocrisy
-which shows that they are not the least interested in philosophy proper. One
-does not have other-persons'-having-minds-experiences {nor are the objective
-tables one supposedly perceives table-experiences); one believes that other
-persons have minds (or that there is an objective table corresponding to one's
-table-experience), and this belief could very well be wrong (in fact, it is, as
-will be shown).
-
-I have explained the current use of the term 'experience'. Now I want
-to propose a new use for the term, which, except where otherwise noted,
-will be that of the rest of this book. (Thus whereas in discussing
-'non-experience' I was merely explaining and accepting the current use of
-the term, in the case of 'experience' I am going to suggest a new use for the
-term.) As I explained, the concept of non-experience preceded that of
-experience, and the latter was developed to explain how one knows the
-former. What I am interested in, however, is not 'experience' as it implies.
-'perceptions, of non-experiences, and in the mind', but as it refers to that
-which one unquestionably knows, is immediate, is just there, is not
-something one believes exists. I am going to use 'experience' to refer, as it
-already does, to that immediate "world", but without the implication that
-experience is perception of non-experience, and in the mind: the same
-referents but without the old connotations. In other words, in my use
-'experience' is completely neutral with respect to relationships to
-non-experiences, is not an antonym for 'non-experience' as conventionally
-used, does not presuppose a metaphysic. The reader is being asked to take a
-leap of understanding here, because there is all the difference in philosophy
-between 'experience' as implying, connoting, relatedness to non-experiences
-or in particular the realm where they could be, and 'experience' without
-these connotations.
-
-Viewing this discussion of terminology in retrospect, it should be
-obvious that although my term 'experience' was introduced last, it is
-intrinsically, logically, the simplest, most immediate, most inevitable of the
-terms, and should be the easiest to understand. In contrast, the notions I
-discussed in reaching it may seem a little arbitrary. As a matter of fact, I
-have used the perspective of the Western philsophical tradition to explain my
-term, but this doesn't mean that it is relevant only to that tradition or,
-especially, the theory of knowing about non-experiences. Even if the reader's
-conceptual background does not involve the concept of non-experience, and
-especially the modern Western theory of knowing about non-experiences, he
-ought to be able to understand, and realize the "orimacy" of, my term
-'experience'. The term should be supra-cultural.
-
-I have gone to some length to explain my use of the term 'experience'.
-As I have said, it is "intrinsically" the simplest term, but I can not define it
-by just equating it to some English expression because all English, including
-the traditional term 'experience', the antonym of 'non-experience', is based
-on metaphysical assumptions, does have implications about non-experience,
-in short, is formulations of beliefs. These implications are different for
-different philosophers according as their metaphysics (or, as is sometimes
-(incorrectly) said, "ontologies") differ. Even such a sentence as "The table is
-black" implies the formulation \formulation{Material objects are real} (to the materialist),
-or \formulation{So-called objects are ideas in the mind} (to the idealist), or \formulation{Substances
-and attributes are real}, and so forth, traditionally. As a result, in order to
-explain the new term I have had to use English in a very special way,
-ultimately turning it against itself, so as to enable the reader to guess how I
-use the term. That is, although there is nothing problematic about my use of
-\term{experience}, about its referents, there is about my English, for example
-when I say that the connotation of relatedness to non-experience is to be
-dropped from \term{experience}. There can be this new term, the philosopher is
-not irrevocably tied to English or other natural language and its implied
-philosophy, as some philosophers claim; because a term is able to be a name,
-to be used to make assertions, not by being a part of conventional English or
-other natural language, but by having referents.
-
-As I suggested at the beginning of this chapter, I need to introduce my
-\term{experience} because without it I cannot question all beliefs, everything
-about non-experiences, since in English there is always the implication that
-there could be non-experiences. The term is a radical innovation; one of the
-most important in this book. The fact that although it is the "simplest" and
-least questionable term, it is a radical innovation and is difficult to explain
-using English, shows how philosophically inadequate English and the
-philosophies it implies are. Now if the reader has not understood my
-\term{experience} he is likely to precisely mis-understand the rest of the book as
-an attempt to show that there are no non-experiences. (It's good that this
-isn't what I'm trying to show, because it is self-contradictory: for there to be
-no non-experiences there would have to be a realm empty of them, and this
-realm would have to be a non-experience.) If he is lucky he will just find the
-book incomprehensible, or possibly even come to understand the term from
-the rest of what I say, using it. But if he does understand the term, then he is
-past the greatest difficulty in understanding the book; in fact, he may
-already realize what I'm going to say.
-
-\subsection*{Chapter 4 : The Linguistic Solution}
-
-Now that I have explained the key terminology for this part of the
-book, I can give the solution to properly philosophical problems, the
-problems of which beliefs are right, in the form of conclusions about the
-language in which the beliefs are formulated. My concern here is to present
-the solution as soon as possible, so as to make it clear to the reader that my
-work contains important results, is an important contribution to philosophy,
-and not just admirable sentiments or the formulation of an attitude or a
-philosophically neutral analysis of concepts or the like. For this reason I will
-not be too concerned to make the solution seem natural, or intuitive, or to
-explore all its implications; that will come later.
-
-However, in the hope that it will make the main "argument" of this
-chapter easier to understand, I will precede it with a short, non-rigorous
-version of it, which should give the "intuitive insight" behind the main
-argument. Consider the question of whether one can know if a given belief is
-true. Now a given belief is cognitively arbitrary in that it cannot be justified
-from the standpoint of having no beliefs, cannot be justified without
-appealing to other beliefs. Thus the answer must be skepticism: one cannot
-know if a given belief is true. However, this skepticism is a belief---a
-contradiction. The ultimate conclusion is that to escape inconsistency, to be
-right, one must, at the linguistic level, reject all talk of beliefs, of knowing if
-they are true, reject all formulations of beliefs. The "necessity", but
-inconsistency, of skepticism "shows" my conclusion in an intuitively
-understandable way.
-
-To get on to the definitive version of my "argument". I will say that
-one name "depends" on another if and only if it has the logical relation to
-that other that \name{black table} has to \name{table}: a referent of the former is
-necessarily a referent of the latter (one of the relations between names
-mentioned in the second chapter). Now the associated name of any
-statement, or formulation, of a belief of necessity depends on
-'non-experience', since non-experiences are what beliefs are about. For
-example, \name{Other persons having minds}, the associated name of the
-formulation \formulation{Other persons have minds}, certainly depends on
-\term{non-experience}. Thus, anything true of \term{non-experience} will be true of the
-associated name of any formulation of a belief.
-
-In the last chapter I introduced, explained the concepts of
-non-experience and experience (in the traditional sense, as the antonym of
-\term{non-experience}), showed the connotations of the expressions
-\term{non-experience} and \term{experience} (traditional). What I did not go on to
-show, left for this chapter, is that if one continues to analyze these concepts,
-one comes on crucial implications which result in contradictions. What
-follows is perhaps the most concentrated passage in this book, so that the
-reader must be willing to read it slowly and thoughtfully. Consider one's
-experience (used in my, "neutral", sense unless I say otherwise). Could there
-be something in one's experience, a part of one's experience, which was
-awareness of whether it's experience (traditional), of whether it's related to
-non-experience, of whether there is non-experience, awareness of
-non-experience? No, as should be obvious from the connotations shown in
-the last chapter. (Compare this with the point that one cannot (cognitively)
-justify a belief from the standpoint of having no beliefs, cannot justify it
-without appealing to other beliefs). If there could be, if such awareness were
-just an experience, the distinctness of experience from experience
-(traditional) and so forth would disappear. The concepts of experience
-(traditional) and so forth would be superfluous, in fact, one couldn't have
-them: experience (traditional) and so forth would just be absorbed into
-experience. One concludes that there cannot be anything in one's experience
-which is awareness of whether it's experience (traditional), of whether there
-is non-experience. But then this awareness, which is in part about experience
-(traditional) and non-experience and thus involves awareness of them, is in
-one's experience---a contradiction. In fact, the same holds for the awareness
-which is "understanding the concepts" of non-experience and the rest as
-they are supposed to be understood. And for "understanding"
-\term{non-experience} (and the rest) as it is supposed to be, being aware of its
-referents (and non-referents); since to name non-experience, it must be an
-experience (traditional). And even for being aware of the referents (and
-non-referents) of "non-experience", which to name an experience
-(traditional) must be one. One mustn't assume that one understands
-'non-experience' --- and "non-experience" --- and \triquote{non-experience}; but here
-one is, using "non-experience" and \triquote{non-experience} to say so (which
-certainly implies that one assumes one understands them). It is impossible
-for there to be non-experiences. When one begins to examine closely the
-concept of non-experience, it collapses.
-
-(A final point for the expert. This
-tangle of contradictions is intrinsic in the concept of non-experience; it does
-not result because I have introduced a violation of the law that names cannot
-name themselves. This should be absolutely clear from the two sentences
-about names, which show contradictions --- that one must not assume that
-one understands certain expressions, but that one uses the expressions to say
-so (does assume it) --- with explicit stratification.)
-
-My exposition has broken down in a tangle of contradictions. Now
-what is important is that it has done so precisely because I have talked about
-experience (traditional), non-experience, and the rest, because I have spoken
-as if there could be non-experiences, because I have used 'experience'
-(traditional), 'non-experience', and the rest. Thus, even though what I have
-said is a tangle of contradictions, it is not by any means valueless. Since it is
-a tangle of contradictions precisely because it involves 'experience'
-(traditional), 'non-experience', and the rest, it shows that one who "accepts"
-the expressions, supposes that they are valid language, has inconsistent
-desires with respect to how they are to be used. The expressions can have no
-explications at all acceptable to him. He cannot consistently use the
-expressions (the way they're supposed to be). The expressions, and,
-remembering the paragraph before last, any formulation of a belief, are
-completely discredited. (What is not discredited is language referring to
-experiences (my use). If it happens that an expression I have said is a
-formulation of a belief does have a good explication for the reader, then it is
-not a formulation of a belief for him but refers to experiences.) Now there is
-an important point about method which should be brought out. If all
-"non-experiential language", "belief language", is inconsistent, how can I
-show this and yet avoid falling into contradiction when I say it? The answer
-is that I don't have to avoid falling into contradiction; that I fall into
-contradiction precisely because I use formulations of beliefs shows what I
-want to show. This, then, is the linguistic solution; as I said we would, we
-have been driven far beyond any such conclusion as 'all formulations of
-beliefs are false'.
-
-Now what do these conclusions about formulations of beliefs, about
-belief language, say about beliefs themselves, about whether a given belief is
-right? Well, to the extent that a belief is tied up with its formulation, since
-the formulation is discredited, the belief is, must be wrong. After all, if a
-belief were right, its formulation would necessarily have an acceptable
-explication which was true; in short, the belief would have a true
-formulation (to see this, note that the contrary assertion is itself a
-formulation of a belief---leading to a contradiction). Incidentally, this point
-answers those who would say, that the inconsistency of their statements of
-belief taken literally does not discredit their beliefs, as the statements are not
-to be taken literally, are metaphorical or symbolic truths. To continue, one
-who because of having a belief took its formulation seriously, expected that
-it could have an acceptable explication for him, could not turn out to be an
-expression he could not properly use, must be deceiving himself in some
-way. Now there is another important point about "method" to be made.
-The question will probably continually recur to the critical reader how one
-can "know", be aware that any given belief is wrong, without having beliefs.
-The answer is that one way one can be aware of it is simply to be aware of
-the inconsistency of belief language, which awareness is not a belief.
-(Whether belief language is inconsistent is not a matter of belief but of the
-way one wants expressions used; being aware of the inconsistency is like
-being aware with respect to a table, "that in my language, this is to be said to
-be a "table"".) Incidentally, to wrap things up, the common belief as to how
-a name has referents is that there is a relation between the name and its
-referents which is an objective, metaphysical entity, a non-experience; this
-belief is wrong. How, in what sense a name can have referents will not be
-discussed here.
-
-The unsophisticated reader may react to all of this with a lot of 'Yes,
-but...' thoughts. !f he doesn't more or less identify beliefs with their
-formulations, and doesn't have an intuitive appreciation of the force of
-linguistic arguments, he my tend to regard my result as a mere (if
-embarrassing) curiosity. (Of course, it isn't, but I am concerned with how
-well the reader understands that.) And there does remain a lot to be said
-about beliefs themselves (as mental acts), and where the self-deception is in
-them; it is not even clear yet just what the relation of a belief to its
-formulation is. Then the reader might ask whether there aren't beliefs whose
-rejection as wrong would conflict with experience, or which it would be
-impossible or dangerous not to have. I now turn to the discussion of these
-matters.
-
-
-\clearpage
-
-
-2/22/1963
-
-
-Tony Conrad and Henry Flynt demonstrate
-against Lincoln Center, February 22,
-
-
-1963
-(photo by Jack Smith)
-
-\clearpage
-
-
-\section{Completion of the Treatment of Properly Philosophical Problems}
-
-
-\subsection*{Chapter 5 : Beliefs as Mental Acts}
-
-
-In this chapter I will solve the problems of philosophy proper by
-discussing believing itself, as a ("conscious") mental act. Although I will be
-talking about mental acts and experience, it must be clear that this part of
-the book, like the fast part, is not epistemology or phenomenology. I will
-not try to talk about "perception" or the like, in a mere attempt to justify
-"common-sense" beliefs or what not. Of course, both parts are incidentally
-relevant to epistemology and phenomenology, since in discussing beliefs I
-discuss the beliefs which constitute those subjects.
-
-I should say immediately that 'belief', in its traditional use as supposed
-to refer to "mental acts, often unconscious, connected with the realm of
-non-experience", has no explication at all satisfactory, has been discredited.
-This point is important, as it means that one does not want to say that one
-does or does not "have beliefs", in the sense important to those having
-beliefs, that beliefs (in my sense) will not do as referents for "belief" in the
-use important to those having beliefs; helping to fill out the conclusion of
-the last part. Now when I speak of a "belief" I will be speaking of an
-experience, what might be said to be "an act of consciously believing, of
-consciously having a belief", of what is "in one's head" when one says that
-one "believes a certain thing". Further, I will, for convenience in
-distinguishing beliefs, speak of belief "that others have minds", for example,
-or in general of belief "that there are non-experiences" (with quotation
-marks), but I must not be taken as implying that beliefs manage to be
-"about non-experiences". (Thus, what I say about beliefs will be entirely
-about experiences; I will not be trying to talk "about the realm of
-non-experience, or the relation of beliefs to it".) I expect that it is already
-fairly clear to the reader what his acts of consciously believing are (if he has
-any); I will be more concerned with pointing out to him some features of his
-"beliefs" (believing) than with the explication of 'act of consciously
-believing', although I will need to make a few comments about that too.
-What I am trying to do is to get the reader to accept a useful, possibly new,
-use of a word ('belief') salvaged from the unexplicatible use of the word,
-rather than rejecting the word altogether.
-
-There is a further point about terminology. The reader should
-remember from the third chapter that quite apart from the theory "that
-perceptions are in the mind", one can make a distinction between mental
-and non-mental experiences, between, for example, visualizing a table with
-one's eyes closed, and a "seen" table, a visual-table-experience. Now I am
-going to say that visualizations and the like are "imagined-experiences". For
-example, a visualization of a table will be said to be an
-"imagined-visual-table-experience". The reader should not suppose that by
-"imagined" I mean that the experiences are "hallucinations", are "unreal". I
-use "imagined" because saying 'mental-table-experience" is too much like
-saying "table in the mind" and because just using 'visualization' leaves no way
-of speaking of mental experiences which are not visualizations. Speaking of
-an "imagined-table-experience" seems to be the best way of saying that it is
-a mental experience, and then distinguishing it from other mental
-experiences by the conventional method of saying that it is an imagining "of
-a (non-mental) table-experience" (better thought of as meaning an imagining
-like a (non-mental) table-experience). In other words, an
-imagined-x-experience (to generalize) is a "valid" experience, all right, but it
-is not a non-mental x-experience; it is a mental experience which is like a
-(non-mental) x-experience in a certain way. Incidentally, an "imagined-imagined-experience" is impossible by definition; or is no different from an
-imagined-experience, whichever way you want to look at it. If this
-terminology is a little confusing, it is not my fault but that of the
-conventional method of distinguishing different mental experiences by
-saying that they are imaginings "of one or another non-mental experiences".
-
-I can at last ask what one does when one believes "that there is a table,
-not perceived by oneself, behind one now", or anything else. Well, in the
-first place, one takes note of, gives one's attention to, an
-imagined-experience, such as an imagined-table-experience or a visualization
-of oneself with one's back to a table; or to a linguistic expression, a supposed
-statement, such as \lexpression{There is a table behind me}. This is not all one does,
-however; if it were, what one does would not in the least deserve to be said
-to be a "belief" (a point about the explication of my 'belief'). The
-additional, "essential" component of a belief is a self-deceiving "attitude"
-toward the experience. What this attitude is will be described below. Observe
-that one does not want to say that the additional component is a belief
-about the experience because of the logical absurdity of doing so, or, in
-other words, because it suggests that there is an infinite regress of mental
-action. Now the claim that the attitude is "self-deceiving" is not, could not
-be, at all like the claim "that a belief as a whole, or its formulation, fails to
-correspond in a certain way to non-experience, to reality, or is false". The
-question of "what is going on in the realm of non-experience" does not arise
-here. Rather, my claim is entirely about an experience; it is that the attitude,
-the experience not itself a belief but part of the experience of believing, is
-"consciously, deliberately" self-deceiving, is a "self-deception experience". I
-don't have to "prove that the attitude is self-deceiving by reference to what
-is going on in the realm of non-experience"; when I have described the
-attitude and the reader is aware of it, he will presumably find it a good
-explication, unhesitatingly want, to say that it is "self-deceiving".
-
-I will now say, as well as can be, what the attitude is. In believing, one
-is attentive primarily to the imagined-experience or linguistic expression as
-mentioned above. The attitude is "peripheral", is a matter of the way one is
-atttentive. Saying that the attitude is "conscious, deliberate", is a little
-strong if it seems to imply that it is cynical self-brainwashing; what I am
-trying to say is that it is not an "objective" or "subconscious" self-deception
-such as traditional philosophers speak of, one impossible to be aware of. This
-is about as much as I can say about the attitude directly, because of the
-inadequacy of the English descriptive vocabulary for mental experiences;
-with respect to English the attitude is a "vague, elusive" thing, very difficult
-to describe. I will be able to say more about what it is only by suggestion, by
-saying that it is the attitude "that such and such" (the reader must not think
-I mean the belief "that such and such"). If the experience to which the
-attention is primarily given in believing is an imagined-x-experience, then the
-self-deceiving attitude is the attitude "that the imagined-x-experience is a
-(non-mental) x-experience". As an example, consider the belief "that there is
-a table behind one". If one's attention in believing is not on a linguistic
-expression, it will be on an imagined-experience such as an
-imagined-table-experience or a visualization of a person representing oneself
-(to be accurate) with his back to a table, and one will have the self-deceiving
-attitude "that the imagined-experience is a table or oneself with one's back
-to a table". Of course, if one is asked whether one's imagined-x-experience is
-a (non-mental) x-experience, one will say that it is not, that it is admittedly
-an imagined-experience but "corresponds to a non-experience". This is not
-inconsistent with what I have said: first, I don't say that one believes "that
-one's imagined-x-experience is an x-experience"; secondly, when one is asked
-the question, one stops believing "that there is a table behind one" and starts
-believing "that one's imagined-experience corresponds in a certain way to a
-non-experience", a different matter (different belief).
-
-lf one's attention in believing is primarily on a linguistic expression
-(which if a sentence, will be pretty much regarded as its associated name),
-the self-deceiving attitude is the attitude "that the expression has a
-referent". With respect to the belief "that there is a table behind one", one's
-attention in believing would be primarily on the expression \expression{There is a table
-behind me}, pretty much regarded as 'There being a table behind me', and
-one would have the self-deceiving attitude "that this name has a referent".
-Unexplicatible expressions, then, function as principal components of
-beliefs.
-
-\inlineaside{This paragraph is complicated and inessential; if it begins to confuse
-the reader it can be skipped.} I will now describe the relation between the
-version, of a belief, involving language and the version not involving
-language. In the version not involving language, the attention is on an
-imagined-x-experience which is "regarded" as an x-experience, whereas in
-the version involving language, the attention is on something which is
-"regarded" as having as referent "something" (the attitude is vague here).
-For the latter version, the idea is "that the reality is at one remove", and
-correspondingly, one whose "language" consists of formulations of beliefs
-doesn't desire to have as experiences, or perceive, or even be able to imagine,
-referents of expressions---which, for the more critical person, may make
-believing easier. Thus, just as one takes note of the imagined-x-experience in
-the version of the belief not involving language, has something which
-functions as the thing the belief is about, so in the version involving language
-one has the attitude that the expression has a referent. Further, just as one
-has the attitude that the imagined-x-experience is an x-experience in the
-version not involving language, does not recognize that what functions as the
-thing believed in is a mere imagined-experience, so in the version involving
-"language" one takes note of an 'expression' not having a referent, since a
-referent could only be a (mere) experience. One who expects an expression,
-which is the principal component of a belief, to have a good explication does
-so on the basis of the self-deceiving attitude one has towards it in having the
-belief. In trying to explicate the expression, one finds inconsistent desires
-with respect to what its referents must be. These desires correspond to the
-way the expression functions in the belief: the desire that it be possible for
-awareness of the referent to be part of one's experience corresponds to the
-attitude, in believing, that the expression has a referent; and the desire that it
-not be possible for awareness of the referent to be (merely) part of one's
-experience corresponds to the expression's not having a referent in believing.
-Pointing out that the expression is unexplicable discredits the belief of which
-it is the principal component, just as pointing out that a belief not involving
-language consists of being attentive to an imagined-experience and having the
-attitude that it is not an imagined-experience, discredits that belief.
-
-Such, then, is what one does when one believes. If the reader is rather
-unconvinced by my description, especially because of my speaking of
-"attitudes", then let him consider the following summary: there must be
-something more to a mental act than just taking note of an experience for it
-to be a "belief"; this something is "peripheral and elusive", so that I am
-calling the something an "attitude", the most appropriate way in English to
-speak of it; the attitude, an experience not itself a belief but part of the
-experience which is the belief, is thus isolated; the attitude is
-"self-deceiving", is a "(conscious) self-deception experience", because when
-aware of it the reader will presumably want to say that it is. The attitude just
-about has to be a ("conscious") self-deception experience to transform mere
-taking note of an experience into something remotely deserving to be said to
-be a "belief". The decision as to whether the attitude is to be said to be
-"self-deceiving" is to be made without trying to think "about the relation of
-the belief as a whole to the realm of non-experience", to do which would be
-to slip into having beliefs, other than the one under consideration, which
-would be irrelevant to our concern here. Ultimately, the important thing is
-to observe what one does in believing, and particularly the attitude, more
-than to say that the attitude is "self-deceiving".
-
-In order for my description of believing to be complete, I must mention
-some things often associated with believing but not "essential" to it. First,
-one may take note of non-mental and imagined-experiences other than the
-one to which attention is primarily given. If one has a table-experience and
-believes "that it is a table-perception corresponding to an objectively existing
-table', one may give much of his attention to the table-experience in so
-believing, associate the table-experience strongly with the belief. One may in
-believing give attention to non-mental experiences supposed to be 'evidence
-for, confirmation of, one's belief" (more will be said about confirmation
-shortly). If one's attention in believing is primarily on the linguistic
-expression 'x', one may give attention to a referent of
-'imagined-x(-experience)', an "imagined-referent" of 'x'; or to
-imagined-y-experiences such that y-experiences are supposed, said, to be
-"analogous to the referent of 'x'". In the latter case the y-experiences will be
-mutually exclusive, and less importance will be given to them than would be
-to imagined-referents. An example of imagined-referents in believing is
-visualizing oneself with one's back to a table, as the imagined-referent of
-'There being a table behind one'. An example of imagined-y-experiences
-(such that y-experiences are mutually exclusive) which are said to be
-"analogous to referents", in believing, is the visualizations associated with
-beliefs "about entities wholly other than, transcending, experience, such as
-Being".
-
-Secondly, there are associated with beliefs logical "justifications",
-"arguments", for them, "defenses" of them. I will not bother to explicate
-the different kinds of justifications because it is so easy to say what is wrong
-with all of them. There are two points to be made. First, explication would
-show that the matter of justifications for beliefs is just a matter of language
-and beliefs of the kind already discussed. Secondly, as I have suggested
-before, whether a statement or belief is right is not dependent on what the
-justifications, arguments for it are. (If this seems to fail for inductive
-justification, the kind invoiving the citing of experience supposed to be
-evidence for, confirmation of, the belief, it is because the metaphysical
-assumptions on which induction is based are rarely stated. Without them
-inductive justifications are just non sequiturs. An example: this table has
-four legs; therefore ("it is more probable that") any other table has four
-legs.) Justification of a statement or belief does nothing but conjoin to it
-superfluous statements or beliefs, if anything. The claim that a justification,
-argument can show that a belief is not arbitrary, gratuitous, in that it can
-show that to be consistent, one must have the belief if one has a Sesser,
-weaker belief, is simply self-contradictory. If a justification induces one to
-believe what one apparently did not believe before hearing the justification,
-then one already had the belief "implicitly" (it was a conjunct of a belief
-one already had), or one has accepted superfluous beliefs conjoined with it.
-
-I will conclude this chapter first with a list of philosophical positions
-my position is not. Although I have already suggested some of this material,
-I repeat it because it is so important that the reader not misconstrue my
-position as some position which is no more like mine than its negation is,
-and which I show to be wrong. My position is not disbelief. (Incidentally, it
-is ironic that 'disbeliever', without qualification, has been used by believers
-as a term of abuse, since, as disbelief is belief which is the negation of some
-belief, any belief is disbelief.) In particular, I am not concerned to deny "the
-existence of non-experience", to "cause non-experiences to vanish", so to
-speak, to change or cause to vanish some of the reader's non-mental
-experiences, "perceived objects". My position is not skepticism of any kind,
-is not, for example, the belief "that there is a realm where there could either
-be or not be certain entities not experiences, but our means of knowing are
-inadequate for finding which is the case." My position is not a mere
-"decision to ignore non-experiences, or beliefs". The philosopher who denies
-"the existence of non-experiences", or denies any belief, or who is skeptical
-of any belief, or who merely "decides to ignore non-experiences, or beliefs",
-has some of the very beliefs I am concerned to discredit.
-
-What I have been concerned to do is to discredit formulations of
-beliefs, and beliefs as mental acts, by pointing out some features of them. In
-the first part of the book I showed the inconsistency of linguistic expressions
-dependent on 'non-experience', and pointed out that those who expect them
-to have explications at all acceptable are deceiving themselves; discrediting
-the beliefs of which the expressions are formulations. In this chapter, I have
-described the mental act of believing, calling the reader's attention to the
-self-deception experience involved in it, and thus showing that it is wrong.
-To conclude, in discrediting beliefs I have shown what the right
-philosophical position is: it is not having beliefs (and realizing, for any belief
-one happens to think of, that it is wrong (which doesn't involve having beliefs)).
-
-\subsection*{Chapter 6 : Discussion of Some Basic Beliefs}
-
-In the preceding chapters I have been concerned, in discrediting any
-given belief, to show what the right philosophical position is. In this chapter
-I will turn to particular beliefs, supposed knowledge, to make it clear just
-what, specifically, have been discredited. Now if the reader will consider the
-entire "history of world thought", the fantastic proliferation of activities at
-least partly "systems of knowledge" which constitute it, Platonism,
-psychoanalysis, Tibetian mysticism, physics, Bantu witchcraft,
-phenomenology, mathematical logic, Konko Kyo, Marxism, alchemy,
-comparative linguistics, Orgonomy, Thomism, and so on indefinitely, each
-with its own kind of conclusions, method of justifying them, applications,
-associated valuations, and the like, he will quickly realize that I could not
-hope to analyze even a fraction of them to show just how "non-experiential
-language", and beliefs, are involved in them. And I should say that it is not
-always obvious whether the concepts of non-experiential language, and
-belief, are relevant to them. Zen is an obvious example (although as a matter
-of fact is unquestionably does involve beliefs, is not for example an
-anticipation of my position). Further, many quasi-systems-of-knowledge are
-difficult to discuss because the expositions of them which are what one has
-to work with, are badly written, in particular, fail to state the insights behind
-what is presented, the real reasons why it can be taken seriously, and are
-incomplete and confused.
-
-What I will do, then, to specifically illustrate my results, is to discuss a
-few particular beliefs which are found in almost all systems of "knowledge";
-have been given especial attention in modern Western philosophy and are
-thus especially relevant to the immediate audience for this book; and are so
-"basic" (accounting for their ubiquity) that they are either just assumed, as
-too trivially factual to be worthy the attention of a profound thinker, or if
-they are explicit are said to be so basic that persons cannot do without them.
-The discussion will make it specifically clear that it is not necessary to have
-these beliefs, that not having them is not "inconsistent" with one's
-experience; and is thus important for the reader who is astonished at the idea
-of rejecting any given belief, the idea of any given belief's being wrong and
-of not having it.
-
-Consider beliefs to the effect "that the world is ordered", beliefs
-formulated in "natural laws", beliefs "about substance", and the like.
-Rejection of them may seem to lead to a problem. After all, one's "perceived
-world" is not "chaotic", is it? The reader should observe that in rejecting
-beliefs "that the world is ordered" I do not say that his "perceived world" is
-("subjectively") chaotic (that is, extremely unfamiliar, strange). The
-non-strange character of one's "perceived world" is associated with beliefs
-"about substance" and beliefs formulated in natural laws, but it is not "the
-world being ordered"; and taking note of the non-strange character of one's
-"perceived world" is not part of what is "essential" in these beliefs.
-
-Rejection of "spatio-temporal" beliefs may seem to lead to a problem.
-After all, cannot one watch oneself wave one's hand towards and away from
-oneself? Of course one can "watch oneself wave one's hand" (in a non-strict
-sense---and if the reader uses the expression in this sense it will not be a
-formulation of a belief for him). However, that one can "watch oneself wave
-one's hand" (in the non-strict sense) does not imply "that there are spatially
-distant, and past and future events"; and although experiences such as a
-visual---"moving"---hand experience are associated with spatio-temporal
-beliefs, taking note of them is not part of what is essential in those beliefs.
-
-Rejection of beliefs "about the objectivity of linguistic referring" may
-seem to lead to a problem. After all, when one says that a table is a "table",
-doesn't one do so unhesitatingly, with a feeling of satisfaction, a feeling that
-things are less mysterious, strange, when one has done so, and without the
-slightest intention of saying that it is a "non-table"? The reader should
-observe that I do not deny this. These experiences are associated with beliefs
-"about the objectivity of referring", but they are not "objective referring";
-and taking note of them is not part of what is essential in those beliefs.
-
-Rejection of the belief "that other humans (better, things) than oneself
-have minds" my seem to lead to a problem. After all, "perceived other
-humans" talk and so forth, do they not? The reader should observe that in
-rejecting the belief "that others have minds" I do not deny that "perceived
-other humans" talk and so forth. Other humans' talking and so forth is
-associated with the belief "that others have minds", but it is not "other
-humans having minds"; and taking note of others talking and so forth is not
-part of what is essential in believing "that others have minds", points I
-anticipated in the second chapter.
-
-Finally, many philosophers will violently object to rejection of
-temporal beliefs of a certain kind, namely beliefs of the form "If \x, then \y\
-will follow in the future", especially if \y\ is something one wants, and \x\ is
-something one can do. (After all, doesn't it happen that one throws the
-switch, and the light goes on?) They object so strongly because they fear
-"that one cannot live unless one has and uses such knowledge". They say,
-for example, "that one had better know that one must drink water to live,
-and drink water, or one won't live". Now "one's throwing the switch and the
-light's coming on" (in a non-strict sense) is like the experiences associated
-with other temporal beliefs; that one can do it (in the non-strict sense) does
-not imply "that there are past or future events", and taking note of it is not
-part of what is essential in the belief "that if one throws the switch, then the
-light will come on". As for what the philosophers say, fear, believe "about
-the necessity of such knowledge for survival", it is just more beliefs of the
-same kind, so that rejection of it is similarly unproblematic. If this abrupt
-dismissal of the fears as wrong is terrifying to the reader, then it just shows
-how badly he is in need of being straightened out philosophically.
-Incidentally, all this should make it clear that it is futile to try to "save"
-beliefs (render them justifiable) by construing them as predictions.
-
-By now the reader has probably observed that the beliefs, and their
-formulations, which I have been discussing, the ones he is presumably most
-suspicious of rejecting, are all strongly (but not essentially) associated with
-non-mental experiences of his. The reader may no longer seriously have the
-beliefs, but have problems in connection with them, get involved in
-defending them, and be suspicious of rejecting them, merely because he
-continues to use the formulations of the beliefs, but to refer to the
-experiences associated with them (as there's no other way in English to do
-so), and confusedly supposes that to reject the beliefs and formulations is to
-deny that he has the experiences. Now I am not denying that he has the
-experiences. As I said in the last chapter, I am not trying to convince the
-reader that he doesn't have experiences he has, but to point out to him the
-self-deception experiences involved in his beliefs. The reader should be wary
-of thinking, however, on reading this, that maybe he doesn't have any beliefs
-after all, just uses the belief language he does to refer to experiences. It
-sometimes happens that people who have beliefs and as a result use belief
-language excuse themselves on the basis that they are just using the language
-to refer to experiences, an hypocrisy. If one uses belief formulations, it's
-usually because one has beliefs.
-
-The point that the language which one may use to describe experiences
-is formulations of beliefs, is true generally. As I said in the third chapter, all
-English sentences are, traditionally anyway, formulations of beliefs. As a
-result, those who want to talk about experiences (my use) and still use
-English are forced to use formulations of beliefs to refer to strongly
-associated experiences, and this seems to be happening more and more; often
-among quasi-empiricists who naively suppose that the formulations have
-always been used that way, except by a few "metaphysicians". I have had to
-so use belief language throughout this book, the most notable example being
-the introduction of my use of "experience" in the third chapter. Thus, some
-of what I say may imply belief formulations for the reader when it doesn't
-for me, and be philosophically problematic for him; he must understand the
-book to some extent in spite of the language, as I suggested in the third
-chapter. I have tried to make this relatively easy by choosing, to refer to
-experiences, language with which they are very strongly associated and
-which is only weakly associated with beliefs, and, the important thing, by
-announcing when the language is used for that purpose.
-
-It is time, though, that I admit, so as not to be guilty of the hypocricy I
-was exposing earlier, that most of the sentences in this book will be
-understood as formulations of beliefs, that, in other words, I have presented
-my philosophy to the reader by getting him to have a series of beliefs. This
-does not invalidate my position, because the beliefs are not part of it. They
-are for the heuristic purpose of getting the reader to appreciate my position,
-which is not having beliefs (and realizing, for any belief one happens to think
-of, that it is wrong (which doesn't involve believing)); and they may well not
-be held when they have accomplished that purpose. I hope I will eventually
-get around to writing a version of this book which presents my position by
-suggesting to the reader a series of imaginings (and no more), rather than
-beliefs; developing a new language to do so. The reason I stick with English
-in this book is of course (!) that readers are too "unmotivated" (lazy!) to
-learn a language of an entirely new kind to read a book, having
-unconventional conclusions, in philosophy proper.
-
-\subsection*{Chapter 7 : Summary}
-
-The most important step in understanding my work is to realize that I
-am trying neither to get one to adopt a system of beliefs, nor to just ignore
-beliefs or the matter of whether they are right. Once the reader does so, he
-will find that my position is quite simple. The reader has probably tended to
-construe the body of the book, the second through the sixth chapters, as a
-formulation of a system of beliefs; or as a proposal that he ignore beliefs or
-the matter of whether they are right. Even if he has, a careful reading of
-them will, I hope, have prepared him for a statement of my position which is
-supposed to make it clear that the position is simple and right. This
-statement is a summary, and thus cannot be understood except in
-connection with the second through the sixth chapters. First, I reiterate that
-my position is not a system of beliefs, supported by a long, plausible
-argument. This means, incidentally, that it is absurd to "remain
-unconvinced" of the rightness of my position, or to "doubt, question" it, or
-to take a long time to decide whether it is right: one can "question" (not
-believe) disbelief, but not unbelief. (Not to mention that it is a wrong belief
-to be "skeptical" of my position in the sense of believing "that although the
-position may subjectively seem right, there is always the possibility that it is
-objectively wrong".) I am trying, not to get one to adopt new beliefs but to
-reject those one already has, not to make one more credulous but less
-credulous. If one "questions my position" then one is misconstruing it as a
-belief for which I try to give a long, plausible argument, and is trying to
-decide which is more plausible, my argument that all beliefs are false, say, or
-the arguments that beliefs are true. It may well take one a long time to
-understand my position, but if one is taking a long time to decide whether it
-is right then one is wasting one's time thinking about a position I show to be
-wrong. Secondly, my position is not a proposal that one ignore beliefs or the
-matter of whether they are right. Thus, it is absurd to conclude that my
-position is irrefutable but trivial, that one who has beliefs can also be right.
-
-Now for the statement of the position. Imagine yourself without
-beliefs. One certainly is without beliefs when one is not thinking, for
-example (although not only then). This being without beliefs is my position.
-Now this position can't be wrong inasmuch as you aren't doing anything to
-be "true or false", to be self-deceiving. Now imagine that someone asks you
-to believe something, for example, to believe "that there is a table behind
-you". Then if you are going to do what he asks, and believe (as opposed to
-continuing not to think; or only imagining---for example, "visualizing
-yourself with your back to a table"), you are going to have to have the
-attitude that you are in effect perceiving what you don't perceive, that is,
-deceive yourself. (What else could he be asking you to do?) You are going
-to have to be wrong. That's all there is to it.
+\tableofcontents*
-As for my language here, it is primarily intended to be suggestive,
-intended, at best, to suggest imaginings to you which will enable you to
-realize what the right philosophical position is (as in the last paragraph). The
-important thing is not whether the sentences in this book correspond to true
-statements in your language (although I expect the key ones will, the
-expressions in them being construed as referring to the experiences
-associated with them); it is for you to realize, observe what you do when
-you don't have beliefs and when you do. You are not so much to study my
-language as to begin to ask what one who asks you to believe wants you to
-do, anyway. The language isn't sufficiently flawless to absolutely force the
-complete realization of what the right position is on you (it doesn't have to
-be flawless to unquestionably discredit "non-experiential language"); if you
-don't want to realize where the self-deception is in believing you can just
-ignore the book, and "justify" your doing so on the basis of what I have said
-about language such as I have used. The point is that the book is not
-therefore valueless.
+\input{essays/introduction.tex}
-So much for what the right philosophical position is. From having
-beliefs to not having them is not a trivial step; it is a complete
-transformation of one's cognitive orientation. Yet astonishing as the latter
-position is when first encountered, does it not become, in retrospect,
-"obvious"? What other position could be the resolution of the fantastic
-proliferation of conflicting beliefs, and of the "profound" philosophical
-problems (for example, "Could an omnipotent god do the literally
-impossible?", "Are statements about what I did in the past while alone
-capable of intersubjective verification?") arising from them? And again, one
-begins to ask, when one is asked to believe something, what it is that one is
-wanted to do, anyway; and one's reaction to the request comes to be "Why
-bother? Cognitively, what is the value of doing so? I'd just be deceiving
-myself". Also, how much simpler my position is than that of the believer.
-And although in a way the believer's position is the more natural, since one
-"naturally" tends to deceive oneself if there's any advantage in doing so
-(that is, being right tends not to be valued), in another way my position is,
-since it is simple, and since the non-believer isn't worried by the doubts
-which arise for one who tries to keep himself deceived.
+\mainmatter
+\part{Philosophy}
+\input{essays/flaws_underlying_beliefs.tex}
+\input{essays/walking_through_walls.tex}
+\input{essays/philosophical_reflections.tex}
+\input{essays/flyntian_modality.tex}
+\input{essays/some_objections.tex}
+\input{essays/philosophy_proper.tex}
\part{Esthetics}
+\input{essays/down_with_art.tex}
+\input{essays/art_or_brend.tex}
+\input{essays/letters.tex}
-\chapter{Down With Art}
-
-\section{\textsc{Art} or \textsc{Brend}?}
-
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item Perhaps the most diseased justification the artist can give of his profession
-is to say that it is somehow scientific. LaMonte Young, Milton Babbitt, and
-Stockhausen are exponents of this sort of justification.
-
-The law which relates the mass of a body to its velocity has predictive value
-and is an outstanding scientific law. Is the work of art such a law? The
-experiment which shows that the speed of light is independent of the motion
-of its source is a measurement of a phenomenon crucial to the confirmation of
-a scientific hypothesis; it is an outstanding scientific experiment. Is the work
-of art such a measurement? The invention of the vacuum tube was an
-outstanding technological advance. Is the work of art such a technological
-advance? Differential geometry is a deductive analysis of abstract relations
-and an outstanding mathematical theory. ts the work of art such an
-analysis?
-
-The motives behind the "scientific" justification of art are utterly sinister.
-Perhaps LaMonte Young is merely rationalizing because he wants an
-academic job. But Babbitt is out to reduce music to a pedantic
-pseudo-science. And Stockhausen, with his "scientific music", intends
-nothing less than the suppression of the culture of "lower classes" and
-"ower races."
-
-It is the creative personality himself who has the most reason to object to
-the "scientific" justification of art. Again and again, the decisive step in
-artistic development has come when an artist produces a work that shatters
-all existing 'scientific' laws of art, and yet is more important to the
-audience than all the works that "obey" the laws.
-
-\item The artist or entertainer cannot exist without urging his product on other
-people. In fact, after developing his product, the artist goes out and tries to
-win public acceptance for it, to advertise and promote it, to sell it, to force it
-on people. If the public doesn't accept it at first, he is disappointed. He
-doesn't drop it, but repeatedly urges the product on them.
-
-People have every reason, then, to ask the artist: Is your product good for
-me even if I don't like or enjoy it? This question really lays art open. One of
-the distinguishing features of art has always been that it is very difficult to
-defend art without referring to people's liking or enjoying it. (Functions of
-art such as making money or glorifying the social order are real enough, but
-they are rarely cited in defense of art. Let us put them aside.) When one
-artist shows his latest production to another, all he can usually ask is "Do
-you like it?" Once the "scientific" justification of art is discredited, the
-artist usually has to admit: If you don't like or enjoy my product, there's no
-reason why you should "consume" it.
-
-There are exceptions. Art sometimes becomes the sole channel for political
-dissent, the sole arena in which oppressive social relations can be
-transcended. Even so, subjectivity of value remains a feature which
-distinguishes art and entertainment from other activities. Thus art is
-historically a leisure activity.
-
-\item But there is a fundamental contradiction here. Consider the object which
-one person produces for the liking, the enjoyment of another. The value of
-the object is supposed to be that you just like it. It supposedly has a value
-which is entirely subjective and entirely within you, is a part of you. Yet---the
-object can exist without you, is completely outside you, is not you or your
-valuing, and has no inherent connection with you or your valuing. The
-product is not personal to you.
-
-Such is the contradiction in much art and entertainment. it is unfortunate
-that it has to be stated so abstractly, but the discussion is about something
-so personal that there can be no interpersonal examples of it. Perhaps it will
-help to say that in appreciating or consuming art, you are always aware that
-it is not you, your valuing---yet your liking it, your valuing it is usually the
-only thing that can justify it.
-
-In art and entertainment, objects are produced having no inherent
-connection with people's liking, yet the artist expects the objects to find
-their value in people's liking them. To be totally successful, the object would
-have to give you an experience in which the object is as personal to you as
-your valuing of it. Yet you remain aware that the object is another's
-product, separable from your liking of it. The artist tries to "be oneself" for
-other people, to "express oneself" for them.
-
-\item There are experiences for each person which accomplish what art and
-entertainment fail to. The purpose of this essay is to make you aware of
-these experiences, by comparing and contrasting them with art. I have
-coined the term \term{brend} for these experiences.
-
-Consider all of your doings, what you already do. Exclude the gratifying of
-physiological needs, physically harmful activities, and competitive activites.
-Concentrate on spontaneous self-amusement or play. That is, concentrate on
-everything you do just because you like it, because you just like it as you do
-it.
-
-Actually, these doings should be referred to as your just-likings. In saying
-that somebody likes an art exhibit, it is appropriate to distinguish the art
-exhibit from his liking of it. But in the case of your just-likings, it is not
-appropriate to distinguish the objects valued from your valuings, and the
-single term that covers both should be used. When you write with a pencil,
-you are rarely attentive to the fact that the pencil! was produced by
-somebody other than yourself. You can use something produced by
-somebody else without thinking about it. In your just-likings, you never
-notice that things are not produced by you. The essence of a just-liking is
-that in it, you are not aware that the object you value is less personal to you
-than your very valuing.
-
-These just-likings are your \term{brend.} Some of your dreams are brend; and
-some children's play is brend (but formal children's games aren't). In a sense,
-though, the attempt to give interpersonal examples of brend is futile,
-because the end result is neutral things or actions, cut off from the valuing
-which gives them their only significance; and because the end result suggests
-that brend is a deliberate activity like carrying out orders. The only examples
-for you are your just-likings, and you have to guess them by directly
-applying the abstract definition.
-
-Even though brend is defined exclusively in terms of what you like, it is not
-necessarily solitary. The definition simply recognizes that valuing is an act of
-individuals; that to counterpose the likes of the community to the likes of
-the individuals who make it up is an ideological deception.
-
-\item It is now possible to say that much art and entertainment are
-pseudo-brend; that your brend is the total originality beyond art; that your
-brend is the absolute self-expression and the absolute enjoyment beyond art.
-Can brend, then, replace art, can it expand to fill the space now occupied by
-art and entertainment? To ask this question is to ask when utopia will
-arrive, when the barrier between work and leisure will be broken down,
-when work will be abolished. Rather than holding out utopian promises, it is
-better to give whoever can grasp it the realization that the experience
-beyond art already occurs in his life---but is totally suppressed by the general
-repressiveness of society.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-
-Note: The avant-garde artist may raise a final question. Can't art or
-entertainment compensate for its impersonality by having sheer newness as a
-value? Can't the very foreignness of the impersonal object be entertaining?
-Doesn't this happen with Mock Risk Games, for example? The answer is
-that entertainmenta! newness is also subjective. What is entertainingly
-strange to one person is incomprehensible, annoying, or irrelevant to
-another. The only difference between foreignness and other entertainment
-values is that brend does not have more foreignness than conventional
-entertainment does.
-
-As for objective newness, or the objective value of Mock Risk Games, these
-issues are so difficult that I have been unable to reach final conclusions
-about them.
-
-\clearpage
-
-\section{Letter from Terry Riley, Paris, to Henry Flynt, Cambridge,
-Mass., dated 11/8/62}
-
-One day a little boy got up and looked at his toys, appraised them and
-decided they were of no value to him so he did them in. Seeing that others
-were blindly and blissfully enjoying theirs he offered them a long and
-"radical new theory" of "pure recreation" for their enjoyment but before he
-let them in for this highly secret and "revolutionary theory" they should
-follow his example and partake of a little 20th C. iconoclasm. From those
-that balked he removed the label "avant-garde" and attached the label
-"traditionalist" or if they were already labeled "traditionalist" he added one
-more star. If they accepted they got a "hip" rating with gold cluster and if
-they comprehended the worth of his theory well enough to destroy their
-own art they would be awarded assignments to destroy those works whose
-designers were no longer around to speak out in their behalf.
-
-Now about this hip radical new theory of pure recreation.---Well---alor! its
-simply what people do anyway but don't realize it but it seems that what
-people "do anyway and don't realize it" will not be fully appreciated until
-"what people do in the name of art" is eliminated. If art can be relegated to
-obscurity, if some one can get John Coltrane to stop blowing, if someone
-can smash up all the old Art tatum records as well as all the existing pianos,
-if someone can get all that stuff out of those museums, If someone can only
-burn down all those concert halls, movie houses, small galleries as well as
-rooms in private houses that contain signs of art, If someone can do in all the
-cathedrals and monuments bridges etc, If someone can get rid of the sun,
-moon, stars, ocean, desert trees birds, bushes mountains, rivers, joy, sadness
-inspiration or any other natural phenomenon that reminds us of the ugly
-scourge art that has preoccupied and plagued man since he can remember
-then yes then at last Henry Flynt, sorry!
-
-\img{terry_flynt_name}
-
-will show us how to really enjoy ourselves. Whooopeeee
-
-\signoffnote{[Terry Riley's spelling etc. carefully preserved]}
-
-\clearpage
-
-\section{letter from Bob Morris to Henry Flynt, dated 8/13/62}
-
-Dear Henry,
-
-\gap
-
-perhaps the desirability of certain kinds of experience in art is not
-important. The problem has been for some time one of ideas---those most
-admired are the ones with the biggest, most incisive ideas (e.g. Cage \&
-Duchamp). The mere exertion in the direction of finding "new" ideas has
-not shown too much more than that it has become established as a
-traditional method; not much fruit has appeared on this vine. Also it can't be
-avoided that this is an academic approach which presupposes a history to
-react against---what I mean here is the kind of continuity one is aware of
-when involved in this activity: it just seems academic (if the term can
-somehow be used without so much emotion attached to it). The difficulty
-with new ideas is that they are too hard to manufacture. Even the best have
-only had a few good ones. (I suppose none of this is very clear and I can't
-seem to get in the mood to do any more than put it down in an off-hand
-way---but what I mean by "new ideas" is not only what you might call
-"Concept Art" but rather effecting changes in the structures of art forms
-more than any specific content or forms) Once one is committed to attempt
-these efforts---and tries it for a while---one becomes aware that if one wants
-"experience" one must repeat himself until other new things occur: a
-position difficult if not impossible to accept with large "idea" ambitions. So
-one remains idle, repeats things, or finds some form of concentration and
-duration outside the art---jazz, chess, whatever. I think that today art is a
-form of art history.
-
-I don't think entertainment solves the problem presented by avant gard art
-since entertainment has mostly to do with replacing that part of art which is
-now hard to get---i.e. experience. It seems to me that to be concerned with
-"just liked" things as you present it is to avoid such things as tradition in art
-(some body of stuff to react against---to be thought of as opponent or
-memory or however). As I said before, I for one am not so self-sufficient and
-when avoiding "given" structures, e.g. art, or even the most tedious and
-decorous forms of social intercourse, I am bored. If I need concentration,
-which I do, I can't think of anything on my own as good as chess.
-
-One accepts language, one accepts logic.
-
-\signoff{Best regards,}
-\signoff{Bob Morris}
-
-\section{}
-
-{
-\raggedleft
-\textsc{From "Culture" to Veramusement} \\
-Boston--New York \\
-\textsc{Press Release:} for March--April, 1963 \par
-}
-
-
-Henry Flynt, Tony Conrad, and Jack Smith braved the cold to demonstrate
-against Serious Culture (and art) on Wednesday, February 27. They began at
-the Museum of Modern Art at 1:30 p.m., picketing with signs bearing the
-slogans
-\textsc{Demolish serious culture! / Destroy art!} ;
-\textsc{Demolish art museums! / No more art!} ;
-\textsc{Demolish concert halls! / Demolish Lincoln Center!} ;
-and handing out announcements of
-Flynt's lecture the next evening. Benjamin Patterson came up to give
-encouragement. There was much spontaneous interest among people around
-and in the Museum. At about 1:50, a corpulent, richly dressed Museum
-official came out and imperiously told the pickets that he was going to
-straighten them out, that the Museum had never been picketed, that it could
-not be picketed without its permission, that it owned the sidewalk, and that
-the pickets would have to go elsewhere. The picket who had obtained police
-permission for the demonstration was immediately dispatched to call the
-police about the matter, while the other two stood aside. !t was found that
-the Museum official had not told the truth; and the picketing was resumed.
-People who care about the rights of pickets generally should recognize the
-viciousness of, and oppose, the notion that picketing can only be at the
-permission of the establishment being picketed. (As for previous picketing of
-the Museum, it is a matter of record.) Interest in the demonstration
-increased; people stopped to ask questions and talk. There was a much
-greater demand for announcements than could be supplied. Some people
-indicated their sympathy with the demonstrators. The demonstrators then
-went on to the Metropolitan Museum of Art. Because of the unexpected
-requirement of a permit to picket on a park street, they had to picket on
-Lexington Avenue, crossing 82nd Street. As a result they were far from the
-fools lined up to worship the Mona Lisa, but there was still interest. Finally,
-they went to Philharmonic Hall. Because of the time, not many people were
-there, but still there was interest; people stopped to talk and wanted more
-announcements than were available. The demonstrations ended at 3:45 p.m.
-Photos of the pickets were taken at all three places.
-
-On Thursday evening, February 28, at Walter DeMaria's loft, Henry Flynt
-gave a long lecture expositing the doctrine the Wednesday demonstrations
-were based on. On entering the lecture room, the visitor found himself
-stepping in the face of a Mona Lisa print placed as the doormat. To one side
-was an exhibition of demonstration photos and so forth. Behind the lecturer
-was a large picture of Viadimir Mayakovsky, while on either side were the
-signs used in the demonstrations, together with one saying
-\textsc{Veramusement---Not culture}. About 20 people came to the lecture.
-The lecturer showed first the suffering caused by Serious-Cultural snobbery,
-by its attempts to force individuals in line with things supposed to have
-objective validity, but actually representing only alien subjective tastes
-sanctioned by tradition. He then showed that artistic categories have
-disintegrated, and that their retention has become obscurantist. (He showed
-that the purpose of didactic art is better served by documentaries.) Finally,
-in the most intellectually sophisticated part of the lecture, he showed the
-superiority of each individual's veramusement (partially defined on the
-lecture announcement) to institutionalized amusement activities (which
-impose foreign tastes on the individual) and indeed to all "culture" the
-lecture was concerned with. After the lecture, Flynt told how his doctrine
-was anticipated by little known ideas of Mayakovsky, Dziga Vertov, and
-their group, as related in Ilya Ehrenburg's memoirs and elsewhere. He
-touched on the Wednesday demonstrations. He spoke of George Maciunas'
-\textsc{Fluxus}, with which all this is connected. Several people at the lecture
-congratulated Flynt on the clarity of the presentation and logicality of the
-arguments. Photos were taken.
-
-\section{Statement of November 1963}
-
-
-Back in March 1963, I sent the first \textsc{FCTB Press Release}, about FCTB's
-February picketing and lecture, to all the communications media, including
-the New Yorker. It is so good that the New Yorker wanted to use it, but
-they didn't want to give FCTB any free publicity; so they finally published
-an inept parody of it, in the October 12, 1963 issue, pp. 49--51. They
-changed my last name to Mackie, changed February 27 to September 25, the
-Museum of Modern Art to a church, changed our slogans to particularly
-idiotic ones (although they got in '\textsc{No More Art/Culture?}', later on),
-and added incidents; but the general outlines, and the phrases lifted verbatim
-from the FCTB RELEASE, make the relationship clear.---Henry Fiynt
-
-\section{}
-
-{ \raggedleft 3/6/63 \par }
-
-Henry,
-
-
-Received your note this morning. I had written down a few things about the
-lecture the very night I got home but decided they were not very clear so I
-didn't send them. Don't know if I can make it any clearer\ldots actually I keep
-thinking that I must have overlooked something because the objection I have
-to make seems too obvious. You spend much time and effort locating
-Veramusement, stating clearly wnat it is not, and stating that it is, if I get it,
-of the essence of an awareness, rather memory, of an experience which
-cannot be predicted and therefore cannot be located or focused by external
-activities. And, in fact, as you said, may cut across, or "intersect" one or
-another or several activities. You have discredited activities---like art,
-competitive games---as pseudo work or unsatisfactory recreation by employing
-arguments which are external to "experiencing" these activities (e.g. chess is
-bad because why agree to some arbitrary standard of performance which
-doesn't fit you)\ldots well it seems to me that Veramusement could never replace
-any cultural form because it has no external "edges" but rather by definition
-can occur anywhere anytime anyplace (By the way I want to say here that
-its existence as a past tense or memory I find objectionable---but I can't at the
-moment really say why.) It seems that you have these two things going:
-Veramusement, that has to do with experience, and art, work,
-entertainment, that have to do with society and I don't think that the
-exposition of how the two things are related has been very clear. George
-Herbert Mead, an early Pragmatist (don't shudder at that word, but I can see
-you throwing up your hands in despair) talked about this relation as a kind
-of double aspect of the personality (which he called the "me" and the "I"
-\ldots can't remember his book, something like \booktitle{Mind, Self, and Society}).
-
-I thought you presented the lecture very weil, but towards the end I was
-getting too tired to listen very carefully and I am sorry because this was the
-newest writing. I would like very much to read this part, i.e. that which dealt
-with the evolution of work, automation and the liberation from
-drudgery---send me a copy if you can.
-
-\signoff{Best regards,}
-\signoff{Bob Morris}
-
-\section{}
-
-{ \raggedleft 3/12/1963 \par }
-Henry
-
-\begin{tabular}{ c c c c c }
- \redact{Jazz} &
- \redact{Cage} &
- \redact{"Folk Music"} &
- \redact{Communism} &
- \begin{tabular}{ c }
- (anti-art?) \\
- ------ \\
- (communism) \\
- \end{tabular} \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-I've been along this road too.
-Yes I certainly do see the harmfullness of serious culture. My favorite movies are plain documentaries.
-
-\gap
-
-
-"Veramusement"
-questions: the way you set it up it sound like veramusement is \textsc{It}. Some
-kind of Absolute good state or activity. ---ie) \textsc{Athletics} are out. \\
----now my brother is a healthy athelete---he enjoys nothing so much as
-swimming or playing tennis all day (he likes to use his body---and he likes the
-form---competition)
-
-{ \centering
-Is this "wrong" \\
-Should he stop.--- \par
-}
-
-or wouldn't your "creep theory" which lets each person be himself and
-relish in himself---by extention from this---shouldn't the atheletic person be
-alowed to be himself? ---too. \\
-I think you were opening up the world to the people at the lecture---
-
-
-{
-making them move free--
-" " ready to be themselves \par
-}
-
-
-I think you were right in not giving examples!
-
-
-however \\
-your absolute---statements and "come on"---and blend with the communist
-ideas---(My mind was pretty tired by then and I didn't follow how the
-veramusement---was tied to communism)---this \textsc{It} kind of talk.---can only shoo
-people off-and let them wait for the next revision or explication. \\
-people off---and let them wait for the next revision or explication.
-
-\signoff{Walter DeMaria}
-
-\section{}
-
-Dear Henry, March 18, 1963
-
-
-As I said before, my main reactions to yr lecture \& ideas is that I'm for
-Henry Flynt but not for his ideas. I think the spirit you show in carrying on
-yr crusade is admirable and exciting. However, I am not against art and think
-that any artist who would say that he is or think that he is would be
-masochistic enough to need psychiatric care. Since you make no claims to
-being an artist this does not refer to you. However, I do call myself a poet
-and do think of myself as one. I like art, culture, etc. and do not yet feel
-that I am being screwed by it. Until I do, I will not need to turn to anti-art
-movements.
-
-All best wishes.
-
-Yours,
-
-Diane Wakoski
-
-\section{}
-
-"Dear Mr. Flynt...Since I may be depending on o-ganized culture for my
-loot \& livelihood I can wish you only a limited success in your movement...
-Cornelius Cardew" [froma postcard of June 7, 1963]
-
-
-\clearpage
-
-{
-2/22/1963
-
-
-Jack Smith and Henry Flynt demonstrate against the
-February 22, 1963
-
-
-(photo by Tony Conrad)
-
-Museum of Modern Art,
-}
-\clearpage
-
-
-\part{Para---science}
-
-
-\chapter{The Perception-Dissociation of Physics}
-
-
-From the physicist's point of view, the human dichotomy of sight and
-touch is a coincidence. It does not correspond to any dichotomy in the
-objective physical world. Light exerts pressure, and substances hot to the
-touch emit infrared light. It is just that the range of human receptors is too
-limited for them to register the tactile effect of light or the visual effect of
-moderate temperatures.
-
-Our problem is to determine what observations or experiences would
-cause the physicist to say that the objective physical world had split along
-the humen sight-touch boundary, to say that the human sight-touch
-dichotomy was an unavoidable model of objective physical reality. Our
-discussion is not about perfectly transparent matter, or light retlection and
-emission in the absence of matter, or the dissociation of electromagnetic and
-inertial phenomena, or the fact that human sight registers light, while touch
-registers inertia, bulk modulus, thermal conduction, friction, adhesion, and
-so on. (However, these concepts may have to be introduced to complete our
-discussion.) Our discussion is about a change in the physicist's observations
-or experiences, such that the anomalous state of affairs would be an
-experimental analogue to the sight-touch dichotomy of philosophical
-subjectivism. Of course, philosophical subjectivism itself will not enter the
-discussion.
-
-Because of the topic, our discussion will often seem psychological and
-even philosophical. However, the psychology involved always has to do with
-experimentally demonstrable aspects of perception. The philosophy involved
-is always scientific concept formation, the relating of concepts to
-experiments. Sooner or later it will be clear that our only concern is with
-experiences that would cause a physicist to modify physics.
-
-Throughout much of the discussion, we have to assume that the human
-physicist exists before the sight-touch split occurs, that he continues to exist
-after it occurs, and that he functions as a physicist after it occurs. Therefore,
-we begin as follows. A healthy human has a realm of sights, and a realm of
-touches: and there is a correlation between the two which receives its highest
-expression in the concept of the object. (In psychological jargon, intermodal
-organization contributes to the object Gestalt. Incidentally, for us "touch"
-includes just about every sense except sight, hearing, smell.) Suppose there is
-a change in which the tactile realm remains coherent, if not exactly the same
-as before, and the visual realm also remains coherent; but the correlation
-between the two becomes completely chaotic. A totally blind person does
-not directly experience any incomprehensible dislocation, nor does a person
-with psychogenic tactile anesthesia (actually observed in hysteria patients).
-Let us define such a change. Consider the sight-touch correlation identified
-with closing one's eyes. The point is that there is a whole realm of sights
-which do not occur when one can feel that one's eyes are closed.
-
-Let $T$ indicate tactile and $V$ indicate visual. Let the tactile sensation of
-open eyes be $T_1$, and of closed eyes be $T_2$. Now anything that can be seen
-with closed eyes---from total blackness, to the multicolored patterns produced
-by waving the spread fingers of both hands between closed eyes and direct
-sunlight---can no doubt be duplicated for open eyes. Closed-eye sights are a
-subset of open-eye sights. Thus, let sights seen only with open eyes be $V_1$,
-and sights seen with either open or closed eyes be $V_2$: If there are sights seen
-only with closed eyes, they will be $V_3$; we want disjoint classes. We are
-interested in the temporal concurrence of sensations. Combining our
-definitions with information about our present world, we find there are no
-intrasensory concurrences (eyes open and closed at the same time). Further,
-our change will not produce intrasensory concurrences, because each realm
-will remain coherent. Thus, we will drop them from our discussion. There
-remain the intersensory concurrences, and four can be imagined; let us
-denote them by the ordered pairs $(T_1, V_1), (T_1, V_2), (T_2, V_1), (T_2, V_2)$. In
-reality, some concurrences are permitted and others are forbidden, Let us
-designate each ordered pair as permitted or forbidden, using the following
-notation. Consider a rectangular array of "places" such that the place in the
-ith row and jth column corresponds to $(T_i, V_j)$, and assign a $p$ or $f$ (as
-appropriate) to each place. Then the following state array is a description of
-regularities in our present world.
-
-$$\begin{pmatrix}
- p & p\\
- f & p
-\end{pmatrix}$$
-
-
-So far as temporal successions of concurrences (within the présent
-world) are concerned, any permitted concurrence may succeed any other
-permitted concurrence. The succession of a concurrence by itself is
-excluded, meaning that at the moment, a $V_1$, is defined as lasting from the
-time the eyes open until the time they next close.
-
-We have said that our topic is a certain change; we can now indicate
-more precisely what this change is. As long as we have a 2x2 array, there are
-16 ways it can be filled with p's and f's. That is, there are 16 imaginable
-states. The changes we are interested in, then, are specific changes from the
-present state
-$\begin{pmatrix}
- p & p \\
- f & p
-\end{pmatrix}$ to another state such as
-$\begin{pmatrix}
- p & f \\
- p & p
-\end{pmatrix}$.
-
-However,
-we want to exclude some changes. The change that changes nothing is
-excluded. We aren't interested in changing to a state having only f's, which
-amounts to blindness. A change to a state with a row or column of f's leaves
-one sight or touch completely forbidden (a person becomes blind to
-open-eye sights); such an "impairment" is of little interest. Of the remaining
-changes, one merely leaves a formerly permitted concurrence forbidden:
-closed-eye sights can no longer be seen with open eyes. The rest of the
-changes are the ones most relevant to perception-dissociation. They are
-changes in the place of the one f; the change to the state having only p's;
-and finally
-
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c l }
- $\begin{pmatrix}
- p & p \\
- f & p
- \end{pmatrix}$ &
- ->
- &
- $\begin{pmatrix}
- f & p \\
- p & f
- \end{pmatrix}$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-In general, we speak of a partition of a sensory realm into disjoint
-classes of perceptions, so that the two partitions are $[T_j]$ and $[V_j]$. The
-number of classes in a partition, m for touch and n for sight, is its
-detailedness. The detailedness of the product partition $[T_j]\times [V_j]$ is written
-$m\times n$. This detailedness virtually determines the $(mn)^2$ imaginable states,
-although it doesn't determine their qualitative content. Now suppose one
-change is followed by another, so that we can speak of a change series. It is
-important to realize that by our definitions so far, a change series is not a
-conposition of functions; it is a temporal phenomenon in which each state
-lasts for a finite time. (A function would be a genera! rule for rewriting
-states. A 2X2 rule might say, rotate the state clockwise one place, from
-$\begin{pmatrix}a & b \\ c & d\end{pmatrix}$ to
-$\begin{pmatrix}c & a \\ d & b\end{pmatrix}$.
-
-But a composition of rules would not be a temporal series; it would be a new
-rule.) Returning to the sorting of changes, we always exclude the no-change
-changes, and states having only f's. We are unenthusiastic about "impairing"
-changes, changes to states with rows or columns of f's. Of the remaining
-changes, some merely forbid, repiacing p's with f's. The rest of the changes
-are the most perception-dissociating ones.
-
-As for changes in the succession state in the eye case, either they leave
-the forbidden concurrence permitted; or else they merely leave permitted
-successions forbidden---for example, in order to open your eyes in the dark
-you might have to open them in the light and then turn the light off. These
-secondary changes are of secondary interest.
-
-If we simply continue with the material we already have, two lines of
-investigation are possible. The first investigation is mathematical, and
-apparently amounts to combinatorial algebra. The second investigation
-concerns the relation between concurrences and commands of the will
-(observable as electrochemica! impulses along efferent neurons). If a change
-occurs, and the perceptual feedback from a willed command consists of a
-formerly forbidden concurrence, is it T or V that conflicts with the
-command? Is it that you tried to close your eyes but couldn't get the sight
-to go away, or that you were trying to look at something but felt your eyes
-close anyway?
-
-Before we carry out these investigations, however, we must return to
-our qualitative theory. If one of our eye changes happens to a physicist, he
-may immediately conclude that the cause of the anomaly is in himself, that
-the anomaly is psychological. But suppose that starting with a state for an
-extremely detailed product partition describing the present world, a whole
-change series occurs. Let p's be black dots and f's be white dots, and imagine
-a continuously shaded gray rectangle whose shading suddenly changes from
-time to time. We evoke this image to impress on the reader the
-extraordinary qualities of our concept, which can't be conveyed in ordinary
-English. Suppose also that to the extent that communication between
-scientists is still possible, perhaps in Braille, everybody is subjected to the
-same changes. !f the physicist turns to his instruments, he finds that the
-anomalies have spread to his attempts to use them. The changes affect
-everything-- everything, that is, except the intrasensory coherence of each
-sensory realm. Intrasensory coherence becomes the only stable reference
-point in the "world." The question of "whether the anomaties are really
-outside or only in the mind" comes to have less and less scientific meaning.
-If physics survived, it would have to recognize the touch-sight dichotomy as
-a physical one! This scenario helps answer a question the reader may have
-had: what is the methodological status of our states? They don't seem to be
-either physics or psychology, yet it is quite clear how we would know if the
-asserted regularities had changed; in fact, that is the whole point of the
-states. The answer is that the states are perfectly good assertions (of
-observed regularities) which would acquire primary importance if the
-changes actually occurred. In fact, the changes would among other things
-shift the boundaries of physics and psychology; but we insist that our
-interest is in the physicist's side of the boundary. To complete the
-investigation we have outlined, the relation between what the states say and
-what existing physics says should be established, so that we will know what
-has to be done to the photons and electrons to produce the changes. It is the
-same as with time travel: the hard part is deciding what it is and the even
-harder part is making it happen.
-
-\visbreak
-
-However, the foundations of our qualitative theory are not yet
-satisfactory, We have assumed that the physicist will be able to identify the
-subjective concurrences of perceptions, and will be able to identify his
-perceptions themselves, even if sense correlation becomes completely
-chaotic. We have assumed that the physicist will be able to say "I see a book
-in my hand but I concurrently feel a pencil." These assumptions may not be
-justified at all. It is quite likely that the physicist will say, "I don't even
-know whether the sight and the touch seem concurrent; I don't even know
-whether I think I see a book; I don't even know whether this sensation is
-visual." In fact, the anomalies may cause the physicist to decide that books
-never looked like books in the first place. In this case, the occurrence of the
-changes would render meaningless the terms in which the changes are
-defined. Alternately, if the changes produce a localized chaos, so that
-everything fits together except the book seen in the hand, the physicist may
-literally force himself to re-see that-book as a pencil, and in time this
-compensation may become habitual and "pre-conscious." In this case, if the
-physicist remembers the changes, he will be convinced that they were a
-temporary psychological malfunction.
-
-These criticisms are based on the fact that our simple perceptions are
-actually learned, "unconscious" interpretations of raw data which by
-themselves don't look like anything. This fact is demonstrated by a vast
-number of standard experiments in which the raw data are distorted, the
-subject perceptually adapts to the distorted data, and then the subject is
-confronted with normal sensations again. The subject finds that the old
-familiar sensation of a table looks quite wrong, and that he has to make an
-effort to see the table which he knows is there.
-
-Consider a modification of the clock-bell simultaneity experiment. The
-subject sits facing a large clock with a second-hand. His hearing is blocked in
-some way. Behind him, completely unseen, is a device which can give hima
-quick tap, a tactile sensation. There is also an unseen movie camera which
-photographs both the tactile contact and the clock face. The subject is
-tapped, and must call out the second-hand reading at the time of the tap. We
-expect a discrepancy between what the subject says and what the film says;
-but even if there is none, the experiment can proceed. Teli the subject that
-he always placed the tap earlier than it actually occurred, and that he will be
-given a reward if he learns to perceive more accurately. The purpose of the
-experiment is to demonstrate to the subject that even his perception of
-subjective simultaneity can be consciously modified. In the course of
-modification, he may not even know whether two perceptions seem
-simultaneous.
-
-This criticism of the changes defined earlier is important, but it may
-not be insurmountable. Although Stratton became used to his trick
-eyeglasses, the image continued to seem distorted. There is some stability to
-our identification of our perceptions. Also, the physicist in our earlier
-scenario might ultimately adapt to the changes. He might realize that it is
-possible separately to identify sights and touches. Only the sight-touch
-correlation is unidentifiable; and the concept of such a correlation might
-become an abstract concept of physics just as the concept of particle
-resonance is today.
-
-Time is inescapably involved in our discussion; so we must decide what
-happens to time as a distinct physical category, and as a sense, in
-perception-dissociation. Here, we will simply distinguish three sorts of time.
-First, there is subjective concurrence, which we have already begun to
-discuss. Secondly, there is the physicist's operational definition of time.
-There must be two repeating processes, which to the best of our knowledge
-are causally independent, so that irregularities in one process aren't
-automatically introduced in the other. !f the ratio of the repetitions of the
-two processes is constant, we assume that the repetitions divide time into
-equal intervals. Eventually the physicist arrives at a concept of time as a real
-line along which movement can be both forward and backward (Feynman).
-One effect of perception-dissociation relating to this sort of time would be
-to disrupt the ratios of visual clocks (such as electric wall clocks) to tactile
-clocks (such as the pulse). The third idea of time comes from an unpublished
-manuscript by John Alten, a Harvard classmate of mine. According to Alten,
-our most intimate sensation of futurity is associated with our acts of will.
-"The future" is simply the time of willing. In comparison with volitional
-futurity, the physicist's linear, reversible time is a mere spatial concept. The
-empirical importance of Alten's idea is thet it raises the question of what the
-perceptual frustration of the will (as we defined it) would do to the sense of
-futurity.
-
-\visbreak
-
-We now come to some considerations which will help us develop the
-state descriptions, and which also show that from one point of view, the
-states are actually necessary for the operational definition of physical
-language. Let parallel but separated sheets of clear plastic and colored plastic
-be mounted in lighting conditions so that the subject can't see the clear
-plastic. He touches the clear plastic, but from what he sees, he believes he is
-touching the colored plastic. The lighting is then changed and his error is
-exposed. In some sense, the sight-touch concurrence identifying an object
-was a mere coincidence. Next, we produce another colored sheet for the
-subject to touch, and we are able to convince him that this time the
-object-identifying concurrence is more than a coincidence.
-
-The physicist interprets this latter case by saying that the matter which
-resists the pressure of the subject's finger also reflects the light into his eyes.
-To the extent that the physicist's interpretation is causal, it employs the
-concept of "matter," a concept which is not really either visual or tactile.
-The physicist explains a sight and a touch with a reference beyond both sight
-and touch. It is important, then, to know the operational definition of the
-physicist's statement, the testing procedures which give the statement its
-immediate meaning. What is significant is that the testing procedures cannot
-be reduced to purely visual procedures or purely tactile procedures.
-Affecting the world requires tactile operations; and the visual "reading" of
-the world is so woven into physics that it can't be given up. Yet our
-experiment showed that the subject can be fooled by object-identifying
-concurrences, and the physicist is supposed to te!l us how to avoid being
-fooled.
-
-We find, then, that there is nothing the physicist can appeal to, in
-testing object-identifying concurrences, that doesn't immediately rely on
-other object-identifying concurrences, the very concurrences which are
-suspect. It is as if the physicist proposed to prove that clicks come from a
-certain metronome by manipulating a detecting device that outputs its data
-as sounds. But suppose the physicist proves that the clicks come from the
-metronome by showing (1) that the metronome has to be stopped or
-removed to stop the clicks, and (2) that the clicks stop if the metronome is
-stopped or removed. The physicist proves that the object-identifying
-concurrence is not a coincidence by demonstrating that certain related
-concurrences are forbidden. We suggest that the physicist ultimately handles
-touch-sight concurrences in just this way. The operational basis of the
-physicist's activity comes down to our states. (But note that the physicist
-has tests, which do not rely directly on his hearing, to determine whether the
-clicks come from the metronome!) One way to develop our states, then,
-may be to develop substates which express the differences between those
-object-identifying concurrences that are coincidental and those that
-aren't---the differences illustrated by the plastic sheet experiment.
-
-
-\clearpage
-{ 2/22/1963
-
-
-Henry Flynt and Jack Smith demonstrate against the Metropolitan Museum of Art,
-February 22, 1963 \\
-(foto\footnote{sic} by Tony Conrad)
-} \clearpage
-
-\chapter{1966 Mathematical Studies}
-
-% TODO start these section numbers at 0? (this should work)
-\section*{0. Introduction}
-
-Pure mathematics is the one activity which is intrinsically formalistic. It
-is the one activity which brings out the practical value of formal
-manipulations. Abstract games fit in perfectly with the tradition and
-rationale of pure mathematics; whereas they would not be appropriate in
-any other discipline. Pure mathematics is the one activity which can
-appropriately develop through innovations of a formalistic character.
-
-Precisely because pure mathematics does not have to be immediately
-practical, there is no intrinsic reason why it should adhere to the normal
-concept of logical truth. No harm is done if the mathematician chooses to
-play a game which is indeterminate by normal logical standards. All that
-matters is that the mathematician clearly specify the rules of his game, and
-that he not make claims for his results which are inconsistent with his rules.
-
-Actually, my pure philosophical writings discredit the concept of
-logical truth by showing that there are flaws inherent in all non-trivial
-language. Thus, no mathematics has the logical validity which was once
-claimed for mathematics. From the ultimate philosophical standpoint, all
-mathematics is as "indeterminate" as the mathematics in this monograph.
-All the more reason, then, not to limit mathematics to the normal concept
-of logical truth.
-
-Once it is realized that mathematics is intrinsically formalistic, and need
-not adhere to the normal concept of logical truth, why hold back from
-exploring the possibilities which are available? There is every reason to
-search out the possibilities and present them. Such is the purpose of this
-monograph.
-
-The ultimate test of the non-triviality of pure mathematics is whether it
-has practical applications. I believe that the approaches presented on a very
-abstract level in this monograph will turn out to have such applications. In
-order to be applied, the principles which are presented here have to be
-developed intensively on a level which is compatible with applications. The
-results will be found in my two subsequent essays, \essaytitle{Subjective Propositional
-Vibration} and \essaytitle{The Logic of Admissible Contradictions}.
-
-\section{Post-Formalism in Constructed Memories}
-\subsection{Post-Formalist Mathematics}
-
-Over the last hundred years, a philosophy of pure mathematics has
-grown up which I prefer to call "formalism." As Willard Quine says in the
-fourth section of his essay "Carnap and Logical Truth,' formalism was
-inspired by a series of developments which began with non-Euclidian
-geometry. Quine himself is opposed to formalism, but the formalists have
-found encouragement in Quine's own book, \booktitle{Mathematical Logic}. The best
-presentation of the formalist position can be found in Rudolph Carnap's
-\booktitle{The Logical Syntax of Language}. As a motivation to the reader, and
-as a heuristic aid, I will relate my study to these two standard books. (It will
-heip if the reader is thoroughly familiar with them.) it is not important
-whether Carnap, or Quine, or formalism---or my interpretation of them---is
-"correct," for this essay is neither history nor philosophy. I am using history
-as a bridge, to give the reader access to some extreme mathematical
-innovations.
-
-The formalist position goes as follows. Pure mathematics is the
-manipulation of the meaningless and arbitrary, but typographically
-well-defined ink-shapes on paper 'w,' 'x,' 'y,' 'z,' '{}',' '(,' '),' '$\downarrow$,' and '$\in$.'
-These shapes are manipulated according to arbitrary but well-detined
-mechanical rules. Actually, the rules mimic the structure of primitive
-systems such as Euclid's geometry. There are formation rules, mechanical
-definitions of which concatenations of shapes are "sentences." One sentence
-is '$((x) (x\in x) \downarrow (x) (x\in x))$.' There are transformation rules, rules for the
-mechanical derivation of sentences from other sentences. The best known
-trasformation rule is the rule that $\psi$ may be concluded from $\varphi$ and
-$\ulcorner \varphi \supset \psi \urcorner$;
-where '$\supset$' is the truth-functional conditional. For later convenience, I will
-say that $\varphi$ and $\ulcorner \varphi \supset \psi \urcorner$ are "impliors,"
-and that $\psi$ is the "implicand."
-Some sentences are designated as "axioms." A "proof" is a series of
-sentences such that each is an axiom or an implicand of preceding sentences.
-The last sentence in a proof is a "theorem."
-
-This account is ultrasimplified and non-rigorous, but it is adequate for
-my purposes. (The reader may have noticed a terminological issue here. For
-Quine, an implication is merely a logically true conditional. The rules which
-are used to go from some statements to others, and to assemble proofs, are
-rules of inference. The relevant rule of inference is the modus ponens; $\psi$ is
-the ponential of $\varphi$ and $\ulcorner \varphi \supset \psi \urcorner$. What I
-am doing is to use a terminology of
-implication to talk about rules of inference and ponentials. The reason is
-that the use of Quine's terminology would result in extremely awkward
-formulations. What I will be doing is sufficiently transparent that it can be
-translated into Quine's terminology if necessary. My results will be
-unaffected.) The decisive feature of the arbitrary game called "mathematics"
-is as follows. A sentence-series can be mechanically checked to determine
-whether it is a proof. But there is no mechanical method for deciding
-whether a sentence is a theorem. Theorems, or rather their proofs, have to be
-puzzled out, to be discovered. in this feature lies the dynamism, the
-excitement of traditional mathematics. Traditional mathematical ability is
-the ability to make inferential discoveries.
-
-
-A variety of branches of mathematics can be specialized out from the
-basic system. Depending on the choices of axioms, systems can be
-constructed which are internally consistent, but conflict with each other. A
-system can be "interpreted," or given a meaning within the language of a
-science such as physics. So interpreted, it may have scientific value, or it may
-not. But as pure mathematics, all the systems have the same arbitrary status.
-
-By "formalist mathematics" I will mean the present mathematical
-systems which are presented along the above lines. Actually, as many authors
-have observed, the success of the non-Euclidian "imaginary" geometries
-made recognition of the game-like character of mathematics inevitable.
-Formalism is potentially the greatest break with tradition in the history of
-mathematics. In the Foreward to \booktitle{The Logical Syntax of Language}, Carnap
-brilliantly points out that mathematical innovation is still hindered by the
-widespread opinion that deviations from mathematical tradition must be
-justified---that is, proved to be "correct" and to be a faithful rendering of
-"the true logic." According to Carnap, we are free to choose the rules of a
-mathematical system arbitrarily. The striving after correctness must cease, so
-that mathematics will no longer be hindered. \said{Before us lies the boundless
-ocean of unlimited possibilities.} In other words, Carnap, the most reputable
-of academicians, says you can do anything in mathematics. Do not worry
-whether whether your arbitrary game corresponds to truth, tradition, or
-reality: it is still legitimate mathematics. Despite this wonderful Principle of
-Tolerance in mathematics, Carnap never ventured beyond the old
-ink-on-paper, axiomatic-deductive structures. I, however, have taken Carnap
-at his word. The result is my "post-formalist mathematics." I want to stress
-that my innovations have been legitimized in advance by one of the most
-reputable academic figures of the twentieth century.
-
-Early in 1961, I constructed some systems which went beyond
-formalist mathematics in two respects. 1. My sentential elements are
-physically different from the little ink-shapes on paper used in all formalist
-systems. My sentences are physically different from concatenations of
-ink-shapes. My transformation rules have nothing to do with operations on
-ink-shapes. 2. My systems do not necessarily follow the axiomatic-deductive,
-sentence-implication-axiom-proof-theorem structure. Both of these
-possibilities, by the way, are mentioned by Carnap in \papertitle{Languages as
-Calculi.} A "post-formalist system," then, is a formalist system which differs
-physically from an ink-on-paper system, or which lacks the
-axiomatic-deductive structure.
-
-As a basis for the analysis of post-formalist systems, a list of structural
-properties of formalist systems is desirable. Here is such a list. By
-"implication" I will mean simple, direct implication, unless I say otherwise.
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item A sentence can be repeated at will.
-
-\item The rule of implication refers to elements of sentences: sentences
-are structurally composite.
-
-\item A sentence can imply itself.
-
-\item The repeat of an implior can imply the repeat of an implicand: an
-implication can be repeated.
-
-\item Different impliors can imply different implicands.
-
-\item Given two or three sentences, it is possible to recognize
-mechanically whether one or two directly imply the third.
-
-\item No axiom is implied by other, different axioms.
-
-\item The definition of "proof" is the standard definition, in terms of
-implication, given early in this essay.
-
-\item Given the axioms and some other sentence, it is not possible to
-recognize mechanically whether the sentence is a theorem.
-Compound indirect implication is a puzzle.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-Now for the first post-formalist system.
-
-{ \centering \large "\textsc{Illusions}" \par}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-A "sentence" is the following page (with the figure on it) so long as the
-apparent, perceived ratio of the length of the vertical line to that
-of the horizontal line (the statement's "associated ratio") does not
-change. (Two sentences are the "same" if end only if their
-associated ratios are the same.)
-
-A sentence Y is "implied by" a sentence X if and only if Y is the same as X,
-or else Y is, of all the sentences one ever sees, the sentence having
-the associated ratio next smaller than that of X.
-
-Take as the axiom the first sentence one sees.
-
-Explanation: The figure is an optical illusion such that the vertical line
-normally appears longer than the horizontal line, even though their
-lengths are equal. One can correct one's perception, come to see
-the vertical line as shorter relative to the horizontal line, decrease
-the associated ratio, by measuring the lines with a ruler to convince
-oneself that the vertical line is not longer than the other, and then
-trying to see the lines as equal in length; constructing similar
-figures with a variety of real (measured) ratios and practicing
-judging these ratios; and so forth.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-\img{illusions}
-
-"IIlusions" has Properties 1, 3--5, and 7--8. Purely to clarify this fact, the
-following sequence of integers is presented as a model of the order in which
-associated ratios might appear in reality. (The sequence is otherwise totally
-inadequate as a model of "Illusions.") 4 2 1; 4 2; 5 4 2 1; 4 3 1. The
-implication structure would then be
-
-\img{illusionstructure}
-
-The axiom would be 4, and 5 could not appear in a proof. "IIlusions" has
-Property 1 on the basis that one can contro! the associated ratio. Turning to
-Property 4, it is normally the case that when an implication is repeated, a
-given occurrence of one of the sentences involved is unique to a specific
-occurrence of the implication. In "Illusions," however, if two equal
-sentences are next smaller than X, the occurrence of X does not uniquely
- belong to either of the two occurrences of the implication. Compare '\begin{tabular}{c c c} t & h & e \\ h & & \\ e & & \end{tabular}',
-where the occurrence of 't' is not unique to either occurrence of 'the'.
-Subject to this explanation, "Illusions" has Property 4. "Illusions" has
-Property 8, but it goes without saying that the type of implication is not
-modus ponens. Properties 3, 5, and 7 need no comment. As for Property 2,
-the rule of implication refers to a property of sentences, rather than to
-elements of sentences. The interesting feature of "IIlusions" is that it
-reverses the situation defined by Properties 6 and 9. Compound indirect
-implication is about the same as simple implication. The only difference is
-the difference between being smaller and being next smaller. And there is
-only one axiom (per person).
-
-Simple direct implication, however, is subjective and illusive. It
-essentially involves changing one's perceptions of an illusion. The change of
-associated ratios is subjective, elusive, and certainly not numerically
-measurable. Then, the order in which one sees sentences won't always be
-their order in the implications and proofs. And even though one is exposed
-to all the sentences, one may have difficulty distinguishing and remembering
-them in consciousness. If I see the normal illusion, then manage to get
-myself to see the lines as being of equal length, I know I have seen a
-theorem. What is difficult is grasping the steps in between, the simple direct
-implications. If the brain contains a permanent impression of every sensation
-it has received, then the implications objectively exist; but they may not be
-thinkable without neurological techniques for getting at the impressions. In
-any case, "proof" is well-defined in some sense---but proofs may not be
-thinkable. "Illusions" is, after all, not so much shakier in this respect than
-even simple arithmetic, which contains undecidable sentences and
-indefinable terms.
-
-In \booktitle{The Logical Syntax of Language}, Carnap distinguishes pure syntax
-and descriptive syntax; and says that pure syntax should be independent of
-notation, and that every system should be isomorphic to some ink-on-paper
-system. In so doing, Carnap violates his ov'n Principle of Tolerance. Consider
-the following trivial formalist system.
-
-{ \centering \large "\textsc{Order}" \par}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-A "sentence" is a member of a finite set of integers.
-
-Sentence Y is "implied by" sentence X if and only if Y=X, or else of all the
-sentences, Y is the one next smaller than X.
-
-Take as the axiom the largest sentence.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-
-Is the pure syntax of "\textsc{Illusions}" insomorphic to "\textsc{Order}"? The preceding
-paragraph proved that it is not. The implication structure of "Order" is
-mechanical to the point of idiocy, while the implication structure of
-"Illusions" is, as I pointed out, elusive. The figure
-
-
-\img{orderstructure}
-
-
-where loops indicate multiple occurances of the same sentence, could
-adequately represent a proof in "Order," but could not remotely represent
-one in "Illusions." The essence of "Illusions" is that it is coupled to the
-reader's subjectivity. For an ink-on-paper system even to be comparable to
-"IIlusions," the subjectivity would have to be moved out of the reader and
-onto the paper. This is utterly impossible.
-
-Here is the next system.
-
-{ \centering \large "\textsc{Innperseqs}" \par}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-Explanation: Consider the rainbow halo which appears to surround a small
-bright light when one looks at it through fogged glass (such as
-eyeglasses which have been breathed on). The halo consists of
-concentric circular bands of color. As the fog evaporates, the halo
-uniformly contracts toward the light. The halo has a vague outer
-ring, which contracts as the halo does. Of concern here is what
-happens on one contracting radius of the halo, and specifically
-what happens on the segment of that radius lying in the vague
-outer ring: the outer segment.
-
-A "sentence" (or halopoint) is the changing halo color at a fixed point, in
-space, in the halo; until the halo contracts past the point.
-
-Several sentences "imply" another sentence if and only if, at some instant,
-the several sentences are on an outer segment, and the other
-sentence is the inner endpoint of that outer segment.
-
-An "axiom" is a sentence which is in the initial vague outer ring (before it
-contracts), and which is not an inner endpoint.
-
-An "innperseq" is a sequence of sequences of sentences on one radius
-satisfying the following conditions. 1. The members of the first
-sequence are axioms, 2. For each of the other sequences, the first
-member is implied by the non-first members of the preceding
-sequence; and the remaining inembers (if any) are axioms or first
-members of preceding sequences. 3. All first members, of
-sequences other than the last two, appear as non-first members. 4.
-No sentence appears as a non-first member more than once. 5. The
-last sequence has one member.
-
-In the diagram on the following page, different positions of the vague outer
-ring at different times are suggested by different shadings. The
-outer segment moves "down the page." The figure is by no means
-an innperseq, but is supposed to help explain the definition.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-Successive bands represent the vague outer ring at successive times as it fades in
-toward the small bright light.
-
-Innperseqs Diagram
-
-\img{innperseqs}
-
-"Sentences" at
-
- \begin{tabular}{ c r l }
- \bimg{time1} & $time_1$: & $a_1 a_2 a_3 a_4 a_5 a_6 a_7 b$ \\
- & & $a_1,a_2 \rightarrow\ b$ \\
- \end{tabular}
-
- \begin{tabular}{c r l}
- \bimg{time2} & $time_2$: & $a_2 a_3 a_4 a_5 a_6 a_7 b c$ \\
- & & $a_3 \rightarrow\ c$ \\
- \end{tabular}
-
- \begin{tabular}{c r l}
- \bimg{time3} & $time_3$: & $a_4 a_5 a_6 a_7 b c d$ \\
- & & $a_4,a_5 \rightarrow\ d$ \\
- \end{tabular}
-
- \begin{tabular}{c r l}
- \bimg{time4} & $time_4$: & $a_6 a_7 b c d e$ \\
- & & $a_6,b \rightarrow\ e$ \\
- \end{tabular}
-
- \begin{tabular}{c r l}
- \bimg{time5} & $time_5$: & $a_7 b c d e f$ \\
- & & $a_7,c \rightarrow\ f$ \\
- \end{tabular}
-
- \begin{tabular}{c r l}
- \bimg{time6} & $time_6$: & $c d e f g$ \\
- & & $d,e \rightarrow\ g$ \\
- \end{tabular}
-
-"Axioms" $a_1 a_2 a_3 a_4 a_5 a_6 a_7$
-
-
-Innperseq \\
-$(a_3,a_2,a_1)$
-$(b,a_3)$
-$(c,a_5,a_4)$
-$(d,b,a_6)$
-$(e,c,a_7)$
-$(f,e,d)$
-$(g)$
-
-
-In "Innperseqs," a conventional proof would be redundant unless al!
-the statements were on the same radius. And even if the weakest axiom were
-chosen (the initial outer endpoint), this axiom would imply the initial inner
-endpoint, and from there the theorem could be reached immediately. In
-other words, to use the standard definition of "proof" in "Innperseqs"
-would result in an uninteresting derivation structure. Thus, a more
-interesting derivation structure is defined, the "innperseq." The interest of
-an "innperseq" is to be as elaborate as the many restrictions in its definition
-will allow. Proofs are either disregarded in "Innperseqs"; or else they are
-identified with innpersegs, and lack Property 8. "Innperseqs" makes the
-break with the proof-theorem structure of formalist mathematics.
-
-Turning to simple implication, an implicand can have many impliors;
-and there is an infinity of axioms, specified by a general condition. The
-system has Property 1 in the sense that a sentence can exist at different
-times and be a member of different implications. It has Property 4 in the
-sense that the sentences in a specific implication can exist at different times,
-and the implication holds as long as the sentences exist. It has Property 3 in
-that an inner endpoint implies itself. The system also has Properties 5 and 7;
-and lacks Property 2. But, as before, Properties 6 and 9 are another matter.
-Given several sentences, it is certainly possible to tell mechanically whether
-one is implied by the others. But when are you given sentences? If one can
-think the sentences, then relating them is easy---but it is difficult to think the
-sentences in the first place, even though they objectively exist. The diagram
-suggests what to look for, but the actual thinking, the actual sentences are
-another matter. As for Property 9, when "theorems" are identified with last
-members of innperseqs, I hesitate to say whether a derivation of a given
-sentence can be constructed mechanically. If a sentence is nearer the center
-than the axioms are, an innperseq can be constructed for it. Or can it? The
-answer is contingent. "Innperseqs" is indeterminate because of the difficulty
-of thinking the sentences, a difficulty which is defined into the system. It is
-the mathematician's capabilities at a particular instant which delimit the
-indeterminacies. Precisely because of the difficulty of thinking sentences, I
-will give several subvariants of the system.
-
-
-{ \centering \large \textsc{Indeterminacy} \par}
-\begin{sysrules}
-A "totally determinate innperseq" is an innperseq in which one thinks all the
-sentences.
-
-An "implior-indeterminate innperseq" is an innperseq in which one thinks
-only each implicand and the outer segment it terminates.
-
-A "sententially indeterminate innperseq" is an innperseq in which one thinks
-only the outer segment, and its inner endpoint, as it progresses
-inward.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-
-Let us return to the matter of pure and descriptive syntax. The interest
-of "Illusions" and "Innperseqs" is precisely that their abstract structure
-cannot be separated from their physical and psychological character, and
-thus that they are not isomorphic to any conventional ink-on-paper system. I
-am trying to break through to unheard of, and hopefully significant, modes
-of implication; to define implication structures (and derivation structures)
-beyond the reach of past mathematics.
-
-\subsection{Constructed Memory Systems}
-
-In order to understand this section, it is necessary to be thoroughly
-familiar with \essaytitle{Studies in Constructed Memories,} the essay following this
-one. (I have not combined the two essays because their approaches are too
-different.) I will define post-formalist systems in constructed memories,
-beginning with a system in an M*-Memory.
-
-{ \centering \large "\textsc{Dream Amalgams}" \par}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-A "sentence" is a possible method, an $A_{a_i}$. with respect to an M*-Memory.
-The sentence $A_{a_p}$ "implies" the sentence $A_{a_q}$ if and only if the $a_q$th
-M*-assertion is actually thought; and either $A_{a_q} = A_{a_p}$, or else there is
-cross-method contact of a mental state in $A_{a_q}$ with a state in $A_{q_p}$\footnote{sic?}
-
-The axioms must be chosen from sentences which satisfy two conditions.
-The mental states in the sentences must have cross-method contact
-with mental states in other sentences. And the M*-assertions
-corresponding to the sentences must not be thought.
-
-Explanation: As \essaytitle{Studies in Constructed Memories} says, there can be
-cross-method contact of states, because a normal dream can
-combine totally different episodes in the dreamer's life into an
-amalgam.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-"\textsc{Dream Amalgams}" has Properties 1-5. For the first time, sentences are
-structurally composite, with mental states being the relevant sentential
-elements. Implication has an unusual character. The traditional type of
-implication, modus ponens, is "directed," because the conditional is
-directed. Even if $\ulcorner\varphi\supset\phi\urcorner$ is true
-$\ulcorner\varphi\supset\phi\urcorner$ may not be. Now implication is also
-directed in "\textsc{Dream Amalgams,}" but for a very different reason.
-Cross-method contact, unlike the conditional, has a symmetric character.
-What prevents implication from being necessarily symmetrical is that the
-implicand's M*-assertion actually has to be thought, while the implior's
-M*-assertion does not. Thus, implication is both subjective and mechanical,
-it is subjective, in that it is a matter of volition which method is remembered
-to have actually: been used. It is mechanical, in that when one is
-remembering, one is automatically aware of the cross-method contacts of
-states in $A_{a_q}$. The conditions on the axioms ensure that they will have
-implications without losing Property 7.
-
-As for compound implication in "\textsc{Dream Amalgams,}" the organism
-with the M*-Memory can't be aware of it at all; because it can't be aware
-that at different times it remembered different methods to be the one
-actually used. (In fact, the organism cannot be aware that the system has
-Property 5, for the same reason.) On the other hand, to an outside observer
-of the M*-Memory, indirect implication is not only thinkable but
-mechanical. It is not superfluous because cross-method contact of mental
-states is not necessarily transitive. The outside observer can decide whether a
-sentence is a theorem by the following mechanical procedure. Check
-whether the sentence's M*-assertion has acually been thought; if so, check all
-sentences which imply it to see if any are axioms; if not, check all the
-sentences which imply the sentences which imply it to see if any are axioms;
-etc. The number of possible methods is given as finite, so the procedure is
-certain to terminate. Again, an unprecedented mode of implication has been
-defined.
-
-When a post-formalist system is defined in a constructed memory, the
-discussion and analysis of the system become a consequence of constructed
-memory theory and an extension of it. Constructed memory theory, which
-is quite unusual but still more or less employs deductive inference, is used to
-study post-formalist modes of inference which are anything but deductive.
-
-To aid in understanding the next system, which involves infalls in a
-D-Memory, here is an
-
-{ \centering \large \framebox[1.1\width]{"Exercise to be Read Aloud"} \par}
-
-(Read according to a timer, reading the first word at O' O", and prolonging
-and spacing words so that each sentence ends at the time in parentheses after
-it. Do not pause netween sentences.)
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r l }
- ($event_1$) & All men are mortal. (17") \\
-
- ($Sentence_1=event_2s$) & The first utterance lasted 17" and ended at 17"; and lasted 15" and ended 1" ago. (59") \\
-
- ($S_2=event_3$) & The second utterance lasted 42" and ended at 59": and lasted 50" and ended 2" ago. (1' 31") \\
-
- ($S_3=event_4$) & The third utterance lasted 32" and ended at 1' 31"; and lasted 40" and ended 1" ago. (2' 16") \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-Since '32' in $S_3$ is greater than '2' in $S_2$, $S_2$ must say that $S_1$ ($=event_2$)
-ended 30" after $S_2$ began, or something equally unclear. The duration of $S_2$
-is greater than the distance into the past to which it refers. This situation is
-not a real infall, but it should give the reader some intuitive notion of an
-infall.
-
-
-\newcommand{\midheading}[1]{
- { \centering \large \textsc{#1} \par}}
-
-\midheading{"Infalls"}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
- A "sentence" is a D-sentence, in a D-Memory such that $event_{j+1}$ is the first
-thinking of the jth D-sentence, for all j.
-
-Two sentences "imply" another if and only if all three are the same; or else
-the three are adjacent (and can be written $S_{j+1},S_j,S_{j-1}$), and are such
-that $\delta_j=x_{j+1}-x_j> z_j,$ $S^D_{j-1}$ is the implicand. (The function of $S_{j+1}$ is to
-give the duration $\delta_j=x_{j+1}-x_j$ of $S_j$. $S_j$ states that $event_j$, the first
-thinking of $S^{D}_{j-1}$, ended at a distance $z_j$ into the past, where $z_j$ is smaller
-than $S^D_j$'s own duration. The diagram indicates the relations.)
-\end{sysrules}
-
-\img{infallsdiag}
-
-In this variety of D-Memory, the organism continuously thinks successive
-D-sentences, which are all different, just as the reader of the above exercise
-continuously reads successive and different sentences. Thus, the possibility
-of repeating a sentence depends on the possibility of thinking it while one is
-thinking another sentence---a possibility which may be far-fetched, but which
-is not explicitly excluded by the definition of a "D-Memory." If the
-possibility is granted, then "\textsc{Infalls}" has Properties 1--5. Direct implication is
-completely mechanical; it is subjective only in that the involuntary
-determination of the $z_j$ and other aspects of the memory is a 'subjective'
-process of the organism. Compound implication is also mechanical to an
-outside observer of the memory, but if the organism itself is to be aware of
-it, it has to perform fantastic feats of multiple thinking.
-
-"\textsc{Dream Amalgams}" and "\textsc{Infalls}" are systems constructed with
-imaginary elements, systems whose "notation" is drawn from an imaginary
-object or system. Such systems have no descriptive syntax. Imaginary objects
-were introduced into mathematics, or at least into geometry, by Nicholas
-Lobachevski, and now I am using them as a notation. For these systems to
-be nonisomorphic to any ink-on-paper systems, the mathematician must be
-the organism with the M*-Memory or the D*-Memory. But this means that
-in this case, the mathematics which is nonisomorphic to any ink-on-paper
-system can be performed only in an imaginary mind.
-
-Now for a different approach. Carnap said that we are free to choose
-the rules of a system arbitrarily. Let us take Carnap literally. I want to
-construct more systems in constructed memories---so why not construct the
-system by a procedure which ensures that constructed memories are
-involved, but which is otherwise arbitrary? Why not suspend the striving
-after "interesting" systems, that last vestige of the striving after
-"correctness," and see what happens? Why not construct the rules of a
-system by a chance procedure?
-
-To construct a system, we have to fill in the blanks in the following rule
-schema in such a way that grammatically correct sentences result.
-
-\newcommand{\blankspace}{\_\_\_\_\_\_\_\_\_\_}
-
-\midheading{Rule Schema}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-A "sentence" is a(n) \blankspace.
-
-Two sentences "imply" a third if and only if the two sentences \blankspace\ the third.
-
-An "axiom" is a sentence that \blankspace.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-
-I now spread the pages of \essaytitle{Studies in Constructed Memories} on the floor.
-With eyes closed, I hold a penny over them and drop it. I open my eyes and
-copy down the expressions the penny covers. By repeating this routine, I
-obtain a haphazard series of expressions concerning constructed memories. It
-is with this series that I will fill in the blanks in the rule schema. In the next
-stage, I fill the first (second, third) blank with the ceries of expressions
-preceding the-first (second, third) period in the entire series.
-
-\midheading{"Haphazard System"}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-A "sentence" is a the duration D-sentences $\triangle\ (\mathparagraph^m)$ conclude these
-"$\Phi*$-Reflection," or the future Assumption voluntarily force of
-conviction for conclusion the Situation or by ongoing that this
-system? be given telling between the Situation 1.
-
-Two sentences "imply" a third if and only if the two sentences is\slash was
-contained not have to the acceptance that a certain and malleable
-study what an event involves material specifically mathematics:
-construct accompanies the rest, extra-linguistically image organism
-can fantasy not remembering $\Phi*$-Memory, the future interval defined
-in dream the third.
-
-An "axiom" is a sentence that internally D-sentences, just as the
-"$\Phi*$-Memory" sentences $A_{a_1}$ is $A_{a_2}$.
-
-In the final stage, I cancel the smallest number of words I have to in
-order to make the rules grammatical.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-\midheading{"Fantasied Amnesia"}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-A "sentence" is a duration or the future force of conviction for the Situation
-or this system given Situation 1.
-
-Two sentences "imply" a third if and only if the two sentences have the
-acceptance that a certain and malleable study extra-linguistically can
-fantasy not remembering the future interval defined in the third.
-
-An "axiom" is a sentence that internally just sentences $A_{a_2}$.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-It becomes clear in thinking about "Fantasied Amnesia" that its
-metametamathematics is dual. Describing the construction of the rules, the
-metamathematics, by a systematic performance, is one thing. Taking the
-finished metamathematics at face value, independently of its origin, and
-studying it in the usual manner, is another. Let us take "Fantasied Amnesia"
-at face value. As one becomes used to its rules, they become somewhat more
-meaningful. I will say that an "interpretation" of a haphazard system is an
-explanation of its rules that makes some sense out of what may seem
-senseless. "Interpreting" is somewhat like finding the conditions for the
-existence of a constructed memory which seemingly cannot exist. The first
-rule of "Fantasied Amnesia" is a disjunction of three substantives. The
-"Situation" referred to in the second substantive expression is either
-Situation 1 or else an unspecified situation. The third substantive expression
-apparently means "this system, assuming Situation 1," and refers to
-"Fantasied Amnesia" itself. The definition of "sentence" is thus meaningful,
-but very bizarre. The second rule speaks of "the acceptance" as if it were a
-written assent. The rule then speaks of a "malleable study" as "fantasying"
-something. This construction is quite weird, but let us try to accept it. The
-third rule speaks of a sentence that "sentences" (in the legal sense) a possible
-method. So much for the meaning of the rules.
-
-Turning to the nine properties of formalist systems, the reference to
-"the future interval" in the implication rule of "Fantasied Amnesia"
-indicates that the system has Property 2; and the system can perfectly well
-have Property 8. It does not have Property 6 in any known sense. Certainly
-it does have Property 9. it just might have Property. 1. But as for the other
-four properties, it seems out of the question to decide whether "Fantasied
-Amnesia" has them. For whatever it is worth, "Fantasied Amnesia" is on
-balance incomparable to formalist systems.
-
-My transformation rule schema has the form of a biconditional, in
-which the right clause is the operative one. If a transformation rule were to
-vary, in such a way that it could be replaced by a constant rule whose right
-clause was the disjunction of the various right clauses for the variable rule,
-then the latter would vary "trivially." 1 will say that a system whose
-transformation rule can vary non-trivially is a "heterodeterminate" system.
-Since 1 have constructed a haphazard metamathematics, why not a
-heterodeterminate metamathematics? Consider a mathematician with an
-M-Memory, such that each $A_{a_i}$. is the consistent use of a different
-transformation rule, a different definition of "imply," for the mathematics
-in which the mathematician is discovering theorems. The consistent use of a
-transformation rule is after all a method---a method for finding the
-commitments premisses make, and for basing conclusions in premisses. When
-the mathematician goes to remember which rule of inference he has actually
-been using, he "chooses" which of the possible methods is remembered to
-have actually been used. This situation amounts to a heterodeterminate
-system. tn fact, the metamathematics cannot even be written out this time; I
-can only describe it metametamathematically in terms of an imaginary
-memory.
-
-We are now in the realm of mathematical systems which cannot be
-written out, but can only be described metametamathematically. I will
-present a final system of this sort. It is entitled \textsc{"System Such That No One
-Knows What's Going On."} One just has to guess whether this system exists,
-and if it does what it is like. The preceding remark is the
-metametamathematical description, or definition, of the system.
-
-\subsection{Epilogue}
-
-Ever since Carnap's Principle of Tolerance opened the floodgates to
-arbitrariness in mathematics, we have been faced with the prospect of a
-mathematics which is indistinguishable from art-for-art's-sake, or
-amusement-for-amusement's-sake. But there is one characteristic which saves
-mathematics from this fate. Mathematics originated by abstraction from
-primitive technology, and is indispensable to science and technology---in
-short, mathematics has scientific applications. The experience of group
-theory has proved, I hope once and for all, the bankruptcy of that narrow
-practicality which would limit mathematics to what can currently be applied
-in science. But now that mathematics is wide open, and anything goes, we
-should be aware more than ever that scientific applicability is the only
-objective value that mathematics has. I would not have set down constructed
-memory theory and the post-formalist systems if I did not believe that they
-could be applied. When and how they will be is another matter.
-
-And what about the "validity" of formalism? The rise of the formalist
-position is certainly understandable. The formalists had a commendable,
-rationalistic desire to eliminate the metaphysical! problems associated with
-mathematics. Moreover, formalism helped stimulate the development of the
-logic needed in computer technology (and also to stimulate this paper). In
-spite of the productiveness of the formalist position, however, it now seems
-beyond dispute that formalism has failed to achieve its original goals. (My
-pure philosophical writings are the last word on this issue.) Perhaps the main
-lesson to be learned from the history of formalism is that an idea does not
-have to be "true" to be productive.
-
-
-\section{Note}
-Early versions of \textsc{"Illusions"} and \textsc{"Innperseqs"} appeared in my essay
-"Concept Art," published in An Anthology, ed. La Monte Young, New
-York, 1963. An early, July 1961 version of \textsc{"System Such That No One
-Knows What's Going On"} appeared in dimension 14, Ann Arbor, 1963,
-published by the University of Michigan College of Architecture and Design.
-
-\section{Studies in Constructed Memories}
-
-\subsection{Introduction}
-
-The memory of a conscious organism is a phenomenon in which
-interrelations of mind, language, and the rest of reality are especially evident.
-In these studies, I will define some conscious memory-systems, and
-investigate them. The investigation will be mathematical. In fact, the nearest
-precedent for it is perhaps the geometry of Nicholas Lobachevski.
-Non-Euclidian geometry had many founders, but Lobachevski in particular
-spoke of his system as an "imaginary geometry." Lobachevski's system was,
-so to speak, the physical geometry of an "imaginary," or constructed, space.
-By analogy, my investigation could be called a psychological algebra of
-constructed minds. It is too early to characterize the investigation more
-exactly. Let us just remember Rudoiph Carnap's Principle of Tolerance in
-mathematics: the mathematician is free to construct his system in any way
-he chooses.
-
-I will begin by introducing a repertory of concepts informally,
-becoming more formal as I go along. Consider ongoing actions, which by
-definition extend through past, present, and future. For example, "I am
-making the trip from New York to Chicago." Consider also past actions
-which have probable consequences in the present. "I have been heating this
-water" (entailing that it isn't frozen now). I will be concerned with such
-actions as these.
-
-Our language provides for the following assertion: "I am off to the
-country today; I could have been off to the beach; I could not possibly have
-been going to the center of the sun". We distinguish an actual action from a
-possible action; and distinguish both from an action which is materially
-impossible. People insist that there are things they could do, even though
-they don't choose to do them (as opposed to things they couldn't do). What
-distinguishes these possible actions from impossible ones? Rather than
-trying to analyze such everyday notions in terms of the logic of
-counterfactual conditionals, or of modalities, or of probability, I choose to
-take the notions at their face value. My concern is not to philosophize, but
-to assemble concepts with which to define an interesting memory system.
-
-What is the introspective psychological difference between a thought
-that has the force of a memory, and a thought that has the force of a
-fantasied past, a merely possible past? I am not asking how I know that a
-verbalized memory is true; I am asking what quality a naive thought has that
-marks it as a memory. Let Alternative E be that I went to an East Side
-restaurant yesterday, and Alternative W be that I went to a West Side one.
-By the "thought of E" I mean mainly the visualization of going into the East
-Side restaurant. My thought of E has the force of memory. It actually
-happened. W is something I could have done. I can imagine I did do W. There
-is nothing present which indicates whether I did E or W. Yet W merely has
-the force of possibility, of fantasy. How do the two thoughts differ? Is the
-thought of E involuntarily more vivid? Is there perhaps an "attitude of
-assertion" involuntarily present in the thought of E?
-
-Consider the memory that I was almost run down by a truck yesterday:
-I could have been run down, but wasn't. In such a case, the possibility that I
-could have been run down would be more vivid than the actuality that I
-wasn't. (Is it not insanity, when a person is overwhelmed by the fear of a
-merely possible past event? ) My hold on sanity here would be the awareness
-that I am alive and well today.
-
-In dreams, do we not wholeheartedly "remember" that a misfortune
-has befallen us, and begin to adjust emotionally to it? Then we awake, and
-wholeheartedly remember that the misfortune has not befallen us. The
-thought that had the force of memory in the dream ceases to have that force
-as we awake. We remember the dream, and conclude that it was a fantasy.
-Even more characteristic of dreams, do I not to al! intents and purposes go
-to far places and carry out all sorts of actions in a dream, only to awaken in
-bed? We say that the dream falsifies my present environment, my
-sensations, my actions, memories, the past, my whole world, in a totally
-convincing way. Can a hypnotist produce artificial dreams, that is, can he
-control their content? Can the hypnotist give his subject one false memory
-one moment, and replace it with a contradictory memory the next
-moment?
-
-I will now specify a situation involving possible actions and
-remembering.
-
-Situation 1. "I could have been accomplishing G by doing $A_{a_1}$, or by
-doing $A_{a_2}$, \ldots, or by doing $A_{a_n}$; but I have actually been accomplishing G by
-doing $A_{a_1}$." Here the ongoing actions $A_{a_i}$, $i=1,...,n$,$a_i\neq a_h if i\neq h$, are
-the possible methods of accomplishing G. (The subscripts are supposed to
-indicate that the methods are distinct and countable, but not ordered.) The
-possible methods cannot be combined, let us assume.
-
-In such a situation, perhaps the thought that I have been doing $A_{a_1}$
-would be distinguished from similar thoughts about $A_{a_2}, ..., A_{a_n}$ by the
-presence of the "attitude of assertion". Since the possible methods are
-ongoing actions, the thought that I have been doing $A_{a_i}$ has logical or
-probabie consequences I can check against the present.
-
-Now $A_{a_1}$, is actual and $A_{a_2}$ is not, so that $A_{a_1}$, simply cannot have
-possible jar in $A_{a_3}$ to contain it. The only "connection" $A_{a_1}$ could have
-material contact with $A_{a_2}$. An actual liquid in $A_{a_1}$ could not require a
-with $A_{a_2}$, would be verbal and gratuitous. Therefore, in order to be possible
-methods, $A_{a_2}$, ..., $A_{a_n}$ must be materially separable. A liquid in $A_{a_2}$ must
-not require a jar in $A_{a_3}$ to contain it. If it did, $A_{a_2}$ couldn't be actualized
-while $A_{a_3}$, remained only a possibility.
-
-Enough concepts are now at hand for the studies to begin in earnest.
-
-\subsection{M-Memories}
-
-\newcommand{\definition}{\textbf{Definition.}}
-\newcommand{\assumption}[1]{\textit{Assumption #1.}}
-\newcommand{\conclusion}[1]{\textbf{Conclusion #1.}}
-
-\definition Given the sentences "I have actually been doing $A_{a_i}$", where
-the $A_{a_i}$ are non-combinable possible methods as in Situation 1, an
-"M-Memory" is a memory of a conscious organism such that the organism
-can think precisely one of the sentences at a time, and any of the sentences
-has the force of memory.
-
-This definition refers to language, mind, and the rest of reality in their
-interrelations, but the crucial reference is to a property of certain sentences.
-I have chosen this formulation precisely because of what I want to
-investigate. I want to find the minimal, elegant, extra-linguistic conditions,
-whatever they may be, for the existence of an M-Memory (which is defined
-by a linguistic property). I can say at once that the conditions must enable
-the organism to think the sentences at will, and they must provide that the
-memory is consistent with the organism's present awareness.
-
-\definition The "P-Memory" of a conscious organism is its conscious
-memory of what it did and what happened to it, the past events of its life. I
-want to distinguish here the "personal" memory from the preconscious.
-
-\definition An "L-Memory" is a linguistic P-Memory having no
-extra-linguistic component. Of course, the linguistic component has
-extra-linguistic mental associations which give it "meaning"--otherwise the
-memory wouldn't be conscious. But these associations lack the force of a
-mental reliving of the past independent of language. An L-Memory amounts
-to extra-linguistic amnesia.
-
-\assumption{1.1} With respect to normal human memory, when I forget
-whether I did x, I can't voluntarily give either the thought that I did x, or
-the thought that I didn't do x, the force of memory. I know that I either did
-or didn't do x, but I can create no conviction for either alternative. (An
-introspective observation.)
-
-\conclusion{1.2} An L-Memory is not sufficient for an M-Memory, even
-in the trivial case that the $A_{a_i}$ are beyond perception (as internal bodily
-processes are). True, there would be no present perceptions to check the
-sentences "I have actually been doing $A_{a_i}$" against. True, the L-Memory
-precludes any extra-linguistic memory-"feelings" which would conflict with
-the sentences. But the L-Memory is otherwise normal. And \textit{Assumption 1.1}
-indicates that normally, either precisely one of a number of mutually
-exclusive possibilities has the force of memory; or else the organism can give
-none of them the force of memory.
-
-\assumption{1.3} I cannot, from within a natural dream, choose to swith
-to another dream. {An introspective observation. A "natural" dream is a
-dream involuntarily produced internally during sleep.)
-
-\conclusion{1.4} An M-Memory could not be produced by natural
-dreaming. It is true that in one dream one sentence could have the force of
-memory, and in another dream a different sentence could. But an M-Memory
-is such that the organism can choose one sentence-memory one moment and
-another the next. See Assumption 1.3.
-
-\assumption{1.5} Returning to the example of the restaurants, I find
-that months after the event, my thought of E no longer has the force of
-memory. All I remember now is that I used to remember that I did E. I
-remember that I did E indirectly, by remembering that I remembered that !
-did E. (My memory that I did E is becoming an L-Memory.) The assumption
-is that a memory of one's remembering can indicate, if not imply, that the
-event originally remembered occurred.
-
-\conclusion{1.6} The following are adequate conditions for the existence
-of an M-Memory.
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item The sentences are the organism's only memory of which
-method he has been using.
-
-\item When the organism thinks "I have actually been doing $A_{a_i}$".
-then (he artificially dreams that) he has been doing $A_{a_i}$ --- and is
-now doing it.
-
-\item When the dream ends, he does not remember that he
-remembered that "he has been doing $A_{a_i}$," That is, he does not remember
-the dream; and he does not remember that he thought the sentence. These
-conditions would permit the existence of an M-Memory or else a memory
-indistinguishable to all intents and purposes from an M-Memory.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-What I have in mind in \conclusion{1.6} is dreams which are produced
-artificially but otherwise have all the remarkable qualities of natural dreams.
-There would have to be a state of affairs such that the sentence would
-instantly start the dream going.
-
-So much for the conditions for the existence of an M-Memory.
-Consider now what it is like as a mental experience to have an M-Memory.
-What present or ongoing awareness accompanies an M-Memory?
-\conclusion{1.6.2} already told what the remembering is like. For the rest, I will
-informally sketch some conclusions. The organism can extra-linguistically
-image the $A_{a_i}$. The organism can think "I could have been doing $A_{a_i}$." When
-not remembering, the organism doesn't have to do any $A_{a_i}$, or he can do any
-one of them. The organism must not do anything which would liquidate a
-possble method, render the action no longer possible for him.
-
-\assumption{2.1} A normal dream can combine two totally different
-past episodes in my life into a fused episode, or amalgam; so that I "relive" it
-without doubts as.a single episode, and yet remain vaguely aware that
-different episodes are present in it. Dreams have the capacity not only to
-falsify my world, but to make the impossible believable. (An introspective
-observation.)
-
-\conclusion{2.2} The conditions for the existence of an M-Memory
-further permit material contact between the possible methods, the very
-contact which is out of the question in a normal Situation 1. The dream is so
-flexible that the organism can dream that an (actual) liquid is\slash was contained
-by a jar in a possible method. See \assumption{2.1} Thus, the $A_{a_i}$ do not have
-to be separable to be possible methods.
-
-I will now introduce further concepts pertaining to the mind.
-
-\definition\ A "mental state" is a mental "stage" or "space" or "mood"
-in which visualizing, remembering, and all imaging can be carried on.
-
-Some human mental states are stupor, general anxiety, empathy with
-another person, dizziness, general euphoria, clearheadedness (the normal
-state in which work is performed), and dreaming. In all but the last state,
-some simple visualization routine could be carried out voluntarily. Even ina
-dream, I can have visualizations, although here I can't have them at will. The
-states are not defined by the imaging or activities carried on while in them,
-but are "spaces" in which such imaging or activities are carried on.
-
-By definition.
-
-\conclusion{3.2} An M-Memory has to occur within the time which the
-possible methods require, the time required to accomplich G. By definition.
-
-\definition An "M*-Memory" is an M-Memory satisfying these
-conditions.
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item $A_{a_i}$, for the entire time it requires, involves the voluntary
-assuming of mental states. $i=1,...,n$.
-\item The material contact between the
-possible methods, the cross-method contact, is specifically some sort of
-contact between states.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-\conclusion{3.3} For an M*-Memory, to remember is to choose the
-mental state in which the remembering is required to occur (by the
-memory). After all, for any M-Memory, to remember is to choose all the
-$A_{a_i}$-required things you are doing while you remember.
-
-By now, the character of this investigation should be clearer. I seek to
-stretch our concepts, rather that to find the "true" ones. The investigation
-may appear similar to the old discipline of philosophical psychology, but its
-thrust is rather toward the modern axiomatic systems. The reasoning is
-loose, but not arbitrary. And the investigation will become increasingly
-mathematical.
-
-
-\subsection{D-Memories}
-
-\definition\ A "D-Memory" is a memory such that measured past time
-appears in it only in the following sentences: "$Event_j$ occurred in the interval
-% TODO\<F11><F12> ? whats up with AF
-of time which is $x_j-x_{j-1}$ long and ended at $x_j$ AF, and is Yj long and ended $z_j$
-\ ago," where $x_j$, $y_j$ and $z_j$ are positive numbers of time units (such as hours)
-and '$AF$' means "after a fixed beginning time." $x_O=O;$ $x_j> x_{j-1}$; and at any
-one fixed time, the intervals $|z_j, z_j+y_j|$ nowhere overlap. $y_j+z_j\leq x_j$ For an
-integer $m$, the $m$th sentence acquires the force of memory, is added to the
-memory, at the fixed time $x_m$. $j=1, ..., f(t)$, where the number of sentences
-$f(t)$ is written as a function of time $AF$. Then $f(t)=m$ when $x_m \leq t \less x_{m+1}$.
-The sentences have the force of memory involuntarily. The organism does
-not make them up at will.
-
-Let me explain what the D-Memory involves. $Event_j$ is assigned to an
-abnormal "interval," a dual interval defined in two unrelated ways. The
-intervals defined by the $y_j$ and $z_j$ are tied to the present instant rather than to
-a fixed time, and could be written $|N-z_j-y_j, N-z_j|$, where '$N$' means "the time
-of the present instant relative to the fixed beginning time."
-
-\newcommand{\proof}{\textit{Proof}}
-
-\conclusion{4} The intervals $|N-z_j-y_j, N-z_j|$ nowhere overlap.
-
-\proof: By definition, the intervals $|z_j, z_j+y_j|$ nowhere overlap. If $j\neq k$,
-$|z_j, z_j+y_j|\cap|z_k, z_k+y_k|=\emptyset$
-This fact implies that \eg $z_j\less z_j+y_j\less z_k\less z_k+y_k$.
-Then $N-z_k-y_k\less N-z_k\less N-z_j-y_j\less N-z_j$.
-Then $|N-z_k-y_k, N-z_k|\cap|N-z_j-y_j, N-z_j|=\emptyset$
-At any one time, the organism can think of all the sliding intervals, and they
-partly cover the time up to now without overlapping.
-
-Suppose you find the deck of n cards
-
-{ \centering
-\framebox[1.1\width]{
- \centering
- $event_j$ \linebreak
- $z_j$ ago}}
-
-
-($j=1,...,n$ and $z_j$ is a positive number of days), and you have no
-information to date them other than what they themselves say. If you
-believe the cards, your mental experience will be a little like having a
-D-Memory. Then, the definition does not require that $y_j=x_j-x_{j-1}$. Again, it is
-not that two concepts of "length" are involved, but that the "interval" is
-abnormal. Of course this is all inconsistent, but I want to study the
-conditions under which a mind will accept inconsistency.
-
-\assumption{5.1} With respect to normal human memory, it is possible
-to forget what day it is, even though one remembers a past date. (An
-empirical observation.)
-
-\assumption{5.2} This assumption is based on the fact that the sign
-'CLOSED FOR VACATION. BACK IN TWO WEEKS' was in the window of
-a nearby store for at least a month this summer; and the fact that a
-filmmaker wrote in a newspaper, "When an actor asks me when the film will
-be finished, I say 'In two months," and two months later I give the same
-answer, and I'm always right.' Even in normal circumstances, humans can
-maintain a dual and outright inconsistent awareness of measured time. [n
-general, inconsistency is a normal aspect of human thinking and even has
-practical value.
-
-Imagine a child who has been told to date events by saying, for
-example, x happened two days ago, and a day later saying again, x happened
-two days ago---and who has not been told that this is inconsistent. What
-conditions are required for the acceptance of this dating system? It is
-precisely because of Assumptions 5.1 and 5.2 that a certain answer cannot
-be given to this question. The human mind is so flexible and malleable that
-there is no telling how much inconsistency it can absorb. I can only study
-what flaws might lead the child to reject the system. The child might "feel"
-that an event recedes into the past, something the memory doesn't express.
-An event might be placed by the memory no later than another, and yet
-"feel" more recent than the other. I speculate that if anything will discredit
-the system, it will be its conflict with naive, "felt," extra-linguistic memory.
-
-\conclusion{5.3} The above dating system would be acceptable to an
-organism with an L-Memory.
-
-\conclusion{5.4} The existence of an L-Memory is an adequate condition
-for the existence of a D-Memory. With extra-linguistic amnesia, the
-structure of the language would be the structure of the past in any case. The
-past would have no form independent of language. Anyway, time is gone for
-good, leaving nothing that can be checked directly. Without an
-extra-linguistic memory to fall back on, and considering Assumptions 5.1
-and 5.2, the dual temporal memory shouldn't be too much to absorb.
-
-As I said, the real difficulty with this line of investigation is putting
-limits on anything so flexible as the mind's capacity to absorb inconsistency.
-
-Now the thinking of a sentence in a D-Memory itself takes time. Let
-$\delta(S^D_j)$ be the minimum number of time units it takes to think the jth
-D-sentence. This function, abbreviated '$\delta_j$', is the duration function of the
-D-sentences.
-
-\conclusion{6.1} If $\delta_j\greater z_j$, the memory of the interval defined by $y_j$ and
-$z_j$ places the end of the interval after the beginning of the memory of it, or
-does something else equally unclear. If $\delta_j\greater y_j+z_j$, the entire interval is placed
-after the beginning of the memory of it. When $\delta_j\greater z_j$, let us say that the end
-of the remembered interval falis within the interval for the memory of it, or
-that the situation is an "\textsc{infall}." (Compare \said{The light went out a half-second
-ago}.)
-
-\conclusion{6.2} If $\delta_j\greater x_{j+k}-x_j$, then $S^D_{j+k}$ is added to the preconscious
-before $S^D_j$ can be thought once. The earliest interval during which the jth
-sentence can be thought "passes over" the (j+k)th interval. Let us say that
-the situation is a "\textsc{passover}." (Something of the sort is true of humans,
-whose brains contain permanent impressions of far more sensations than can
-be thought, remembered in consciousness.)
-
-\conclusion{6.3} If there are passovers in a D-Memory, the organism
-cannot both think the sentences during the earliest intervals possible and be
-aware of the passovers.
-
-\proof: The only way the organism can be aware of $\delta(S_j)$
-is for $event_{j+h}$ (h a positive integer) to be the thinking of $S_j$.
-If the thinking of $S_j$ takes piace as the $(j+1)^{th}$ event, then the organism gets two
-values for $\delta(S_j)$, namely $x_{j+1}-x_j$ and $y_{j+1}$. Assume that only $x_{j+1}-x_j$
-is allowed as a measure of $\delta(S_j)$. Since $\delta(S_j)=x_{j+1}-x_j$, there is no passover. If
-the thinking of $S_j$ takes place as the $(j+2)^{th}$ event, then $x_{j+2}-x{j+1}=\delta(S_j)$
-could be greater than $x_{j+1}-x_j$. But since $S_j$ goes into the preconscious at $x_j$,
-$S_j$ is not actually thought in the earliest interval during which it could be
-thought. See the diagram.
-
-\img{dmemdiag}
-
-\conclusion{6.4} Let there be an \textsc{infall} in the case where $event_{j+1}$ is the
-thinking of $S_j$. $\delta(S_j)=x_{j+1}-x_j$ and $\delta(S_j)\greater z_j$. $S_{j+1}$ gives $\delta(S_j)$,
-so that the organism can be aware of it.
-It is greater than $z_j$. Thus, the organism can be
-aware of the \textsc{infall}. However, the \textsc{infall} will certainly be no more difficult to
-accept than the other features of the D-Memory. And the thinking of $S_j$ has
-to be one of the events for the organism to be aware of the infall.
-
-\subsection{$\Phi$-Memories}
-I will conclude these studies with two complex constructions.
-
-\definition A "$\Phi$-Memory" is a memory which includes an M*-Memory
-and a D-Memory, with the following conditions.
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item The goal G, for the M*-Memory, is to move from one point to another.
-
-\item For the D-Memory, "$event_j$" becomes a numerical term, the decrease in the organism's distance
-from the destination point during the temporal interval. \said{A 3-inch move
-toward the destination} is the sort of thing that "$event_j$' here refers to.
-
-\item The number of $A_{a_i}$ equals the number of D-sentences factorial. The number
-of D-sentences, of course, increases.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-Consider the consecutive thinking of each D-sentence precisely once, in
-minimum time, while the number of sentences remains constant. Such a
-"D-paragraph" is a permutation of the D-sentences. Let $\mathparagraph^m$ be a
-D-paragraph when the number of sentences equals the integer m. There are
-$m!$ $\mathparagraph^m$s. When $f(t)=m=3$, one of the six $\mathparagraph^3$s is $S^D_3 S^D_1 S^D_2$,
-thought in
-minimum time. Assume that the duration $\triangle$ of a D-paragraph depends only
-on the number of D-sentences and the $\delta_j$. We can write
-
-$$ \triangle(\mathparagraph^m)=\sum_{j=1}^{m} \delta_j $$
-
-The permutations of the D-sentences, as well as the D-paragraphs, can be
-indexed with the $a_i$, just as the possible methods are.
-
-Definition. A "$\Phi*$-Memory" is a $\Phi$-Memory in which the order of the
-sentences in the $a_i$th $\mathparagraph^m$ has the meaning of \said{I have actually been doing $A_{a_i}$}
-assigned to it. The order is the indication that $A_{a_i}$ has actually been used; it
-is the $a_j$th M*-assertion. \said{I have actually been doing $A_{a_i}$} is merely an English
-translation, and does not appear in the $\Phi*$-Memory.
-
-\conclusion{7} Given a $\Phi*$-Memory, if one D-sentence is forgotten, not
-only will there be a gap in the awareness of when what events occurred; it
-will be forgotten which method has actually been used.
-
-This conclusion points toward a study in which deformations of the
-memory language are related to deformations of general consciousness.
-
-\definition A "$\Phi*$-Reflection," or reflection in the present of a
-$\Phi*$-Memory, is a collection of assertions about the future, derived from a
-$\Phi*$-Memory, as follows.
-\begin{enumerate}
- \item There are the sentences "$Event_j$ will occur in the
-interval of time which is $x_j-x_{j-1}$ long, and begins at twice the present time
-$AF$, minus $x_j AF$; and which is $y_j$ long and begins $z_j$ from now." If $event_j$ was
-a 3-inch move toward the destination in the "$\Phi*$-Memory, the sentence in the
-$\Phi*$-Reflection says that a 3-inch move will be made in the future temporal
-interval.
- \item The $a_i$th permutation of the sentences defined in (1) is an
-assertion which has the meaning of \said{I will do $A_{a_i}$}; and the organism can
-think precisely one permutation at a time. The $A_{a_i}$, $x_j$, $y_j$, $z_j$, and the rest are
-defined as before (so that in particular the permutations can be indexed with
-the $a_i$).
-\end{enumerate}
-
-\conclusion{8} Given that the $\Phi*$-Memory's temporal intervals $|x_{j-1}, x_j|$
-are reflected as $|2N-x_j, 2N-x_{j-1}|$, the reflection preserves the intervals'
-absolute distances from the present.
-
-\proof: The least distance of $|x_{j-1}, x_j|$
-from $N$ is $N-x_j$; the greatest distance is $N-x_{j-1}$. Adding the least distance, and
-then the greatest distance, to $N$, gives $|2N-x_j, 2N-x_{j-1}|$.
-
-I will end with two problems. If a $\Phi*$-Memory exists, under what
-conditions will a $\Phi*$-Reflection be a precognition? Under what conditions
-will every assertion be prescience or foreknowledge? By a "precognition" I
-don't mean a prediction about the future implied by deterministic laws; I
-mean a direct "memory" of the future unconnected with general principles.
-
-Finally, what would a precognitive $\Phi*$-Reflection be like as a mental
-experience? What present or ongoing awareness would accompany a
-precognitive $\Phi*$-Reflection?
+\part{Para-science}
+\input{essays/dissociation_physics.tex}
+\input{essays/mathematical_studies.tex}
+\input{essays/post_formalism_memories.tex}
+\input{essays/studies_in_constructed_memories.tex}
\part{The New Modality}
-
-\chapter{Representation of the Memory of an Energy Cube Organism (1966 VERSION)}
-
-
-The energy cube organism is a conscious organism which is nothing but
-energy confined to a cubical space. It rests on a rectangular energy slab, in a
-stationary, colorless liquid, separated from the slab by a thin film of liquid.
-It has been on the slab for an indefinitely long time. There are in fact two
-infinite bodies of the liquid, alternating with two infinite empty spaces; the
-four volumes are outlined by two intersecting planes which just miss being
-perpendicular. The slab is poised, at a slant, on the faces of the upper body
-of liquid, near where they meet. There are no other objects in the bodies of
-liquid. The slab, liquid, and spaces are the energy cube organism's entire
-cosmology. (See the illustration.)
-
-\img{energycube}
-
-The energy cube organism can continuously change position,
-continuously and instantly moving the liquid from its path into its wake so
-as to make no current in the liquid. For almost as long as it has been on the
-slab, the organism has devoted itself to crossing the slab, from the slab's edge
-on one face of the liquid to its edge on the other.
-
-The energy cube organism has a conscious memory (by which I mean
-strictly a memory of what it did and what happened to it, the past events of
-its existence). The memory consists of symbols which are given "meaning"
-by their extra-linguistic mental associations---in human terms, it consists of
-language. The complete memory contains tens of thousands of partial
-memories, which the organism can only have one at a time. Going through
-the partials---which it does as if they were the phonemes of one long
-word---constitutes its one complete memory. Each partial is a memory of the
-difference in the organism's minimum distances from the destination edge, at
-the beginning, and at the end, of some interval of time. Call the difference its
-"progress." The total of time intervals in all the partials completely covers
-the interval from the earliest remembered event to the most recent
-remembered event. As time passes, more partials are added to the complete
-memory. The production of partial memories is an involuntary process of
-the organism.
-
-The memory is temporally dual. The interval for each partial is an
-interval of fixed time, defined by its duration, and the distance from the
-fixed time when the energy cube organism appeared on the slab up to the
-interval's end. But it is also a sliding interval, defined by its duration, and a
-constant distance from the present instant back to the interval's end. When
-partials are added to the memory, each of the former intervals exactly covers
-the tire not already covered, up to the absolute time when the partial is
-added. But the latter intervals, while they never overlap, can have gaps
-between them. The intervals generally are of different durations. The energy
-cube organism lacks any independent extra-linguistic memory, any mental
-reliving of the past, which could conflict with the dual temporal memory.
-There is no form to the past other than that of the memory's language. (See
-the graph.)
-
-The order of the partials in the complete memory is a linguistic
-phenomenon which indicates the method the organism has been using to
-move itself--and thus the order (with its extra-linguistic associations) is the
-memory of the method. A single method" is everything to be done by the
-energy cube organism to move itself, throughout the entire time it takes to
-reach the destination edge. There are different possible methods, and each
-could get the organism across; but the methods cannot be combined in any
-way. Every order of all partials signifies a different possible method. These
-possible methods are in no special order. When a partial is added to the
-memory, the number of possible methods is increased by a factor equal to
-the new number of partials.
-
-\img{energycubegraph}
-
-{
- \centering
- \textsc{Graph} showing a possible relationship in the dual temporal memory
- \par
-}
-
-
-Now the complete memory is obtained by going through the partials---in
-any order! Any order gives the memory. This feature, which can be
-precisely characterized in terms of the memory language, is perhaps the most
-remarkable feature of the whole cosmology. An approach to this feature in
-human terms is to say that when the organism goes through the partials, (it
-dreams that) it has been using the method indicated---and is presently using
-it. It (does not remember the dream, and) does not remember going through
-the partials. It has no other memory of which method it has been using.
-
-The organism moves itself by mental exertion, teleports itself. The
-"possible methods" are mental routines. These routines draw on the
-following standard mental resources. The organism can assume at will many
-"mental states." By 'mental state' I refer to a mental "stage" or "space" or
-"mood" in which visualizing, remembering, and all imaging can be carried
-on. Some human mental states are general euphoria, stupor, general anxiety,
-dreaming, dizziness, empathy with another person, and clearheadedness, the
-normal state in which work is performed. These states are not defined by
-specific imagings, but are "spaces" in which imaging is carried on. The
-organism changes its state by changing from one form of energy to another,
-gravity, magnetism, electric energy, radiated heat, or light. In these states,
-the organism has an unlimited capacity to image; in human terms, to
-visualize. There are visualized regions of colored liquids. Call them "fluid
-colors." There are visualized glowing surfaces, and there are black regions or
-"holes." There are visualized "covers," "lattices," and "shells," which are all
-formed from transparent planes, spherical surfaces and the like. Call them
-"orojected surfaces." The fluid colors can be stationary or flowing. There are
-"channels," which are strung-out series of fluid colors. There are
-"reservoirs," which are clusters of fluid colors. A channel can be closed or
-open. Two channels can cross each other. There are pairs of channels such
-that earlier members of each channel flow into later members of the
-other---called "screw-connected" channels. Fluid colors often occur on or
-within projected surfaces. Projected surfaces can be growing or held. A
-visualization can be at the forefront of attention, or in the back of the mind.
-That is, states have depth, and visualizations can be at different depths. The
-state as a whole can be "frozen" or "melted." A human approach is to say
-that a "frozen" state is set or fixed; while a "melted" state is fluid---the state
-itself flows. A state can be projected into "superstate," gaining an abnormal
-amount of mental energy and becoming superdizziness or superanxiety, for
-instance.
-
-Most interesting, states in different possible methods can have contact
-with each other. A human approach is to say that dreams are so flexible that
-the organism can dream that an actual state is\slash was in contact with a state in
-a possible method. One sort of cross-method contact is for states to be
-"interfrozen"---more easily frozen because they are somehow mixed. They
-can also be "intermelted."
-
-I will describe a method, as the organism would be conscious of it in
-remembering. For concreteness, I will refer to the different states with the
-names of human states rather than with letters. Channels are generated in a
-frozen stupor, and become fixed at the forefront of attention of euphoria
-intermelted with a possible state. The screw-crossed channels erode crevices
-in a held lattice, which breaks into growing sheets (a variety of covers). The
-sheets are stacked, and held in a frozen dream thawed at intervals for
-reshuffling of the stack. The dream becomes melted, and proceeds in a
-trajectory which shears, and closes, open channels. If no violation of the
-channels cross-mars the melt, the stack meshes with the sharp-open channels.
-The dream becomes interfrozen, and mixed clear-headed states compress the
-closed channels which were not fixed at the dream's surface. A fused
-exterior double-flash (a certain maximally "glowing surface") is
-expand-enveloped by euphoria, which becomes dizziness; and oblique
-lattices are projected from the paralinear deviation of guided open channels
-in it. Growing shells are dreamed into violet sound-slices (certain synesthetic
-"fluid colors") by the needed jumped drag (a generic state), a crossfrozen
-dream. Channels in a growing anxiety enspiral concentric shells having
-intermixed reservoirs between them, during cyclic intersection of the anxiety
-in superstate. And on and on. Time is here the time it takes to carry out the
-successive steps of the routine.
-
-The energy cube organism language, the symbols constituting the
-partials, are themselves mental entities. A partial is a rectangular plane
-glowing surface, which has two stationary plane reservoirs on it, and has a
-triangular hole in it. As a mental entity, in other words, a partial is a
-visualization like those which are part of the methods. The perimeter of the
-triangular hole equals the organism's progress in the corresponding time
-interval. Absence of the hole indicates zero progress.
-
-The fluid colors in each of the reservoirs on each partial memory are
-primary colors, and are mixed together. Speaking as accurately as possible in
-human terms, in each reservoir there is precisely one point of "maximum
-mixture" of the primary colors. The primary colors are mentally mixed in
-any way until the right amount of mixture is reached. There is a scale of
-measurement for amounts of mixture of the colors. There is a scale for
-vertical distances on the surface---for how far one point is below another. The
-difference in amounts of mixture at the two points of maximum mixture
-corresponds to the length of the first temporal interval; and the difference
-between the maximum possible amount of mixture and the lesser of the two
-amounts of maximum mixture on the surface corresponds to the distance
-from the fixed beginning time to the interval's and. The vertical distance
-between the two points of maximum mixture corresponds to the length of
-the second temporal interval; and the vertical distance from the middle of
-the surface to the point nearer it corresponds to the constant distance from
-the present instant back to the interval's enc. The middle of the surface
-represents the present, and the upper half represents the future; the
-reservoirs are all in the lower half. For each partial it is necessary to
-determine (1) the number of units of duration per unit difference in
-amounts of mixture; and (2) the number of units of duration per unit
-difference in vertical distances. The average glow per unit area of each
-glowing surface (excepting the hole) is correlated with a pair of numbers
-constituting this information.
-
-Finally, turning all the partial memories upside down--and reflecting the
-first temporal memory in the present instant, so that the intervals' absolute
-distances from the present are preserved--gives the precognition of the
-organism's future course of action, tells what progress will be made when
-and by which method.
-
-
-\section*{The Representation}
-
-This essay accompanies a representation of the energy cube organism's
-memory--hence its title. The way to picture the memory, naturally, is to
-make something that looks like the partials. I have represented the partials
-by rectangular sheets of paper of different translucencies with mixtures of
-inks of primary colors on them and holes cut in them; together in an
-envelope, which bears the injunction not to have more than one sheet out at
-a time. Three of the tens of thousands of partials are represented.
-
-
-\chapter{Representation of the Memory of an Energy Cube Organism (Original 1961 Version)}
-
-\section*{Foreward}
-
-I have refrained from editing the Original Version except where
-absolutely necessary. It is full of inconsistencies and inadequate
-explanations, but I have flagged only two major ones, by placing them
-between the signs $\ltimes$ and $\rtimes$. Part of the fourth paragraph is flagged because a
-sequence of units is not analogous to a sequence of inflected words; it is
-rather more like permutations of letters which form words ('rat', 'tar', 'art').
-Most of the seventh paragraph is flagged because I promise to define intervals
-by their lengths and ends, but instead give their beginnings and ends.
-
-In the fourth paragraph, there are two different versions of the
-correspondence between possible methods and sequences of units, and of
-why any sequence is acceptable. Passages belonging exclusively to the
-"multiplex" version are set off by the sign \#. Passages which belong
-exclusively to the "style" version and which should be deleted if the
-"multiplex" version is used are placed between slashes (\slash). The "style" version is
-the main version. In the fifth paragraph, a notion appears which is
-interesting, but unconvincingly explained. It is not clear whether this notion
-relates only to the "multiplex" version, or whether it would relate to the
-"style" version if the word 'multiplex' were omitted. The passages suggesting
-this notion are placed in brackets.
-
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item Energy cube organisms are conscious organisms which are cubical
-spaces containing only energy. The particular energy cube organism of
-concern here has, for an indefinitely long time, been in a body of liquid,
-"resting on' a rectangular energy slab also in the body of liquid; the
-organism's "bottom" face is separated from the slab by only a very thin film
-of the liquid. The "universe" the organism and slab are in is made up of four
-infinite triangular right prisms, prismatic spaces, as defined geometrically by
-two intersecting planes almost perpendicular to each other. The prismatic
-spaces defined by the vertical obtuse dihedral angles are empty. The other
-spaces, defined by the vertical acute dihedral angles, are infinite bodies of a
-stationary, colorless liquid--the "upper" body of liquid being what the
-organism and slab are in. The two opposite shorter edges of the slab are at
-the faces of the body of liquid, the planes, near their intersection; the slab is
-"slanted," so that the edges are at slightly different distances from the line
-of intersection. The organism and slab are the only "objects" in the bodies
-of liquid. (See the illustration.) The organism can move (the energy cube can
-continuously change position) without creating currents in the liquid. For
-almost as long as it has been in the liquid, the organism has devoted all its
-"intelligence," all its "energies," to moving across the slab, from one of the
-shorter edges to (any point on) the other.
-
-\item The organism's conscious, distinct memory is entirely concerned
-with, is entirely of, its efforts to cross the slab. (I am using 'memory'
-narrowly to refer to an organism's memory of its past. I am counting its
-"general information," for example knowing a language, not as part of its
-memory but as imagings not memories. Thinking the sequence 1, 2, 1, 2 is
-not in itself remembering.) The total memory consists of a large number of
-units (tens of thousands), of which the organism can be attentive to precisely
-one at a time. "Total recall," the total memory, involves considering, having,
-all units in any succession, which the organism can do very rapidly. Now
-from one point of view, the memory consists of its content; from another, it
-consists of symbols, just as human memories often consist of language. In
-describing the memory, I will go from considering primarily the content,
-what the memory is of; to considering the specific character of the units,
-specific symbolism used in the memory, and specific content. Each unit is
-first a memory of the amount of progress made toward the destination edge
-in a particular interval of time. The amount of progress is the difference
-between the minimum distance of the organism from the destination edge at
-the beginning of the interval, and the minimum distance at the end of the
-interval. The total of intervals, in the total of units, cover the "absolute"
-interval of time from the earliest to the most recent remembered event; as
-time passes, more units are added to the memory.
-
-\item Now the memory is temporally dual: the interval of time for each
-unit is first, an interval of 'absolute' time; defined by its duration, and the
-"absolute" time of its end (stated with respect to an "absolute event" such
-as the appearance of the organism on the slab); and secondly, an interval
-defined by its duration, and how far from the present instant its end is. It is
-like remembering that so much progress was made during one year which
-ended at January 1, 1000 A.D.; as well as remembering that it was made
-during one year which ended 1,000 years ago. In the second temporal
-memory, the absolute time of the end of the interval to which the progress is
-assigned changes according as the absolute time of the present instant
-changes. For example, it is like remembering \said{that so much progress was
-made during one year ending 1,000 years ago,} and, 100 years later,
-remembering---\said{that so much progress was made during one year ending
-1,000 years ago}; and in general, always remembering \said{that so much
-progress was made during one year ending 1,000 years ago.} Both temporal
-memories are in their own ways "natural," the first being anchored at an
-"absolute beginning," the second at the present instant. When a unit is added
-to the memory, the interval of time of the first temporal memory is added at
-the end, exactly covers the time not already covered, up to the absolute time
-when the unit is added; so that the total of intervals of the first temporal
-memory exactly cover, without overlap, the absolute total time. In contrast,
-although the intervals of the second temporal memory do not overlap at any
-time, there can be gaps between them; so that when a unit is added to the
-memory, the interval for the second temporal memory may be placed
-between existing intervals and not have to cover an absolute time which they
-have left behind, that is, not have to be placed farther back than all of them.
-Intervals of both temporal memories are of different sizes, a "natural
-complexity." (See the graph.) Incidentally, the condition for coincidence of
-the two temporal intervals of a unit is: if the two intervals are of the same
-duration, they will coincide at the absolute time which is the sum of the
-absolute time of the end of the first interval, and the distance from the
-present instant of the end of the second interval. The two temporal
-memories complement each other; aside from this comment I will not be
-concerned to "explain" the duality with respect to when the amounts of
-progress were made, whether when they were "really" made stayed the same
-and changed, or whether the memory is inconsistent about it, or what.
-
-\item I will now turn to the aspect of the memory concerned with the
-method the organism has used to move itself. \# Methodologically, the
-memory is a multiplex symbol. \# A "single method" is everything to be done
-by the organism, to move itself, throughout the total time it takes to reach
-the destination edge; so that the organism could not use two different
-"single methods," must, after it chooses its method, continue with it alone
-throughout. The organism has available different (single) methods, has
-different methods it could try. The different sequences, of all units, are
-assigned to the different (single) methods available to the organism to signify
-them; are symbols for them. (Thus, the number of available methods
-increases as units are added to the memory.) \slash Now all this only approximates
-what is the case, because contrary to what I may have implied, which
-method is used is not a matter of "fact" as are the temporal intervals and
-amounts of progress. As I have said, having all units in any succession
-constitutes the total memory, total recall ("factually")--different sequences
-of all units are each the total memory, total recall, $\ltimes$ but, as language, the
-total memory in different styles (like words in different orders in a highly
-inflected language); and the matter of method (which might better be said to
-be "manner") corresponds to the matter of style, rather than factual
-content, of language. Different styles exclude each other, but not what is
-said in each other's being true.$\rtimes$ Thus it is that the number of available
-methods can increase; and that any sequence of all units can constitute the
-total memory, total recall ("factually"), although different sequences signify
-different methods used. \slash \# As an indicator of the method used, the whole
-memory is a multiplex symbol. Names for each of the methods are combined
-in a single symbol, the totality of units. In remembering, the organism
-separates any single name by going through all the units in succession, and
-that name is the complete reading of the multiplex symbol, the complete
-information about the method used. I will not be concerned to "explain"
-the matter of the increasing number of available methods; or the matter of
-any sequence of all units' constituting the complete reading, the total
-memory, total recall, but different sequences' signifying different methods
-used. \#
-
-\item I will give just an indication of what the available methods [and
-their relations through the multiplex memory] are like. Throughout this
-description, there has been the difficulty that English lacks a vocabulary
-appropriate for describing the "universe" I am concerned with, but the
-difficulty is particularly great here, in the case of the methods [and their
-relations through the multiplex memory]; so that I will just have to
-approximate a vocabulary with present English as best as I can. The
-methods, instruments of autokinesis, are all mental, teleportation, resu!t in
-teleportation. The "consciousnesses" available to the organism to be
-combined into methods are infinitely many. It has available many states of
-mind (as humans have non-consciousness, autohypnotic trance, dizziness,
-dreaming, clear-headed calculation, and so forth), corresponding to different
-forms its energy can assume. To give this description more content I will
-differentiate its states of mind by referring to them with the names of the
-human states of mind (rather than just with letters). It has available an
-indefinite variety of contents, as humans have particular imagings, in its
-conscious states of mind. I will outline the principal contents. There are
-"visualized" fluid regions of color (like colored liquids), first-order contents.
-There are 'visualized' radient surfaces, and non-radient surfaces or regions
-("holes"), the intermediate contents. The second-order contents are
-"projective" constructs of imaged geometric surfaces, "covers," "lattices,"
-and "shells." Fluid colors can be stationary or flowing. They can occur in
-certain series, "channels"; and in certain arrays, "reservoirs." A channel can
-be "closed" or "open"; two channels can be "crossed," or
-"screw-connected" (earlier members of each channel flowing into later
-members of the other). First-order contents (fluid colors) often occur on or
-within second-order ones (projective surfaces). Second-order contents can be
-"held" or "growing." States of mind have depth, 'deeper' being 'farther from
-the forefront of attention'; and contents can be at different depths. A state
-of mind as a unity can be "frozen," which is more than just unchanging (in
-particular having its contents stationary or held). It can be projected into
-"superstate," remaining a state of mind but being superenergized. [Most
-interesting, states of mind, in different methods signified by different
-symbols combined in the multiplex methodological memory, can have
-contact with each other, for example be "interfrozen."] A partial description
-of a method will give an idea of the complexity of the methods. Channels are
-generated by a frozen non-conscious state, and become fixed in the surface
-layer of an [inter] melted trance. The screw-crossed channels erode crevices
-in a held shell, which breaks into growing sheets (certain covers). The sheets
-are stacked, and held in a frozen dream thawed at intervals for reshuffling.
-The dream becomes melted, and proceeds in a trajectory which shears, and
-closes, open channels. If no violation of the channels cross-mars the melt, the
-stack meshes with the sharp-open channels. The dream becomes [inter]
-frozen, and mixed calculation states compress the closed channels which
-were not surface-fixed in it. A fused exterior double-flash (a certain
-maximally radient surface) is expand-enveloped by a trance, which becomes
-dizziness; and oblique lattices are projected from the paralinear deviation of
-guided open channels in it. Growing shells are dreamed into violet
-sound-slices (certain fluid colors) by the needed jumped drag (a certain
-consciousness), a [cross] frozen dream. Channels in a growing trance enspiral
-concentric shells having intermixed reservoirs between them, during cyclic
-intersection of the trance in superstate. I will not say more about the
-available methods, because in a sense the memory does not: a sequence of
-units is a marker arbitrarily assigned to a method to signify it, like an
-arbitrary letter, say 'q', assigned to a certain table to signify it; it no more
-gives characteristics of the method than 'q' does of the table. In fact, the
-available methods and sequences do not have any particular order; one
-cannot speak of the "first" method, the "second," or the like.
-
-\item I will now concentrate on the character of the memory as a mental
-entity, and the rest of the symbolism used in it and specific content. A unit
-is a rectangular plane ("visualized") radient surface (! ---the terminology is
-that introduced in the last paragraph), which has two stationary plane
-reservoirs (!) on it, and has a triangular hole (!) in it. The triangular hole is
-a simple symboi not yet explained: its perimeter equals the amount of the
-organism's progress, the difference in its minimum distances from the
-destination edge, in the interval the unit is concerned with. Absence of the
-hole indicates zero perimeter and no progress.
-
-\item As for the symbols for the temporal interval. The colors in each of
-the two reservoirs on each unit are primary, and are mixed together.
-Speaking as accurately as possible in English, in each reservoir there is
-precisely one point of "maximum mixture' of the primary colors. (The rest
-of the reservoirs are not significant: the primary colors are mentally mixed in
-any way to get the right amount of mixture, as pigments are mixed on a
-palette.) $\ltimes$ For the first temporal memory, these points are two points on a
-scale of amounts of color mixture. For the second memory, the points are
-two points on a scale of vertical distances from the imaginary horizontal! line
-which bisects the rectangular surface, divides it into lower and upper halves.
-The units are marked in their lower halves only; because for the second
-memory the imaginary dividing line represents the present instant, distances
-below it represent distances into the past, and distances above it distances
-into the future (lower and upper edges representing equal distances from the
-present). Now a scale is required so that it can be told what temporal
-intervals the interval on the amount of mixture scale and the interval on the
-distance scale represent. The parts of the scale which may vary from unit to
-unit and have to be specified in each unit are the "absolute" time
-corresponding to the maximum possible color mixture, the number of units
-of absolute duration per unit difference in amounts of mixture, and the
-number of units of absolute duration per unit difference in distances from
-the imaginary dividing line. The markers arbitrarily assigned to the triples of
-information giving these parts of the scale are average radiences per unit
-areas of the units (excepting the holes). $\rtimes$
-
-\item A final aspect of interest. Not too surprisingly, the transformation
-which is inverting all units gives, if one considers not the first temporal
-memory but its reflection in the present instant, the organism's precognized
-course of action in the future, specifically, what progress will be made when.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-
-\section*{The Representation}
-
-With this background, it is not surprising that the method of
-representation I have chosen is visual representation of the units, the
-"visualizations." Units are represented by rectangular sheets of paper of
-different translucencies with mixtures of inks of primary colors on them and
-holes cut in them, together in an envelope. Only one sheet should be out of
-the envelope at a time. A sheet should be viewed while placed before a white
-light in front of a black background, so that the light illuminates the whole
-sheet as evenly as possible without being seen through the hole, only the
-black being seen at the hole. The ultimate in fidelity would be to learn to
-visualize these sheets as they look when viewed properly; then one could
-have the memory as nearly as possible as the organism does. I have
-represented eleven of the tens of thousands of units in the total memory.
-
-
-\chapter{Concept Art}
-{ \raggedleft (1961) \par }
-
-
-Concept art is first of all an art of which the material is concepts, as the
-material of e.g. music is sound. Since concepts are closely bound up with
-language, concept art is a kind of art of which the material is language. That
-is, unlike e.g. a work of music, in which the music proper (as opposed to
-notation, analysis, etc.) is just sound, concept art proper will involve
-language. From the philosophy of language, we learn that a concept may as
-well be thought of as the intension of a name; this is the relation between
-concepts and language.\footnote{The extension of the word 'table' is all
-existing tables; the intension of 'table' is all possible instances of a table.}
-The notion of a concept is a vestige of the notion of
-a platonic form (the thing which e.g. all tables have in common: tableness),
-which notion is replaced by the notion of a name objectively, metaphysically
-related to its intension (so that all tables now have in common their
-objective relation to table). Now the claim that there can be an objective
-relation between a name and its intension is wrong, and (the word) concept,
-as commonly used now, can be discredited (see my book, Philosophy
-Proper). If, however, it is enough for one that there be a subjective relation
-between a name and its intension, namely the unhesitant decision as to the
-way one wants to use the name, the unhesitant decisions to affirm the names
-of some things but not others, then concept is valid language, and concept
-art has a philosophically valid basis.
-
-Now what is artistic, aesthetic, about a work which is a body of
-concepts? This question can best be answered by telling where concept art
-came from; I developed it in an attempt to straighten out certain traditional
-activities generally regarded as aesthetic. The first of these is structure art,
-music, visual art, etc., in which the important thing is "structure." My
-definitive discussion of structure art is in my unpublished essay \essaytitle{Structure
-Art and Pure Mathematics}; here I will just summarize that discussion. Much
-structure art is a vestige of the time when \eg music was believed to be
-knowledge, a science, which had important things to say in astronomy \etc
-Contemporary structure artists, on the other hand, tend to claim the kind of
-cognitive value for their art that conventional contemporary mathematicians
-claim for mathematics. Modern examples of structure art are the fugue and
-total serial music. These examples illustrate the important division of
-structure art into two kinds according to how the structure is appreciated. In
-the case of a fugue, one is aware of its structure in listening to it; one
-imposes relationships, a categorization (hopefully that intended by the
-composer) on the sounds while listening to them, that is, has an (associated)
-artistic structure experience. In the case of total serial music, the structure is
-such that this cannot be done; one just has to read an analysis of the
-music, definition of the relationships. Now there are two things wrong with
-structure art. First, its cognitive pretensions are utterly wrong. Secondly, by
-trying to be music or whatever (which has nothing to do with knowledge),
-and knowledge represented by structure, structure art both fails, is
-completely boring, as music, and doesn't begin to explore the aesthetic
-possibilities structure can have when freed from trying to be music or
-whatever.The first step in straightening out e.g. structure music is to stop
-calling it music, and start saying that the sound is used only to carry the
-structure and that the real point is the structure--and then you will see how
-limited, impoverished, the structure is. Incidentally, anyone who says that
-works of structure music do occasionally have musical value just doesn't
-know how good real music (the Goli Dance of the Baoule; Cans on Windows
-by La Monte Young; the contemporary American hit song Sweets for My
-Sweets, by the Drifters) can get. When you make the change, then since
-structures are concepts, you have concept art. Incidentally, there is another,
-less important kind of art which when straightened out becomes concept art:
-art involving play with the concepts of the art such as, in music, the score,
-performer vs. listener, playing a work. The second criticism of structure art
-applies, with the necessary changes, to this art.
-
-The second main antecedent of structure art is mathematics. This is the
-result of my revolution in mathematics, presented in my 1966 \essaytitle{Mathematical
-Studies}; here I will only summarize. The revolution occured first because for
-reasons of taste I wanted to deemphasize discovery in mathematics,
-mathematics as discovering theorems and proofs. I wasn't good at such
-discovery, and it bored me. The first way I thought of to de-emphasize
-discovery came not later than Summer, 1960; it was that since the value of
-pure mathematics is now regarded as aesthetic rather than cognitive, why not
-try to make up aesthetic theorems, without considering whether they are
-true. The second way, which came at about the same time, was to find, as a
-philosopher, that the conventional claim that theorems and proofs are
-discovered is wrong, for the same reason I have already given that 'concept'
-can be discredited. The third way, which came in the fall-winter of 1960,
-was to work in unexplored regions of formalist mathematics. The resulting
-mathematics still had statements, theorems, proofs, but the latter weren't
-discovered in the way they traditionally were. Now exploration of the wider
-possibilities of mathematics as revolutionized by me tends to lead beyond
-what it makes sense to call mathematics; the category of mathematics, a
-vestige of Platonism, is an unnatural, bad one. My work in mathematics leads
-to the new category of concept art, of which straightened out traditional
-mathematics (mathematics as discovery) is an untypical, smal! but
-intensively developed part.
-
-I can now return to the question of why concept art is art. Why isn't it an
-absolutely new, or at least a non-artistic, non-aesthetic activity? The answer
-is that the antecedents of concept art are commonly regarded as artistic,
-aesthetic activities; on a deeper level, interesting concepts, concepts
-enjoyable in themselves, especially as they occur in mathematics, are
-commonly said to have beauty. By calling my activity art, therefore, I am
-simply recognizing this common usage, and the origin of the activity in
-structure art and mathematics. However: it is confusing to call things as
-irrelevant as the emotional enjoyment of (rea!) music, and the intellectual
-enjoyment of concepts, the same kind of enjoyment. Since concept art
-includes almost everything ever said to be music, at least, which is not music
-for the emotions, perhaps it would be better to restrict art to apply to art for
-the emotions, and recognize my activity as an independent, new activity,
-irrelevant to art (and knowledge).
-
-\section*{Concept Art Version of Mathematics System 3/26/61 (6/19/61)}
-
-An element is the adjacent area (with the figure in it) so long as the
-apparent, perceived, ratio of the length of the vertical line to that of the
-horizontal line (the element's associated ratio) does not change.
-
-A selection sequence is a sequence of elements of which the first is the one
-having the greatest associated ratio, and each of the others has the associated
-ratio next smaller than that of the preceding one. (To decrease the ratio,
-come to see the vertical line as shorter, relative to the horizontal line, one
-might try measuring the lines with a ruler to convince oneself that the
-vertical one is not longer than the other, and then trying to see the lines as
-equal in length; constructing similar figures with a variety of real (measured)
-ratios and practicing judging these ratios; and so forth.)
-
-[Observe that the order of elements in a selection sequence may not be the
-order in which one sees them.]
-
-
-\img{implications}
-
-\section*{Implications---Concept Art Version of Colored Sheet Music No. 1 3/14/61 (10/11/61)}
-
-[This is a mathematical system without general concepts of statement,
-implication, axiom, and proof. Instead, you make the object, and stipulate
-by ostension that it is an axiom, theorem, or whatever. My thesis is that
-since there is no objective relation between name and intension, all
-mathematics is this arbitrary. Originally, the successive statements, or sheets,
-were to be played on an optical audiorecorder.]
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-The axiom: a sheet of cheap, thin white typewriter paper
-
-The axiom implies statement 2: soak the axiom in inflammable liquid which
-does not leave solid residue when burned; then burn it on horizontal
-rectangular white fireproof surface---statement 2 is ashes (on surface)
-
-Statement 2 implies s.3: make black and white photograph of s.2 in white
-light (image of ashes' rectangle with respect to white surface (that is, of the
-region (of surface, with the ashes on it) with bounding edges parallel to the
-edges of the surface and intersecting the four points in the ashes nearest the
-four edges of the surface) must exactly cover the film); develop film---s.3 is
-the negative.
-
-s.2 and s.3 imply s.4: melt s.3 and cool in mold to form plastic doubly
-convex lens with small curvature; take color photograph of ashes' rectangle
-in yellow light using this lens; develop film---s.4 is color negative.
-
-s.2 and s.4 imply s.5: repeat last step with s.4 (instead of 3), using red
-light---s.5 is second color negative
-
-s.2 and s.5 imply s.6: repeat last step with s.5, using blue light---s.6 is third
-color negative
-
-s.2 and s.6 imply s.7: make lens from s.6 mixed with the ashes which have
-been being photographed; make black and white photograph, in white fight,
-of that part of the white surface where the ashes' rectangle was; develop film
---- s.7 is second black and white negative
-
-s.2, s.6, and s.7 imply the theorem: melt, mold, and cool lens used in last
-step to form negative, and make lens from s.7; using negative and lens in an
-enlarger, make two prints, an enlargement and a reduction--enlargement and
-reduction together constitute the theorem.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-\section*{Concept Art: Innpersegs (May--July 1961)}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-A "halpoint" iff whatever is at any point in space, in the fading rainbow halo
-which appears to surround a small bright light when one looks at it through
-glasses fogged by having been breathed on, for as long as the point is in the
-halo.
-
-An "init`point" iff a halpoint in the initial vague outer ring of its halo.
-
-
-An "inn`perseq" iff a sequence of sequences of halpoints such that all the
-halpoints are on one (initial) radius of a halo; the members of the first
-sequence are initpoints; for each of the other sequences, the first member (a
-consequent) is got from the non-first members of the preceding sequence
-(the antecedents) by being the inner endpoint of the radial segment in the
-vague outer ring when they are on the segment, and the other members (if
-any) are initpoints or first members of preceding sequences; all first members
-of sequences other than the last [two] appear as non-first members, and
-halpoints appear only once as non-first members; and the last sequence has
-one member.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-\section*{Indeterminacy}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-A $\ulcorner$totally determinate innperseq' iff an innperseq$\urcorner$ in which one is aware of
-(specifies) all halpoints.
-
-An $\ulcorner$antecedentally indeterminate innperseq' iff an innperseq$\urcorner$ in which one is
-aware of (specifies) only each consequent and the radial seqment beyond it.
-
-A $\ulcorner$halpointally indeterminate innperseq' iff an innperseq$\urcorner$ in which one is
-aware of (specifies) only the radial segment in the vague outer ring, and its
-inner endpoint, as it progresses inward.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-\subsection*{Innperseqs Diagram}
-
-In the diagram, different positions of the vague outer ring at different times
-are suggested by different shadings. The radia! segment in the vague outer
-ring moves down the page. The figure is by no means an innperseq, but is
-supposed to help explain the definition.
-
-\img{innperseqsdiagram}
-
-\chapter{Exhibit of a Working Model of a Perception-Dissociator}
-
-\section{\textsc{Statement of Objectives}}
-
-To construct a model of a machine a thousand years before the machine
-itself is technologically feasible---to model a technological breakthrough a
-thousand years before it occurs
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-(Analogies: constructing a model of an atomic power plant in ancient
-Rome; chess-playing-machine hoaxes of 19th-century Europe as
-models of computers; Soviet Cosmos Hall at Expo 67 as model
-of anti-gravity machine)
-
-To construct the mode! almost entirely from the visitors coming to see it, so
-that each visitor regards the others as the model!
-
-What the hypothetical perception-dissociator will do that is not
-possible now:
-\end{sysrules}
-
-\begin{itemize}
-\item Physically alter the world (relative to you): sound disappears; sights and
-touches are dissociated; other people unconsciously signal you.
-
-\item Physically, "psychoelectronically" induce conditioned reflexes in your
-nervous system. Physically break ddwn your sense of time.
-\end{itemize}
-
-{ \centering
- \large
- [\textsc{Invitation}] \par}
-
-{ \centering
-Because of your interest in technology and science, you are invited to visit \\
- \textsc{Exhibit of a Working Model of a} \\
- \textsc{Perception-Dissociator} \\
-Sponsored by (legitimate sponsor) Open continuously from (date) \\
-to (date) At (lunar colony or space station) \par
- }
-
-"The perception-dissociator is a machine which is the product of a
-technology far superior to that of humans. With it, a conscious organism can
-drastically transform its psychophysical relation to objects and to other
-conscious organisms\ldots The exhibit spotlights the technical interest of the
-perception-dissociator, giving the visitor a working model of the machine
-which he can use to 'transform' himself." ---from the Guidebook
-
-It isn't possible for this exhibit to be open or public, because of the nature of
-the model. You have been invited in the belief that you will be a cooperative
-visitor. Come alone. Don't discuss the exhibit at all before you see it; and
-don't discuss it afterwards except with other ex-visitors. Come prepared to
-spend several hours without a break. There will be absolutely no risk or
-danger to you if you follow instructions.
-
-\section*{\textsc{To the Director}}
-
-Exhibit requires two adjacent rooms, on moon or other low-gravity
-location, so that humans can easily jump over each other and fall without
-being hurt. First room, the anteroom, has "normal" entrance door leading in
-from "normal" human world. Is filled with chairs or school desks. At far
-corner from normal door is two-step lock, built in anteroom, connecting
-rooms. Normai door on hinges leads from anteroom into first step of lock.
-Sliding panel door leads into second step; and smooth curtain with slit in
-middle leads into the exhibit hali. Another sliding door leads from lock's
-first step directly back out to normal human world, bypassing anteroom.
-Shelf required in first lock to check watches and shoes.
-
-Exhibit hall large and empty with very high ceiling (Fuller dome?). I
-Room must be strongly lighted, so that objects in front of closed eyes will
-cast highly visible shadows on eyelids. Room's inner surfaces must be
-sound-absorbing, and moderate noise must be played into room to mask
-accidental sounds; thus humans will cease to notice sound. Floor must be of
-hard rubber or other material that will not splinter, and will not be too hard
-to fall and crawl on.
-
-Exhibit open continuously for days. Invite people who will seriously
-try to play along---preferably engineers; and invite many of them, because
-is better to have many in exhibit. Sample invitation enclosed. Attendants
-working in shifts must be at two posts throughout. Try to keep surprising
-features of exhibit secret from those who have not been through it.
-
-Procedure. Visitor arrives and enters anteroom. Entrance attendant
-gives him a Guidebook and sends him to sit down and start reading. Then
-visitor goes to lock. Lock attendant must try hard to see that no more than
-one visitor is in lock at a time. If lock is empty of visitors, attendant lets
-entering visitor into first step, checks his watch and shoes, and sends him
-alone into second step and on to exhibit room. When visitor comes out of
-exhibit hall for any reason, he must be gotten into first step, and then
-attendant sends him out the exit. When a visitor comes out, he just goes out
-and doesn't go back in.
-
-\img{dissociatordiag}
-
-
-\clearpage
-
-\textsc{Exhibit of a working model of a perception-dissociator (conceived by Henry Flynt)}
-
-
-\img{guidebook}
-
-
-\textsc{Read this guidebook as directed---straight through or as otherwise directed. Don't leaf around.}
-
-
-\textsc{Read pages 2--3 before you go in to see the exhibit.}
-
-\clearpage
-
-Introduction. The perception-dissociator is a machine which is the
-product of a technology far superior to that of humans. With it, a conscious
-organism can drastically transform its psychophysical relation to objects and
-to other conscious organisms. When the organism has transformed itself,
-sound disappears, time is immeasurable; and the relation between seeing and
-touching becomes a random one. That is, the organism never knows whether
-it will be able to touch or fee! what it sees, and never knows whether it will
-be able to see what it touches or what touches it. The world ceases to be a
-collection of objects (relative to the physically altered organism). Further,
-the machine induces a pattern of communication in the organism's nervous
-system, an involuntary pattern of responses to certain events, to help the
-organism cope with the invisible tactile phenomena. A dimension is added of
-involuntarily relating to other organisms as unconscious signalling devices.
-The transformation induced by the machine is permanent unless the
-organism subsequently uses the machine to undo it.
-
-
-The perception-dissociator is not conscious or alive in any human sense.
-The components of the machine that the user is aware of are:
-\begin{enumerate}
- \item Optical phenomena that are seen---"sights."
- \item Solid or massive phenomena that are felt cutaneously---"touches."
-\end{enumerate}
-If the user tries to touch a sight, he may not be
-able to feel anything there. If he looks for a component that touches him, he
-may not be able to see it.
-
-
-(Keep reading)
-
-\clearpage
-
-In other words, from the beginning the machine has properties that the
-entire world comes to have to the transformed organism.
-
-The exhibit spotlights the technical interest of the
-perception-dissociator, giving the visitor a working model of the machine
-which he can use to "transform" himself. Nothing is said about the purpose
-of the perception-dissociator in the society that can make one. The model is
-sophisticated enough that it can run independently of the visitor's will, and
-can affect him. In fact, the visitor may be hurt if he doesn't follow the
-instructions for using the machine.
-
-
-When you have absorbed the above, go to the entrance and be admitted
-to the exhibit. You must check your shoes, and your watch (if you have
-one), with the attendant. As you enter, turn this page and begin reading Page
-4.
-
-\clearpage
-
-\textsc{Do not talk or make any other uncalled-for noise.}
-
-
-Be prepared for the touch of pulling your feet out from under you
-from behind. Don't resist; just fall forward, break your fali with your arms
-(and retrieve this Guidebook). The floor is not hard and the gravity is weak,
-so the fall should leave you absolutely unhurt.
-
-\plainbreak{2}
-
-\textsc{Avoid all touches (except floor and yourself) unless directed otherwise.}
-(You have been directed not to resist having your
-feet pulled out from under you.)
-\textsc{In effect, if you bump into a solid object or step on one, draw back. Remember
-that you avoid touches by your tactile senses alone.}
-Whether your eyes are open or closed makes no difference. It is not necessary to avoid
-sights unless you touch something.
-
-\plainbreak{2}
-
-There may be the touch of being pushed forward at your shoulder
-blades. Don't resist; just move forward.
-
-\plainbreak{2}
-
-As for the sights in this model, it happens that they will be humanoid.
-All the human appearances other than you in the exhibit hall are sights from
-the machine. This is just the way the model is; don't give it a thought. Sights
-may appear or disappear (for example, at the curtain) while you are looking.
-
-\plainbreak{2}
-
-I am referring to the components of the model with the names of the
-components of the perception-dissociator.
-
-\plainbreak{2}
-
-As soon as you understand the above and are prepared to remember
-and follow the instructions, go immediately to Page 6.
-
-\clearpage
-
-\img{dissoceqns}
-
-\clearpage
-
-You will now begin the first phase of perception-dissociation by the
-machine. Throughout this phase, you walk erect.
-
-Instructions for operating the machine and for protecting yourself from
-it will be given both in English and in an abbreviated symbolism. It is
-important to master the symbolism, because later instructions can't be
-expressed without it.
-
-\begin{itemize}
-\item u means you
-
-\item $s$, $s_1$, $s_2$, $s_3$ mean different sights from the machine
-
-\item $t$, $t_1$, $t_2$, $t_3$ mean different touches from the machine
-
-\item $a\wedge$ means a's eyes are open or a opens its eyes
-
-\item $a\vee$ means a's eyes are shut or a shuts its eyes
-
-\item $a\equiv b$ means a blows on b's hand
-
-\item $a\sqsupset b$ means a pushes b, typically from behind
-(a holds Guidebook under arm or elsewhere)
-
-\item $a\overbracket{b}$ means a jumps over b, crossing completely above b (weak gravity
-should make this easy)
-
-\item $a^\infty b$ means a rapidly waves both hands in front of and near b's eyes so that
-moving shadows are cast on b's eyes (a "shadows" b)
-
-\item $a\overbrace{b}$ means a pulls b's ankles back and up and immediately lets them go, so
-that b falls forward (a "tackles" b)
-
-\item $a\longdivision{b}$ means a jumps and falls on b, or a steps on b
-
-\item $a\lrcorner$ means a rapidly moves aside
-
-\item $()$ parentheses around the symbol for an action mean the action will
-probably happen
-
-\item A line of action symbols constitutes an instruction. The order of symbols
-indicates the order of events. !f one symbol is right above another, the
-actions are simultaneous.
-\end{itemize}
-
-\textsc{You may always turn back to these explanations if you forget them.}
-
-(Keep reading)
-
-\clearpage
-
-Instructions 1--3 apply \textsc{when your eyes are open.}
-
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item If you see a sight close its eyes, a heavy touch from the machine
-may be falling toward you. You must instantly jump aside.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ c c }
- \begin{tabular}{ c c }
- $s_1\wedge$ & $s_1\vee$ \\
- $u\wedge$ & $(t\longdivision{u})$ \\
- \end{tabular} &
- $u\lrcorner$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\textsc{You must follow this and succeeding instructions as long as you stay in the exhibit. Stay with each instruction until you have it thoroughly in memory; and check out the symbolic version so you learn to read the symbols.}
-
-\item If a sight in front of you jumps over you, a touch may be about to
-tackle you. You must instantly jump to one side.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c l }
- $u\wedge$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $s\overbracket{u}$ \\
- $(t\overbrace{u})$ \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\lrcorner$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\item If a sight waves its hands in front of your open eyes, a touch may
-be about to shove from behind. Jump to one side.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c l }
- $u\wedge$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $s^\infty u$\\
- $(t\sqsupset u)$ \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\lrcorner$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\textsc{If there are any sights, try standing around and following these instructions for a short while.}
-
-\item If you close your eyes, you must keep them closed until a touch
-tackles you, a touch shoves you, or you can't keep your mind on the exhibit
-(which you should also consider to be an effect of the machine). Then you
-immediately open your eyes.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c l }
- $u\vee$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $t\overbrace{u}$ \\ \midrule
- $t\sqsupset u$ \\ \midrule
- $u$ inattentive \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\wedge$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\emph{(A horizontal line between action symbols means \emph{or.} With it, instructions can be combined)}
-
-\textsc{The next three instructions tell you what to do when your eyes are closed. Learn them well.}
-
-\item If you feel a breath blowing on one of your hands, a touch may be
-falling on you. You must instantly jump to the side away from the breath.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c l }
- $u\vee$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $t_1\equiv u$ \\
- $t_2\longdivision{u}$ \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\lrcorner$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-(Turn page and continue)
-
-\clearpage
-
-\item If your closed eyes are shadowed, a touch may be about to tackle
-you. You must instantly jump aside.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c l }
- $u\vee$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $s^\infty u$ \\
- ($t\overbrace{u}$) \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\lrcorner$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\item If you sense a massive touch going above your head, another touch
-may be about to shove you from behind. Jump aside.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c l }
- $u\vee$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $t_1\overbracket{u}$ \\
- ($t_2\sqsupset u$) \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\lrcorner$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\item If you have any time left over from following other instructions,
-close your eyes and go around with your hands in front of you, shoving
-touches whenever you feel them.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ c c }
- $u\vee$ & $u\sqsupset t$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\textsc{Now try instr. 8, remembering and following the other instructions about closed eyes (instr. 4--7).
-When you have to open your eyes again, as per instr. 4, check anything you forgot: and then go to the
-succeeding instructions. Now---close your eyes.}
-
-\textsc{The next three instructions apply when your eyes are open.}
-
-\item If you see a sight falling toward or about to step on another sight
-whose eyes are open, run until you face the sight on the ground and close
-your eyes.
-
-\textsc{Before you follow this instruction you must have mastered the preceeding instructions about closed eyes.}
-
-$$
-u\wedge\ s_2\wedge(s_1\longdivision{s_2}) u\vee
-$$
-
-(Keep going)
-
-\clearpage
-
-\item If you see a sight about to tackle another whose eyes are open, run
-until you face the sight about to be tackled and jump over both sights. If the
-sight about to be tackled has closed eyes, you must immediately shadow
-them.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c }
- $u\wedge$ & \begin{tabular}{ c c c }
- $s_2\wedge$ & $s_1\overbrace{s_2}$ & $u\overbracket{s_1s_2}$ \\ \midrule
- $s_2\vee$ & $(s_1\overbrace{s_2})$ & $u^\infty s_2$
- \end{tabular} \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\item If you see a sight about to push another with open eyes from
-behind, you must shadow the sight about to be pushed. But if the sight
-about to be pushed has closed eyes, you must immediately jump over both
-sights.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c }
- $u\wedge$ & \begin{tabular}{ c c c }
- $s_2\wedge$ & $(s_1\sqsupset s_2)$ & $u^\infty s_2$ \\ \midrule
- $s_2\vee$ & $(s_1\sqsupset s_2)$ & $u\overbracket{s_1s_2}$ \\
- \end{tabular} \\
-\end{tabular}
-\end{enumerate}
-
-You must now put all the instructions into practice until you have
-learned them thoroughly by doing as they say. In other words, carry out
-Instr. 8, and the other instructions as they apply.
-
-If you can't practice the instructions because you still have not seen a
-sight or felt a touch, skip directly to Page 18.
-
-Learning the instructions in practice should take a good while. When
-you have mastered them, the first phase is over. Turn to Page 10 and begin
-the second phase.
-
-\clearpage
-
-{\centering \textit{Page 10} \par}
-
-\subsection*{Second Phase}
-
-You are now in the second phase of transforming yourself with the
-perception-dissociator. Throughout this phase, you must stoop or crouch
-somewhat. That is, you must keep yourself below the height of your neck
-when you stand straight---except when you jump over a sight. The symbol is
-$u\sfrac{3}{4}$. $u\sfrac{3}{4}\wedge$ means that you crouch and close your eyes. Now crouch.
-
-The numbered instructions for this phase are so similar to those in the
-preceeding phase that they will be given in symbols only. Changes are noted
-parenthetically. You may turn back if you forget symbols.
-
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item \begin{tabular}{ c l }
- \begin{tabular}{ c c }
- $s_1\wedge$ & $s_1\vee$ \\
- $u\sfrac{3}{4}\wedge$ & $(t\longdivision{u})$ \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\lrcorner$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\item \begin{tabular}{ c c c }
- $u\sfrac{3}{4}\wedge$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $s\overbracket{u}$ \\
- $t\overbrace{u}$ \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\lrcorner$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\item \begin{tabular}{ c c c }
- $u\sfrac{3}{4}\wedge$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $t\equiv u$ \\
- $t_2\sqsupset u$ \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\lrcorner$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\emph{(change component blows on you instead of shadowing you)}
-
-\item \begin{tabular}{ c c c }
- $u\sfrac{3}{4}\vee$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $t\overbrace{u}$ \\ \midrule
- $t\sqsupset u$ \\ \midrule
- $u$ inattentive \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\wedge$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\item \begin{tabular}{ c c c }
- $u\sfrac{3}{4}\vee$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $t_1\equiv u$ \\
- $(t_2\longdivision{u})$ \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\lrcorner$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\item \begin{tabular}{ c c c }
- $u\sfrac{3}{4}\vee$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $s^\infty u$ \\
- $(t\overbrace{u})$ \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\lrcorner$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\item \begin{tabular}{ c c c }
- $u\sfrac{3}{4}v$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $t_1\overbracket{u}$ \\
- $(t_2\sqsupset u)$ \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\lrcorner$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\item \begin{tabular}{ c c }
- $u\sfrac{3}{4}\vee$ & $u\sqsupset t$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-The big change comes next.
-
-\emph{(Keep going)}
-
-\clearpage
-
-\item \begin{tabular}{ c c }
- $u\sfrac{3}{4}\wedge s_2\wedge (s_1\longdivision{s_2}) u\vee$ & and also \\
- $u\sfrac{3}{4}\wedge s_2\vee (s_1\longdivision{s_2})$ & $u\equiv s_2$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-That is, if you see a sight falling or stepping on another sight with closed
-eyes, you must immediately blow on the sight on the ground. This is an
-addition.
-
-\item \begin{tabular}{ r c }
- $u\sfrac{3}{4}\wedge$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $s_2\wedge (s_1\overbrace{s_2}) u\overbracket{s_1s_2}$ \\ \midrule
- $s_2\vee (s_1\overbrace{s_2}) u^\infty s_2$ \\
- \end{tabular}
-\end{tabular}
-
-\item \begin{tabular}{ c c }
- $u\sfrac{3}{4}\wedge$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $s_2\wedge (s_1\sqsupset s_2) u\equiv s_2$ \\ \midrule
- $s_2\vee (s_1\sqsupset s_2) u\overbracket{s_1s_2}$ \\
- \end{tabular}
-\end{tabular}
-\emph{(change: you blow on $s_2$)}
-
-So far there have been only three changes in the instructions. Memorize
-them. Then go on to Instr. 12, which is new, and carry it out along with the
-other eleven instructions.
-
-\textsc{As soon as you have put any changed instruction (3, 9, or 11) into practice,
-the second phase is over. Turn to page 12 and the third phase.}
-
-If you can't practice the instructions because all the components have
-vanished, skip to Page 18.
-
-\item Adding to Instruction 8, if you have time left over from following
-other instructions, you may also keep your eyes open and jump over, blow
-on, or shadow sights.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c }
- $u\sfrac{3}{4}\wedge$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $u\overbracket{s}$ \\ \midrule
- $u^\infty s$ \\ \midrule
- $u\equiv s$ \\
- \end{tabular} \\
-\end{tabular}
-\end{enumerate}
-
-\clearpage
-
-\emph{(page 12)}
-
-\subsection*{Third Phase}
-
-Throughout the third phase, you must squat or move on your hands
-and knees. That is, you must always keep yourself below the height of your
-waist when you stand straight---unless you are able to jump over a sight from
-your low position. The symbol is $u\sfrac{1}{2}$. Now get down.
-
-Instr. 1--7 from the last phase apply here without change. They are thus
-stated in the most abbreviated form.
-
-1--3.
-(i will put these in when im confident in my interpretation of the syntax)
-
-4--7.
-(i will put these in when im confident in my interpretation of the syntax)
-
-The biggest change comes next.
-
-8. If you have any time left over, close your eyes and go around with
-your hands in front of you. If you encounter touches standing higher than
-you, tackle them. If you encounter touches as near the ground as you, shove
-them. You must be sensitive and judge heights with eyes closed.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c }
- $u\sfrac{1}{2}\vee$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $t_\greater u\overbrace{t}$ \\ \midrule
- $t_\less u\sqsupset t$ \\
- \end{tabular} \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\emph{($t\greater$ means "if t stands high relative to you" \\
-$t\less$ means "if t is near ground relative to you")}
-
-9. No change.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c }
- $u\sfrac{1}{2}$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $s_2\wedge (s_1\longdivision{s_2}) u\vee$ \\ \midrule
- $s_2\vee (s_1\longdivision{s_2}) u\equiv s_2$ \\
- \end{tabular}
-\end{tabular}
-
-10. The previous Instr. 10 applies if $s_2$ is near the ground, that is, it
-applies unless $s_2$ is too high for you to jump or shadow it.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c }
- $u\sfrac{1}{2}$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $s_2\wedge\less\ (s_1\overbrace{s_2}) u\overbracket{s_1 s_2}$ \\ \midrule
- $s_2\vee\less\ (s_1\overbrace{s_2}) u^\infty s_2$ \\
- \end{tabular}
-\end{tabular}
-
-(Keep going)
-
-\clearpage
-
-11. $u\sfrac{1}{2}\wedge\ s_2\wedge\ (s_1\sqsupset s_2)\ u\equiv s_2$
-
-The second half of the previous Instr. 11 is dropped.
-
-Except for the instruction to tackle touches, the changes are simply
-limitations to make the instructions feasible for $u\sfrac{1}{2}$. They should be easy
-to remember.
-
-You will next go on to Instr. 12, and carry it out along with the other
-instructions. As soon as you encounter an actual situation where you cannot
-act because $u\sfrac{1}{2}$, the third phase will be over.
-\textsc{At that point you must turn to page 14 and the fourth phase.}
-
-If you can't carry out the instructions because all the components have
-vanished, the third phase is over. Turn to Page 14 and the fourth phase.
-
-12. Adding to Instr. 8, if you have time left over, you may also keep
-your eyes open and blow on sights. You may also shadow or jump over
-sights unless they are too high.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c }
- $u\sfrac{1}{2}\wedge$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $u\equiv s$ \\ \midrule
- \begin{tabular}{ r c }
- $s\less$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $u^\infty s$ \\ \midrule
- $u\overbracket{s}$ \\
- \end{tabular}\\
- \end{tabular} \\
- \end{tabular} \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\subsection*{Fourth phase}
-
-You are in the fourth phase of perception-dissociation. Throughout this
-phase, you must crawl on your stomach (keep below knee height). The
-symbol is $u\sfrac{1}{4}$. Now get on the floor.
-
-You can no longer be tackled, nor can you jump. Thus, the numbered
-instructions are greatly limited, and they will be restated fully.
-
-\textsc{The first two instructions apply when your eyes are open.}
-
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item If you see a sight close its eyes, a touch may be falling or stepping
-on you, and you must immediately scramble aside.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ c l }
- \begin{tabular}{ c c }
- $s_1\wedge$ & $s_1\vee$ \\
- $u\sfrac{1}{4}\wedge$ & $(t\longdivision{u})$ \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\lrcorner$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\item \begin{tabular}{ r c l }
- $u\sfrac{1}{4}\wedge$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $t_1\equiv u$ \\
- $(t_2\sqsupset u)$ \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\lrcorner$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\textsc{The next three instructions tell you what to do when your eyes are closed.}
-
-\item When to reopen your eyes.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c l }
- $u\sfrac{1}{4}\vee$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $t\sqsupset u$ \\ \midrule
- $u$ inattentive \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\wedge$
-\end{tabular}
-
-\item If your closed eyes are shadowed, a touch may be falling or
-stepping on you. Scramble aside.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c l }
- $u\frac{1}{4}\vee$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $s^\infty u$ \\
- $(t\longdivision{u}$
- \end{tabular} & $u\lrcorner$
-\end{tabular}
-
-\item \begin{tabular}{ c c c }
- $u\frac{1}{4}\vee$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $t_1\overbracket{u}$ \\
- $(t_2\sqsupset u)$ \\
- \end{tabular} & $u\lrcorner$ \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-\item \begin{tabular}{ r c }
- $u\sfrac{1}{4}\vee$ \begin{tabular}{ c c }
- $t\greater$ & $u\overbrace{t}$ \\ \midrule
- $t\sfrac{1}{4}$ & $u\sqsupset t$ \\
- \end{tabular}
-\end{tabular}
-
-\textsc{Try instr. 6, remembering and following instr. 3--5.} \\
-\textsc{When you have to reopen your eyes as per instr. 3, check on anything you forgot.
- Then go to page 15. Now---close your eyes.}
-
-
-The rest of the instructions apply when your eyes are open.
-
-\item \begin{tabular}{ r c }
- $u\sfrac{1}{4}\wedge$ & \begin{tabular}{ c c c }
- $s_2\wedge$ & $(s_1\longdivision{s_2})$ & $u\vee$ \\ \midrule
- $s_2\vee\less$ & $(s_1\longdivision{s_2})$ & $u^\infty s_2$ \\
- \end{tabular} \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-If $s_2$'s eyes are closed, you must shadow them unless they are too high.
-
-\item $$u\sfrac{1}{4}\wedge\ s\wedge\less\ (s_1\sqsupset s_2)\ u\equiv s_2$$
-
-You blow on $s_2$'s hand unless it is too high.
-
-\item Adding to Instr. 6, if you have time left over from following
-instructions, you may also shadow or blow on sights if they aren't too high.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ c c c }
- $u\sfrac{1}{4}\wedge$ & $s\less$ & \begin{tabular}{ c }
- $u^\infty s$ \\ \midrule
- $u\equiv s$ \\
- \end{tabular} \\
-\end{tabular}
-\end{enumerate}
-
-You must now put these nine instructions into practice until you have
-learned them thoroughly in practice; and even continue after that until you
-have difficulty keeping your mind on the exhibit.
-
-\textsc{If you can't practice the instructions because all the components have vanished, skip to page 18.}
-
-Otherwise, stay with this phase until you have difficulty keeping your
-mind on it. Then turn to Page 16 and the final phase of
-perception-dissociation.
-
-\clearpage
-
-\subsection*{Final Phase}
-\emph{(Page Sixteen)}
-
-You are now in the final phase of transforming yourself with the
-perception-dissociator. When you finish transforming yourself, you will have
-lost track of time, and will have ceased to notice sound. You will be dealing
-with sights and touches as unrelated phenomena; and you will be responding
-by reflex action to unconscious signals from "other people."
-
-For this last phase, you will turn to Page 5. You will go through the
-symbols there in any order you like as if they were one long instruction,
-carrying out that instruction. You are to "use" each symbol once. There
-have been enough precedents in the interpretation of the symbols that you
-should now be able to interpret any combination of them. Continue to
-follow the previous numbered instructions as they apply, depending on
-whether you are 1, \sfrac{3}{4}, \sfrac{1}{2}, or \sfrac{1}{4}.
-(But forget the instructions for time left
-over; you won't have any extra time.)
-\textsc{Remember the instructions about when to reopen your eyes if you close them.}
-
-When you are through, you will be transformed.
-\textsc{Now turn to page 5 and begin.}
-
-\clearpage
-
-If you have found these words and are reading them in desperation
-because you are completely confused; or because you have lost interest in
-the exhibit; or because you have finished; then you are transformed.
-
-
-If you want to use the model to simulate the reversal of your
-transformation before you leave the exhibit, do the following. Spend 50
-seconds erect, with open eyes, walking up to sights and pushing
-them---assuming that you will find touches where you see sights. Count the
-seconds "one-thousand-and-one," "one-thousand-and-two," etc.
-
-
-Then you will close your eyes. If you are blown on or pushed before
-250 seconds have passed, you will open your eyes and--assuming that you
-will find a sight where you were touched--you wil! shadow it. Otherwise you
-will open your eyes when the 250 seconds have passed. Now close your eyes
-and do as instructed.
-
-
-It is now suggested that you leave the exhibit. Go out through the
-curtain.
-
-\clearpage
-
-Stay in the exhibit and follow every instruction that is relevant, until
-you become thirsty.
-
-
-If you begin to encounter components, return to the page you were on
-before you turned to this one.
-
-
-lf you still don't encounter components, the model must be broken.
-Leave the exhibit by the same passage through which you entered.
-
-\clearpage
-
-
-2/22/1963
-
-
-Henry Flynt and Tony Conrad demonstrate against the Metropolitan Museum of Art,
-February 22, 1963
-
-
-(foto by Jack Smith)
-
-\chapter{Mock Risk Games}
-
-
-Suppose you stand in front of a swinging door with a nail sticking out of it
-pointing at your face; and suppose you are prepared to jump back if the
-door suddenly opens in your face. You are deliberately taking a risk on the
-assumption that you can protect yourself. Let us call such a situation a "risk
-game." Then a mock risk game is a risk game such that the misfortune which
-you risk is contrary to the course of nature, a freak misfortune; and thus
-your preparation to evade it is correspondingly superficial.
-
-If the direction of gravity reverses and you fall on the ceiling, that is a
-freak misfortune. If you don't want to risk this misfortune, then you will
-anchor yourself to the floor in some way. But if you stand free so that you
-can fall, and yet try to prepare so that if you do fall, you will fall in such a
-way that you won't be hurt, then that is a mock risk game. if technicians
-could actually effect or simulate gravity reversal in the room, then the risk
-game would be a real one. But I am not concerned with real risk games. I am
-interested in dealing with gravity reversal in an everyday environment, where
-everything tells you it can't possibly happen. Your 'preparation' for the fall
-is thus superficial, because you still have the involuntary conviction that it
-can't possibly happen.
-
-Mock risk games constitute a new area of human behavior, because they
-aren't something people have done before, you don't know what they will be
-like until you try them, and it took a very special effort to devise them.
-They have a tremendous advantage over other activities of comparable
-significance, because they can be produced in the privacy of your own room
-without special equipment. Let us explore this new psychological effect; and
-let us not ask what use it has until we are more familiar with it.
-
-Instructions for a variety of mock risk games follow. (I have played
-each game many times in developing it, to ensure that the experience of
-playing it will be compelling.) For each game, there is a physical action to be
-performed in a physical setting. Then there is a list of freak misfortunes
-which you risk by performing the action, and which you must be prepared
-to evade. The point is not to hallucinate the misfortunes, or even to fear
-them, but rather to be prepared to evade them. First you work with each
-misfortune separately. For example, you walk across a room, prepared to
-react self-protectingly if you are suddenly upside down, resting on the top of
-your head on the floor. In preparing for this risk, you should clear the path
-of objects that might hurt you if you fell on them; you should wear clothes
-suitable for falling; and you should try standing on your head, taking your
-hands off the floor and falling, to get a feeling for how to fail without
-getting hurt. After you have mastered the preparation for each misfortune
-separately, you perform the action prepared to evade the first misfortune
-and the second (but not both at once). You must prepare to determine
-instantly which of the two misfortunes befalls you, and to react
-appropriately. After you have mastered pairs of misfortunes, you go on to
-triples of misfortunes, and so forth.
-
-The principal games are for a large room with no animals or distracting
-sounds present.
-
-\textbf{A.}Walk across the lighted room from one corner to the diagonally
-opposite one, breathing normally, with your eyes open.
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item You are suddenly upside down, resting on the top of your head on the
-floor. You must get down without breaking your neck.
-
-\item Although the floor looks unbroken and solid, beyond a certain point
-nothing is there. If you step onto that area, you will take a fatal fall. Thus, as
-you walk, you must not shift your weight to your forward foot until you are
-sure it will hold. Put the ball of the forward foot down before the heel.
-
-\item Something happens to the cohesive forces in your neck so that if your
-head tips in any direction, it will come right off your body, killing you
-immediately. Otherwise everything remains normal. Thus, as you walk, you
-must "balance" your head on your neck. When you reach the other side of
-the room, your neck will be restored to normal. (Prepare beforehand by
-walking with a book balanced on your head.)
-
-\item Invisible conical weights fall around you with their points down, each
-whistling as it falls. You must evade them by ear in order not to be stabbed.
-Walk softly and fast.
-
-\item The room is suddenly filled with water. You have to contro! your lungs
-and swim to the top. Wear clothes suitable for swimming.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-\textbf{A'.} Play game A while on a long walk on an uncrowded street. The floor
-is replaced by the sidewalk. The fifth misfortune becomes for space suddenly
-to be filled with water to a height of fifteen feet above the street.
-
-\textbf{B.} Lie on your back on a pallet in the dimly lit room, hands at your
-sides, with a pillow on your face so that it is slightly difficult to breathe, for
-thirty seconds at a time.
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item The pillow suddenly hardens and becomes hundreds of pounds heavier. !t
-remains suspended on your face for a split second and then "falls," bears
-down with full weight. You must jerk your head out from under it in that
-split second.
-
-\item The pillow adheres to your skin with a force greater than your skin's
-cohesion, and begins to rise. You must rise with it in such a way that your
-skin is not torn.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-\textbf{C.} Lie on your back on the pallet in the dimly lit room.
-
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item Gravity suddenly disappears completely, so that nothing is held down by
-it; and the ceiling becomes red-hot. You must avoid drifting up against the
-ceiling.
-
-\item The surface you are lying on becomes a vast lighted open plane. From the
-distance, giant steel spheres come rolling in your direction. You must evade
-them.
-
-\item Your body is split in half just above the waist by an indefinitely long,
-rather high, foot-thick wall. Your legs and lower torso are on one side, and
-your upper torso, arms, and head are on the other side. Matter normally
-exchanged between the two halves of your body continues to be exchanged
-through the. wall by telekinesis. It is as if you are a foot longer above the
-waist. In order to reunite your body, you must first roll over and get up,
-bent way forward. There are depressions in the wall on the same side as your
-feet. You have to climb the wall, putting your feet in the depressions and
-balancing yourself. You will be reunited when you reach the top and your
-waist passes above the wall.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-\textbf{D.} Sit in a plain, small, straight chair, on the edge of the seat, hands
-hanging at the sides of the seat, feet together in front of the chair, in the
-lighted room, for about thirty seconds at a time.
-
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item The chair is suddenly out from under you and sitting on you with Its legs
-straddling your lap and legs. You have to get your weight over your feet so
-you won't take a hard fall.
-
-\item The direction of gravity reverses and the chair remains anchored to the
-floor. You have to grab the seat and hold on in order not to fall on the
-ceiling.
-
-\item You are suddenly in a contra-terrene universe, in which the atmosphere is
-unbreathable and prolonged contact with either the atmosphere or the
-ground will disintegrate you. The seat and back of the chair become a
-penetrable hyperspatial sheet between the alien universe and your own. As
-soon as you feel the alien atmosphere, you must jerk your feet off the
-ground and deliberately sink or p!unge through the seat and back of the chair
-in the best way that you can. You will end up on the floor under the chair in
-your universe.
-
-\item You are suddenly in dark empty space in a three-dimensional lattice of
-gleaming wires. Segments of the lattice alternately burst into flame and cool
-off. You adhere to the chair as if it were part of you. With your hands
-holding onto the seat, you can move yourself and the chair forward by
-
-\end{enumerate}
-
-\plainbreak{2}
-
-\textbf{[NOTE: TWO PAGES MISSING HERE IN SCAN]}
-
-\plainbreak{2}
-
-from blundering into a radiation beam, you have to communicate
-pre-verbally to the other mind by every means from vocal cries to
-pantomine, and get your-body/his-mind out of range of the radiation. When
-the body is out, you will both be restored to normal. (The first thing to
-anticipate is the basic shift in viewpoint by which you will be looking at
-your own body from the other's position. There is no point in tensing your
-muscles in preparatiton for the misfortune, because if it occurs, you will be
-working with a strange set of muscles anyway. The next thing to prepare to
-do is to spot the radiation beams; and then to yell, gesture, or
-whatever--anything to get the "other" to avoid the radiation. Note finally
-that neither player prepares for the possibility that he will be surrounded by
-radiation. Each player prepares for the same role in an asymmetrical pas de
-deux.)
-
-\emph{Asymmetry:} The two of you play a given duo game, but each prepares
-to evade a different misfortune.
-
-\textbf{AB.} Stay awake with eyes closed for an agreed upon time between one
-and fifteen minutes. Use a timer with an alarm.
-
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item Each suddenly has the other's entire present consciousness in addition to
-his own, from perceptions to memories, ideologies, ambitions, and
-everything else---threatening both with psychological shock.
-
-The couple must take up positions such that their sensory perceptions
-are as nearly identical as possible. Beforehand, each must discuss with the
-other the aspects of the other's attitude to the world which each must fears
-having impused on his consciousness. During the game, each must think
-about these aspects and try to prepare for them.
-
-\item Each suddenly relives the other's most intense past feelings of depression
-and suicidal impulses. In other words, if five years ago the other attempted
-suicide because he failed out of college, you suddenly have the consciousness
-that "you" have just failed out of college, are totally worthless, and should
-destroy yourself. Presumably the other has since learned to live with his past
-disasters, but you do not have the defenses he has built up. You are
-overwhelmed with a despair which the other felt in the past, and which is
-incongruous with the rest of your consciousness. In summary, both of you
-risk shock and suicidal impulses. Beforehand, of course, each must tell the
-other of his worst past suicidal or depressed episode; and discuss anything
-else that may minimize the risk of shock.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-\section*{Intrusions in Duo Games}
-
-As before, distractions and modulations can be openly studied by
-consent of the players. As for bogies, it is possible in duo games for one
-player to create a bogy without warning, in effect acting as a saboteur. As
-soon as a game is sabotaged, though, confidence is lost, and each player just
-watches out for the other's bogies. Here are some sample intrusions.
-
-\begin{tabular}{ r c c c }
- \textsc{Game} & \textsc{Distraction} & \textsc{Bogy} & \textsc{Modulation} \\
- AA 1. & cough & shout in other's face & each take a different drug \\
- 2. & talk and laugh \linebreak get out of step & $\rightarrow$ \linebreak (stomp hard) & \\
- 3. & spin around & $\rightarrow$ & \\
- AB 1. & cough \linebreak talk and laugh & gasp \linebreak silently pass palm back \& forth in front of other's face & \\
- 2. & & & \\
-\end{tabular}
-
-
-\chapter{The Dream Reality}
-
-
-\section{Memo on the Dream Project}
-
-
-Original aim: To recreate the effect of e.g. Pran Nath's singing---transcendent
-inner escape---in direct life rather than art. I needed material which could
-function as an alien civilization (since the source of Pran Nath's expression is
-an alien civilization relative to me); yet which was encultured in me and not
-an affectation or pretense. I decided to use dreams as the material, assuming
-that my dreams would take me to alien worlds. But mostly they did not.
-Mostly my dreams consist of long periods of tawdry, familiar life interrupted
-occasionally by senseless, unmotivated anomalies. In contrast, my original
-aim required alluring, psychically gratifying material.
-
-The emphasis shifted to redefining reality so that dreams were on the same
-level as waking life; so that they were apprehended as what they seem to be:
-literal reality (and not memory, precognition, or symbolism). The project
-was still arcane, but in a drastically different way. I was getting into an
-alternate reality which was extremely bizarre but not psychically gratifying.
-It was boringly frightful and sometimes obscene. I became concerned with
-analytical study of the natural order of the dream world, a para-scientific
-investigation. As I grappled with the rational arguments against treating
-dreams as literal reality, the project became a difficult analytical exercise in
-the philosophy of science. The original sensuous-esthetic purpose was lost.
-
-Now I would like to return to the original aim, but how to do it? Obtain
-other people's dreams---see if they are more suitable? Work only with my
-very rare dreams which do take me to alien worlds? Try to alter the content
-of my raw dreams? Attempt to affect content of dreams by experiment in
-which many people sleep in same room and try to communicate in their
-sleep? The most uncertain approach to a solution: set up a transformation
-on my banal dreams, so that to the first-order activity of raw dreaming is
-added a second-order activity. The transformation procedure to somehow
-combine conscious ideational direction---coding of the banal dreams---with
-alteration of my experience, my esthesia, my lived experience.
-
-
-\section{Dreams and Reality---An Experimental Essay}
-
-Excerpts from my dream diary which are referred-to in the essay that
-follows.
-
-\dreamdate{12/11/1973}
-
-I notice a state between waking and dreaming: a waking dream. I have
-been asleep; I wake up; I close my eyes to sleep again. While not yet asleep, I
-experience isolated objects before me as in a dream, but with no
-background, only a dark void. !n this case, there are two pocket combs, both
-with teeth broken. In the waking world, I threw away one of my two pocket
-combs because I broke it; the other comb is still in good condition.
-
-\dreamdate{12/30/1973}
-
-I am chased by the police for one block west on West Market Street in
-Greensboro. I reach the intersection with Eugene Street, and in the north
-direction there is a steep hill rather than the street. The surface of the hill is
-bare ground and grass. I run up the hill, sensing that if I can get over the hill
-I will find Friendly Road and the general neighborhood of my mother's
-houses on the other side. The police start shooting. If I can get a few yards
-farther on the top of the hill I will be past the line of fire. I take a headlong
-dive and awaken in the middle of the dive to find myself diving forward on
-my mattress in the front room of my apartment. The action is carried on
-continuously through waking up and through the associated change of
-setting.
-
-
-\dreamdate{1/12/1974}
-
-Just before I go to sleep for the night, I am lying in bed drowsy. I think
-of being, and suddenly am, at the south edge of the Courant Institute plaza,
-which is several feet above the sidewalk. The edge of the plaza and the drop
-are all I see. It is night; and there is only a void where the peripheral
-environment should be. (Comment: It is of great theoretical importance that
-while most of the internal reality cues were present in this experience, some,
-like the peripheral environment, were not. In my dream experiences, all
-reality cues are present.) The drop expands to twenty or thirty feet, and I
-start to fall off. Fright jolts me completely awake. I have had something like
-a waking nightmare and have awakened from being awake. I thought of the
-scene, was suddenly in it (except for peripheral reality cues), lost control and
-became endangered by it, and then snapped back to my bedroom.
-
-\dreamdate{1/1-/1974}
-
-One or two nights after 1/12/74 I was lying in bed just before going to
-sleep. I could see women standing on a sidewalk. The scene was real, but I
-was not in it; I was a disembodied spectator. Also, the peripheral
-environment was absent. The reality was between that of a waking
-visualization and that of the Courant Institute incident of 1/12/74.
-Comment: The differences between this experience and a waking
-visualization are that the latter is less vivid than seeing and is accompanied
-by waking reality cues such as cues of bodily location.
-
-
-\dreamdate{1/16/1974}
-
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item I am in an apartment vaguely like the first place in which I lived, at
-1025 Madison Avenue in Greensboro. I am a spy. I am teen-aged and short;
-and I am in the apartment with several enemy men, who are middle-aged and
-adult-sized. My code sheets look like the sheets of Yiddish I have been
-copying out in waking life. Eventually the men discover me in the front
-room with the code sheets on a fold-up desk. They chase me out the front
-door and onto the west side of the lawn, and shoot me with a needle gun. At
-that moment my consciousness jumps from my body and becomes that of a
-disembodied spectator watching from an eastward location, as if I were
-watching a film.
-
-\item I am living in a dormitory in a rural setting with other males. At one
-point I walking barefoot in weeds outside the dormitory, and Supt. Toro
-tells me I am walking in poison ivy. My feet begin to show the rash, but I
-recognize that I am in a dream and think that the rash will not carry over to
-the waking state. I then begin to will away the rash in the dream, and I
-succeed,
-\end{enumerate}
-
-
-\dreamdate{1/20/1974}
-
-For some reason the dream associates Simone Forti with flute-like
-music. It is shortly before midnight. In the dream I believe that Simone lives
-in a loft on the east side of Wooster Street. The blocks in SOHO are very
-small. If I walk through the streets and whistle, she will hear me. I start to
-whistle but can only whistle a single high note. I half awaken but continue
-whistling, or trying to; the dream action continues into waking. But I cannot
-change pitch or whistle clearly because my mouth is taped. As I realize this, I
-awaken fully.
-
-Comments: I tape my mouth at night so I will sleep with my mouth closed. I
-experimented at trying to whistle with the tape on while fully awake. The
-breath just hisses against the tape. The pitch of the hiss can be varied.
-
-
-\dreamdate{2/1/1974}
-
-1. I try to assist a man in counterfeiting ten dollar bills by taking half
-of a ten, scotch taping it to half of a one, and then coloring over the one
-until it looks like the other half of the ten. The method fails because I bring
-old crumpled tens rather than new tens, and the one doilar bills are new.
-
-
-Comments: There are no natural anomalies in this dream at all. What is
-anomalous is that this counterfeiting method seems perfectly sensible, and I
-only begin to question it when we try to fit the crumpled half-bill to the
-crisp half-bill. Why am I so foolish in this dream? I retain my identity as
-Henry Flynt, and yet my outlook, my sense of what is rational, is so
-different that it is that of a different person. More generally, the person I am
-in my dreams is much more limited in certain ways that I am in waking life.
-My waking preoccupations are totally absent from my dreams. Instead there
-is bland material about my early life which could apply to any child or
-teen-ager. Thus, I must warn readers who know me only from this diary not
-to try to make the image of me here fit my waking life.
-
-
-\dreamdate{2/3/1974}
-
-3. I have had several dreams that I am taking the last courses of my
-student career. (In waking life I have completed all course work.) I am
-usually failing them. Tonight I dream that I have gone all semester without
-studying (in a course in English?). Now I am in the final exam and sinking. I
-will have to repeat these courses. Subsequently, I am sitting in a school
-office (of a professor or psychologist?), giving him a long list (of words, a
-foreign vocabulary?). (I mention this episode because I remember that while
-I retained my nominal identity as Henry Flynt, I had the mind of a different
-person. I experienced another person's existence instead of mine. Professor
-Nell also appeared somewhere in this dream; as he has in several school
-dreams I have had recently.
-
-
-\dreamdatecomment{2/3/1974}{This is the date I recorded, but it seems that it would have to be later.}
-
-I get up in the morning and decide to have a self-indulgent breakfast
-because of the unpleasantness of working on my income tax the day before.
-So I put two slices of pizza in the oven, and also eat two bakery sweets,
-possibly \'{e}clairs. Then I think that a Mexican TV dinner would have been
-better all around, but it is too late; I have to eat what I am already preparing.
-Subsequently, I go with John Alten to a Shoreham Cafeteria at Houston and
-Mercer Streets. The cafeteria chain is a good one, but this cafeteria is dark
-and extremely dingy upstairs where the serving line is. John complains that
-there is no ventilation and that he is suffocating, and he stalks out.
-
-Comment: When I awoke, my first thought was that the pizza in the oven
-would be burning. (I assumed that I had arisen, put the pizza in the oven,
-and gone back to sleep.) But then I realized that the breakfast was a dream. I
-got up and prepared the Mexican dinner which I had decided was best in the
-dream, but I also ate one \'{e}clair.
-
-\dreamdate{7/8/1974}
-
-I am caught out in a theft of money, and I feel that the rest of my life
-will be ruined.
-
-Comment: The quality of the episode depended on my
-strong belief in the reality of the social future and in my ability to form
-accurate expectations about it. When I awakened, the whole misadventure
-vanished.
-
-
-End of excerpts from my dream diary.
-
-\begin{quotation}
-"... It is correct to say that the objective world is a synthesis of private views
-or perceptions... But ... inasmuch as it is the common objective world that
-renders ... general knowledge possible, it will be this world that the scientist
-will identify with the world of reality. Henceforth the private views, though
-just as real, will be treated as its perspectives. ... the common objective
-world, whether such a thing exists or is a mere convenient fiction, is
-indispensable to science ...
-."\footnote{A. d'Abro, The Evolution of Scientific Thought (New York, Dover, 1950), pp. 176--7}
-\end{quotation}
-
-
-\textbf{A.} We wish to postulate that dreams are exactly what they seem to be
-while we are dreaming, namely, literal reality. Naively, we want to get closer
-to literal empiricism than natural science is. But science has worked out a
-very comfortable world-view on the assumption that both dreams and
-semi-conscious quasi-dreams are mere subjective phenomena of individual
-consciousness. If we wish to carry through the postulate that dreams are
-literal reality, then we will have to adopt a cognitive model quite different
-from that of natural science. It is of crucial importance that we are not
-interested in superstition. We do not wish to adopt a cognitive model which
-would simply be defeated in competition with science. We wish to be at least
-as rational, as empirical, and as cognitively parsimonious as science is. We
-want our cognitive model to be compelling, and not to be a plaything which
-is easily taken up and easily discarded.
-
-The question is whether there can be a rational empiricism which
-differs from science in placing dreamed episodes on the same level as waking
-episodes, but which stops short of the "nihilistic empiricism" of my
-philosophical essay entitled \essaytitle{The Flaws Underlying Beliefs}. (In effect, the
-latter essay rejects other minds, causality, persistent objective entities, past
-time, the possibility of objective categories and significant language, and so
-forth, ending up with ungraded immediate experience.)
-
-As an example of our problem, the waking scientific outlook assumes
-that a typewriter continues to exist even when we turn our backs on it
-(persistence of objective entities). In many of our dreams we make the same
-sort of assumption. In other words, in some of our dreams the natural order
-is not noticeably different from that of the waking world; and in many
-dreams our conscious world-view has much in common with waking
-common sense or scientific pragmatism. On 2/3/1974 I had a dream in which
-a typewriter was featured. I certainly assumed that the typewriter continued
-to exist when my back was turned to it. On 7/8/1974 I dreamed that I was
-caught out in a theft of money, and I felt my life would be ruined because of
-it. I certainly assumed the reality of the social future, and my ability to form
-accurate expectations about it. These examples illustrate that we are not
-nihilistic empiricists in our dreams. The question is whether acceptance of
-the pragmatic outlook which we have in dreams is consistent with not
-regarding the dream-world as a subjective phenomenon of individual
-consciousness. Can we accept dreams as "literal reality"; or must we reject
-the very concept of "reality" on order to defend the placing of the dream
-world on the same level as the waking world?
-
-In summary, the question is whether we can place dreams on the same
-fevel as the waking world while stopping short of nihilistic empiricism. A
-further difficulty in accomplishing this aim is that neurological science might
-succeed in gaining complete experimental control of dreams. Scientists might
-become able to produce dreams at will and to monitor them. The whole
-phenomenon of dreaming would then tend to be totally assimilated to the
-outlook of scientists. Their decision to treat dreams as subjective phenomena
-of individual consciousness would be greatly supported by these
-developments. Would we have to go all the way to nihilistic empiricism in
-order to have a basis for rejecting the neurologists' accomplishments?
-
-Still another difficulty is presented for us by semi-conscious
-quasi-dreams such as the ones described in my diary. Semi-conscious
-quasi-dreams exhibit some reality cues, but lack other important internal
-reality cues. Science handles these experiences easily, by dismissing them
-along with dreams as subjective phenomena of individual consciousness.
-Suppose we accept that the semi-conscious quasi-dreams are illusory reality.
-But if they can be illusory reality, how can we exclude the possibility that
-dreams might be also? If, on the other hand, we accept the quasi-dreams as
-literal reality, what about the missing reality cues? Can we justify different
-treatment for dreams and quasi-dreams by saying that all reality cues have to
-be present before an experience is accepted as non-illusory? If we propose
-to do so, the question then becomes whether we should accept the weight
-which common sense places on reality cues.
-
-Why do we wish to stop short of nihilistic empiricism? Because we do
-wish to assert that dreams can be remembered; that they can be described in
-permanent records; that they can be compared and studied rationally. We do
-want to cite the past as evidence; we do want to distinguish between actual
-dream experience and waking fabrications, waking lies about what we have
-dreamed; and we do want to describe what we experience in intersubjective
-language.
-
-As easy way out which would offend nobody would be to treat dreams
-as simulations of alternate universes. But this approach is a cowardly evasion
-for several reasons. It excludes the phenomenon of the semi-conscious
-quasi-dream, which poses the problem of internal reality cues in the sharpest
-way. Further, we cannot give up the notion that our project is nearer to
-literal empiricism than natural science is. We cannot accept the notion that
-we must dismiss some of our experiences as mere illusions, but not all of
-them. We do not see dreams as simulations of anything. Some of the most
-interesting observations I have made about connections between adjacent
-dreamed and waking episodes in my own experience are noticeable only
-because I take both dreamed and waking experience literally.
-
-\gap
-
-
-\textbf{B.} Before we continue our attempt to resolve our methodological
-problem, we will provide more detail on topics which we have mentioned in
-passing. We begin with the purported empiricism of natural science. The
-philosopher Hume postulated that experience was the only raw material of
-reality or cognition. However, he did not content himself with ungraded
-experience. He insisted on draping the experiential raw material on an
-intellectual framework in such a way that experience was used to simulate
-the inherited conception of. reality, a conception which we will call
-Aristotelian realism. Similarly for the purported empiricism of natural
-science. In fact, the working scientist learns to think of the framework or
-model as primary, and of experiences and verification procedures as ancillary
-to it. The quotation by d'Abro which heads this essay concedes as much.
-
-What we are investigating is whether experiences can be draped on a
-different intellectual framework in which dreamed and waking life come out
-as equally real. Some examples of alternate verification conventions follow.
-
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item Accept intersubjective confirmation of my experience of the dream world
-which occurs within the dream as confirmation of the reality of the dream
-world.
-
-\item Accept intersubjective confirmation of the past of the dream world which
-occurs in the dream itself as confirmation of the reality of the dreamed past.
-
-\item Recognize that there is no infallible way to tell whether other people are
-lying about their dreamed experience or their waking experience.
-
-\item Develop sophisticated interrogation techniques as a limited test of
-whether people are telling the truth about their dreams.
-
-\item Accept that a certain category of anomalies occurs in dreams only when
-several people have reported experiences in that category.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-The principal characteristic of the approach which these conventions
-represent is that each dream is treated as a separate world. There is no
-attempt to arrive at an account, for a given "objective" time period, which is
-consistent with more than one dream or with both dreamed and waking
-periods. Thus, many parallel worlds could be confirmed as real. As our
-discussion proceeds, we will move away from this approach, probably out of
-a sense that it is pointless to maintain a strong notion of reality and yet to
-forego the notion of the consistency of all portions of reality.
-
-\textbf{C.} Something that I have learned from a study of my dream records is
-that while dreams are not chaotic, while they can be compared and
-classified, it is not possibie to apply the method of natural science to them in
-the sense of discerning a consistent, impersonal natural order in the dream
-world. It is not that the natural order is different in dreams from what it is in
-the waking world; it is that the dream worlds are incommensurate with the
-discernment of a natural order in the scientific sense. Here are some specific
-observations which relate to this whole question.
-
-\begin{enumerate}
- \item Some dreams are not noticeably anomalous. The laws of science are not
-violated in them. This observation is important in giving us a normal base for
-our investigation. Dreams are not all crazy and chaotic.
-
-\item In some dreams, it is impossible to abstract an impersonal natural order
-from personal experiences and anecdotes. There are no impersonal events.
-There is no nature whose order can be defined impersonally. The dreams are
-full of personal magic which cannot be generalized to a characteristic of an
-impersonal natural order.
-
-\item As a special case of (2), in some dreams, we jump back in time and move
-discontinuously in time and space. Chronological personal magic.
-
-\item In dreams, the distinction between myself and other people is blurred in
-many different ways. Also, I sometimes become a disembodied
-consciousness.
-
-\item As a generalization of (4), sometimes it becomes impossible to distinguish
-objects from our sensing and perceiving function. The mediating sensory
-function becomes obtrusively anomalous. Stable object gestalts cannot be
-identified.
-
-\item Sometimes we experience the logically impossible in dreams. My father
-was both dead and buried, and alive and walking around, in one dream.
-
-\item The possibility of identifying causal relationships is sometimes lacking in
-dreams. It is not just that actions have unexpected effects. It is that events
-are strung together like beads on a string. There is no sense of willful acting
-on the world or manipulation of the world which can be objectified as a
-causal relation between impersonal events.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-The possibility arises of using dreams as philosophical experiments in
-worlds in which one or more of the preconditions for application of the
-scientific method is absent. (But in the one case in which Alten and I tried
-this, we reached opposite conclusions. Alten said that dreams in which one
-can jump around in time proved that the irreversibility of time is the basis
-for distinguishing between time and space; I said that the dreams proved that
-time and space can be distinguished even when the irreversibility of time is
-lacking.)
-
-Observation (2) above can lead us to an insight about the waking world.
-Perhaps science insists on the elimination of personal anecdotes from the
-natural order which it recognizes because the scientist wants results which
-can be transferred from one life to another and which will give one person
-power over another. At any rate, science excludes anecdotal anomalies which
-cannot be made somehow into "objective" events. As an example, I may be
-walking down the street and suddenly find myself on the other side of the
-street with no awareness of any act of crossing the street.
-
-What dreams provide us with is worlds in which anecdotal anomalies
-cannot be relegated to limbo as they are in waking science. They are so
-prominent in dreams that we can become accustomed to identifying them
-there. We may then learn to recognize analogous anomalies in the waking
-world, where we had overlooked them before because of our scientific
-indoctrination.
-
-Of course, we run the risk that superstitious people will misuse our
-theory to justify their folly. But the difference between our theory and
-superstition is clear. When the superstitious person says that he
-communicates with spirits, he either lies outright; or alse he misinterprets his
-experiences---embedding them in an extraneous pre-scientific belief system,
-or treating them as controversions of scientific propositions. We, on the
-other hand, maintain more literally than science does that the only raw
-material of cognition is experience. We differ from science in draping
-experiences on a different organizational framework. The "reality" we arrive
-at is incommensurate with science; it does not falsify any scientific
-proposition. As for science and superstition, we headed this essay with the
-quotation by d'Abro to emphasize that the scientist himself is superstitious:
-he is determined to believe in the common objective world, even though it is
-a fiction, because it is necessary to science. The superstitious person wants
-you to believe that his communication with spirits is intersubjectively
-consequential. Thus our theory, which tends toward the attitude that
-nothing is intersubjectively consequential, offers him even less comfort than
-science does.
-
-\textbf{D.} We next turn to semi-conscious quasi-dreams. Referring to my
-experience on the morning of 1/12/1974, I describe the experience by saying
-that I was on the Courant Institute plaza. But I cannot conclude that I was
-on the Courant Institute plaza. The reason is that important internal reality
-cues are missing in the experience. For one thing, the peripheral environment
-is missing; in its place is a void. Referring to my experience on 1/1-/1974,
-still other cues are missing. I am awake, and the scene is unstable and
-momentary. The slightest attention shift will cause the scene to vanish.
-
-When we recognize that we have disallowed falling asleep, awaking, and
-anomalous phenomena in dreams as evidence of unreality, a careful analysis
-yields only two types of reality cues.
-
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item Presence of the peripheral environment.
-
-\item "Single consciousness." This cue is missing when we see a
-three-dimensional scene and move about in it, and yet have a background
-awareness that we are awake in bed; and lose the scene through a mere shift
-of attention. Its absence is even more marked if the scene is a momentary
-one between two waking periods.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-Let us recall our earlier discussion of the empiricism of science. Science
-does not content itself with ungraded experience. it drapes experience on an
-intellectual framework in such a way as to simulate Aristotelian realism. It
-feeds experience into a maze of verification procedures in order to confirm a
-model which is not explicit in ungraded experience. It short, science grades
-experience as to its reality on the basis of standards which are
-"intellectually" supplied. Internal reality cues are thus characteristics of
-experience which are given special weight by the grading procedure. The
-immediate problem for us is that ordinary descriptive language implicitly
-recognizes these reality cues; one would never say without qualification that
-one was on the Courant Institute plaza if the peripheral environment was
-missing and if one was also aware of being awake in bed at the time. (In
-contrast, it is fair to use ordinary descriptive language with respect to
-dreamed episodes when our consciousness is singulary, that is, when
-everything seems real and unqualified.)
-
-For purposes of further comparison I may mention an experience I
-have had on rare occasions while lying on my back in bed fully awake. It is
-as if colored spheres whose centers are located a few feet or yards in front of
-my chest expand until they press against me, one after the other. I use the
-phrase "as if" because reality cues are missing in this experience, and thus I
-cannot use the language of stable object gestalts without qualification in
-describing it. The colors are not vivid as real colors are. They are like
-visualized colors. The spheres pass through each other, and through me---with
-only a moderate sensation of pressure. I can turn the experience off by
-getting out of bed. The point, again, is that it is inherent in ordinary
-language not to use unqualified object descriptions in these circumstances.
-Yet the only language I have for such sensory configurations is the language
-of stable object gestalts-this is particularly obvious in the example of the
-Courant Institute plaza. (Is "ringing in the ears' in the same class of
-phenomena?)
-
-An insight that is crucial in elucidating this problem is that when I
-describe episodes, the descriptions implicitly convey not only sensations but
-beliefs, as when I speak of a typewriter in a dream on the assumption that it
-persisted while I was not looking at it. The peculiar quality of a quasi-dream
-comes about not only because it is an anomaly in my sensations but because
-it is an anomaly in the scientific-pragmatic cognitive model which underlies
-ordinary language. If I discard this cognitive model and then report the
-event, it will not be the same event: the beliefs implicit in ordinary language
-helped give the event its quality. As a further example, now that I have
-recognized experiences such as that of 1/12/1974, I am willing to entertain
-the possibility that they are the basis for claims by superstitious persons to
-have projected astrally. But to use the phrase "astral projection" is to embed
-the experiences in a pre-scientific belief system extraneous to the
-experiences themselves. If we learn to report such experiences by using
-idioms like "ringing in the ears" and blocking any comparison with notions
-of objective reality or intersubjective import, we will have flattened out
-experience and will have moved in the direction of ungraded experience and
-nihilistic empiricism.
-
-\textbf{E.} We next take up connections between adjacent dreamed and waking
-periods. As a preliminary, we reject conventional notions that dreams are
-fabricated from memories of waking reality; or that dreams are precognitions
-of waking reality; or that dreams are mental phenomena which symbolize
-waking reality. We reject these notions because they conflict with the placing
-of the dream world on the same level as the waking world.
-
-Connections between dream and waking periods are important in this
-study because we may wish to create such connections deliberately, and even
-to attribute causal significance to them. Initially, we define the concept of
-dream control: it is to conduct one's waking life so that it is supportive of
-one's dreamed life in some sense. We also define controlled dreaming: it is to
-manipulate a person "from outside" before sleep {or during sleep) so as to
-influence the content of that person's dreams. (An example would be to give
-somebody a psychoactive sleeping pill.)
-
-A careful analysis of connections between dream and waking periods
-yields the following classification of such connections.
-
-\begin{enumerate}
- \item I walk around the kitchen in a dream, then awaken and walk around the
-kitchen. Voluntary continued action.
-
-\item Given a project with causally separate components, voluntarily
-assembled, I can carry out the project entirely while awake, entirely in
-dreams, or partly while awake and partly in dreams.
-
-\item I walk around the kitchen while awake, then sleep. I may then walk
-around the kitchen in a dream. Also, I draw a glass of water while awake. I
-may have the glass of water to use in the dream. We could postulate that
-such connections are not mere coincidences, if they occur. However, we
-certainly cannot produce such connections at will. We call these connections
-echoes of waking actions in dreams. Note the case in which I taped my
-mouth shut before sleeping, and could not whistle in the subsequent dream.
-
-\item We next have connections from dreamed to waking periods which can be
-postulated to have causal significance. First, misfortune or danger in dreams
-is regularly followed by immediate awaking. Secondly, I! have had
-experiences in which a headlong dive or an attempt to whistle continued
-from dream to waking, right through waking up. These experiences are
-causally continuous actions. However, I cannot bring them about at will.
-
-\item We can manipulate a person "from outside" before sleep (or during sleep)
-so as to influence the content of that person's dreams. The dream is not an
-echo of the waking action; the causal relationship is manipulative. Examples
-are to give someone a psychoactive sleeping drug or to create a special
-environment for sleep. The case in which I taped my mouth shut before
-sleeping was a remarkable borderline case between an echo and a
-manipulation.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-in conclusion, dream control is any of the connections described in
-(1)--(4). Controlled dreaming is (5). We have analyzed these concepts
-meticulously because we want to exclude all attempts at magic, all
-superstition from the project of placing dreamed and waking life on the same
-level. There must be no rain dancing, no false causality, in this project.
-
-\textbf{F.} Until now, we have analyzed our experience episode by episode. We
-could make this approach into a principle by assuming that each episode is a
-separate and complete world, which has its reality confirmed internally. In
-particular, the notion of objective location in space and time would be
-maintained if it appeared in a dream and was intersubjectively confirmed in
-the dream, but the notion would be purely internal to each episode. The
-objection to these assumptions, as we mentioned at the end of (B), is that
-they propose to maintain the notion of objective location, and yet they
-forego the notion of the consistency of all portions of reality. if we adopt
-these assumptions and then compare all the reports of our dreamed and
-waking periods, we may find that we have experienced different events
-attributed to the same location---and indeed, that is exactly what we do
-experience.
-
-One of the main discoveries of this essay has been that dreamed and
-waking periods are more symmetrical than our scientific-pragmatic
-indoctrination would have us suppose. The reality of the dream world is
-intersubjectively confirmed---within the dream. Anecdotal anomalies can be
-found in waking periods as well as in dreams. Entities which resemble
-common object gestalts but which lack some of the reality cues of object
-gestalts can be encountered whicle we are fully awake. Now we can
-recognize a further symmetry between dreamed and waking life. A dreamed
-misfortune is usually "lost" when we awaken, and its disappearance is taken
-as evidence of the unreality of the dream (the nightmare). But we can also
-"lose" a waking misfortune by going to sleep and dreaming. Further, just as
-a waking misfortune can persist from one waking period to another, a
-dreamed misfortune can persist from one dream to another (recurrent
-nightmares). Thus, we conclude that in regard to the consistency of episodes
-with each other, there is no basis for preferring any one episode, dreamed or
-waking, as the standard by which the reality of other episodes will be judged.
-Of course, rather than maintaining the reality of each episode as a separate
-world, we can block all attributions of events to objective locations. This
-approach would alter the quality of the events and bring us closer to
-nihilistic empiricism.
-
-A further problem arises if we take the dream reports of other people as
-reports of reality. Suppose I am awake in my apartment at 3 AM on
-2/6/1974, but that someone dreams at that time that I am out of my
-apartment. Multiple existences which I do not even experience are now being
-attributed to me. (My own episodes also pose a problem of whether
-"multiple existences" are being attributed to me, but that problem concerns
-events I experience myself.) What we should recognize is that the problem of
-"multiple existences" is not as unique to our investigation as may at first
-appear. Natural science has an analogous problem in disposing of the notion
-of other minds. The notion of the existence of many minds, none of which
-can experience any other, is difficult to assimilate to the cognitive model of
-science. On the other hand, to deny the existence of any mind, as
-behaviorists do, is to repudiate the scientist's observations of his own mental
-life. And if the scientist's observations of his own mental life are repudiated,
-then there is no good reason not to repudiate the scientist's observations of
-his budily sensations and of external phenomena also; that is, to repudiate
-the very possibility of scientific observation. Further, when behaviorists try
-to convince people that they have no awareness, whom (or what) are they
-trying to convince? And what is the behaviorist explanation of the origin of
-the fiction of consciousness? Who benefits from perpetuating this fiction,
-and how does he benefit?
-
-We must emphasize that the above critique is not applicable to every
-philosophical outlook. It applies specifically to science---because the scientist
-wants to have the benefits of two incompatible conceptual frameworks.
-Some of the common sense about other minds is necessary in the operational
-preliminaries to formal science; and the scientist's role as observer is
-indispensable to formal science. Yet the conceptual framework of science is
-essentially physicalistic, and can allow only for external objects. What this
-difficulty reveals is that the cognitive model of science has stabilized and
-prevailed even though it has blatent discrepancies in its foundations. The
-foremost discrepancy, of course, is that the scientist is willing to have his
-enterprise rest on a fiction, that of the common objective world. Thus, the
-example of science suggests an additional way of dealing with the problems
-which arise for our theory: we can allow discrepancies to persist unresolved.
-
-There is an interesting observation to be made about one's own dreams
-in connection with multiple existences. I have found that the person I am in
-my dreams is significantly different from the waking identity I take for
-granted, as in my dream of 2/1/1974. As for the problem of other people's
-dreams, one way of handling them would be simply to reject the existence of
-other people's dream worlds and of their consciousnesses, and to limit one's
-consideration to one's own dreams. But perhaps the most productive way to
-handle the problem would be to construe it as one involving language in the
-way that the problems concerning quasi-dreams did. Our descriptive language
-is a language of stable object gestalts, of scientific-pragmatic reality. If we
-accept reports of other people's dreams in language which blocks any
-implications concerning objective reality, then our perceptual interpretations
-will be different and the quality of the events will be fundamentally
-different. The experience-world will be flatter. But maybe this is a
-revolutionary advance. Maybe reports of our appearances in other people's
-dreams, in language which blocks any implications about reality, are what we
-should strive for. And if ve cease to be stable object gestalts for others,
-maybe our stable object gestalts will not even appear in their dreams.
-
-
-\section*{Note on how to remember dreams}
-
-The trick in remembering a dream is to fix in your mind one incident or
-theme in the dream immediately upon awaking from it. You will then be
-able to remember the whole dream well enough to write a description of it
-the next day, and you will probably find that for weeks afterwards you can
-add to the description and correct it.
-
+\input{essays/energy_cube1966.tex}
+\input{essays/energy_cube1961.tex}
+\input{essays/concept_art.tex}
+\input{essays/perception_dissociator.tex}
+\input{essays/exercise_awareness_states.tex}
+\input{essays/mock_risk_games.tex}
+\input{essays/dream_reality.tex}
\part{Social Philosophy}
-
-\chapter{On Social Recognition}
-
-The most important tasks which the individual can undertake arise not
-from personal considerations but from the general conditions of society. The
-standards of accomplishment for these tasks are implicit in the tasks, and are
-objective in the sense that they can be applied without reference to public
-opinion. For example, given that humans express themselves in statements
-which are supposedly true or false, there arises a fundamental philosophical
-"problem of knowledge." Then, the fact that societies are organized in
-different ways at different times and places poses fundamental problems of
-"political" thought and action. Sometimes the most important task posed by
-the conditions of society is to invent a whole new activity. The origination
-of experimental science in Europe in the seventeenth century is an example.
-For lack of a better term, these tasks will be referred to as 'fundamental!
-tasks."
-
-The fact that a fundamental task is posed by the general conditions of
-society does not mean that public opinion will be aware of the task, or that
-the ruling class will commission someone to undertake it. It may well be that
-the first person to perceive the problem is the person who solves it; and
-public opinion may not catch up with him for decades or centuries.
-
-The person who devotes himself to a fundamental task is, more often
-than not, persecuted or ignored by society. Society puts up an immense
-resistance to solutions of fundamenta! problems, even when, as in the cases
-of Galois and Mendel, those solutions are politically innocuous. There is no
-evidence that this state of affairs is limited to some particular organization of
-society. Further, there are cases in which an objectively valid result is
-known, and yet apparently society can never adopt the result institutionally.
-Art is objectively inferior to brend, as I have shown, and yet all indications
-are that art will always be a major institution. The persecution of individuals
-who undertake fundamental tasks is an instance of a general human social
-irrationality which runs throughout history, from human sacrifice in ancient
-times to present-day war between communist countries. The conclusion is
-that for an individual to commit himself to a fundamental task tends to
-preclude social approval for his activities.
-
-Quite apart from the fundamental tasks which are posed by general
-social conditions, the ruling class needs a continual supply of new talent at
-all levels of society. At the lower levels, this supply is assured by the
-necessity of selling one's labor power in order to eat. At the higher levels of
-accomplishment, the ruling class assures itself of a continual supply of new
-talent by offering publicity or fame---social recognition---as a reward for
-accomplishing the tasks specified by the ruling class. Famous men such as
-Einstein are held up to children as examples of the proper relationship
-between the talented individual and society; and an internationa! institution,
-the Nobel Prize, exists to implement this system of supplying talent.
-According to the doctrine, the individual has a duty to benefit society, to
-choose a task posed by the ruling class as his occupation. (His publicly
-known occupation is supposed to correspond to his real goals.) If he
-performs successfully, he will receive publicity as an indication that he is
-indeed benefiting society.
-
-Our analysis of fame is the opposite of that of Ben Vautier. Vautier
-asserts that the desire for personal publicity is an instinctive drive of human
-beings, and that the accumulation of publicity is a genuinely selfish act like
-the accumulation of food. In fact, Vautier goes so far as to make no
-distinction between what Gypsy Rose Lee and Lenin, for example, did to
-gain fame; and he assumes that a pacifist, for example, would welcome
-military honors equally as much as he would a peace award. We assert, on
-the contrary, that the desire for publicity is not instinctive; it is inculcated in
-the young so that the ruling class may have a continual supply of new talent
-to serve its purposes. The desire for publicity, far more than the desire for
-money, is establishment-serving more than self-serving. (We suggest that the
-principal reason why Vautier seeks publicity is not instinct, but economics.
-Vautier has no inherited source of income, and has never been trained for a
-profession. For him, the alternative to the art\slash publicity racket would be
-common labor. If he had the opportunity for a life of leisure, he might feel
-differently about publicity.)
-
-The issues which are raised here are extremely important for the person
-who perceives a fundamental task, because his sanity may depend on
-whether he understands the rationality of his motives for undertaking the
-task. He will already have been inculcated with the establishment's concepts
-of service and recognition, concepts which are epitomized in the image of
-Einstein's career. What we suggest is that it is vital to disabuse oneself of
-these concepts. To repeat, fundamental tasks are posed by the general
-conditions of society. Yet the individual who undertakes such a task will
-probably be persecuted or ignored. Given these circumstances, the doctrine
-that the individual has a duty to benefit society is a hypocritical fraud, an
-obscenity. For the individual to commit himself to a fundamental task tends
-to preclude social recognition for his activities; or, to reverse the remark,
-social recognition is not a reward to accomplishment of a fundamental task
-(just as military honors are not a reward to pacifism). Thus, it is not rational
-for the individual to undertake a fundamental task in order to gain fame.
-
-The motive for undertaking a fundamental task should be genuine
-selfishness. (We will continue our argument that the striving for fame is not
-genuinely selfish below.) The individual who perceives a fundamental task
-should undertake it for his private gratification. The task is of primary
-importance to society. By accomplishing it, the individual gains the privilege
-of knowing something which is socially important, but which society cannot
-deal with honestly. The individual should undertake the task in order to
-utilize his real abilities, to develop his potentiality for its own sake. The
-undertaking of a significant task which utilizes one's real abilities is the true
-source of happiness. To perceive a fundamental task and not to undertake it
-is to be stunted: one loses one's self-respect and becomes progressively
-demoralized. (Another rational motive for undertaking a fundamental task is
-to transform the social environment by methods which do not depend on
-society's approval or comprehension.)
-
-We do not mean to suggest that the individual who undertakes a
-fundamental task should conceal his results. Even though such tasks may
-seem individualistic, they require cooperative, social activity for their
-accomplishment. A proposed solution to a fundamental problem can hardly
-develop without being scrutinized from a variety of perspectives. It is
-essential to have qualified critics, and it is unfortunate that they are so rare.
-Solutions to fundamental problems are social consumption goods (their
-consumption is not exclusionary), so that critics or collaborators have as
-much opportunity to benefit from them as their originators do. As an
-example, most of my writings are really collaborations with Tony Conrad. I
-often find that I do not understand my own position until I know how it
-appears to him. When communication of results is essentially a form of
-collaboration, it is very different from the attempt to gain publicity or fame.
-
-It is precisely in the context of the generalized social irrationality which
-runs throughout history that the attempt to gain fame must be seen as
-foolishly un-selfish. What difference can it possibly make whether the masses
-venerate one's name a hundred years after one's death? The adulation of the
-masses after one is dead is of no conceivable value to oneself. It is society
-which indoctrinates one to worry about one's reputation after one is dead, in
-order to condition one to serve the interests of the ruling class.
-
-Then, what does it mean to the individual who solves a fundamental
-problem to have his name publicized in the mass media, to be a celebrity
-among people who cannot possibly understand what he has done? Even
-more important, we must recognize that publicity carries a definte risk for
-the individual committed to a fundamental task. The solution of such a
-problem must usually be expressed in categories which are incommensurate
-and incompatible with the categories of thought which are common coin at
-the time. In order for the solution of a fundamental! problem to be exposed
-in the mass media, it has to be translated into media categories and this
-usually results in irreparable distortion. In fact, the solution is distorted in
-precisely such a manner that it begins to serve the interests of the ruling
-class. One encounters an immense pressure which tends to harness one to
-goals which have nothing to do with objective value. More precisely, when an
-individual who has solved a fundamental problem is publicized in the mass
-media, a process of mutual subversion takes place as between the
-establishment\slash media and the individual. In the process, the establishment is
-likely to come out far ahead.
-
-There are two other reasons why it is actually advantageous to the
-individual who undertakes a fundamental task to avoid publicity. Since one's
-activity is likely to be treated as a threat by society, one can minimize the
-energy required to defend it, and can carry the activity further, if one
-receives no publicity. Then, there will unavoidably be false starts made in
-developing the solution to a fundamental problem. If one is not operating in
-the glare of publicity, it is far easier to abandon these false starts.
-
-It used to be that when I saw publicity being given to an inferior way of
-doing a thing, and I knew a better way, then I reacted with a sense of duty. I
-had to appoint myself as a missionary, to enter the public arena and start a
-campaign to replace the inferior approach with the better approach. But this
-sense of duty must now be called into question. Is it really in my interest to.
-thrust myself on the media as a missionary? The truth is that in the context
-of generalized social irrationality, it is un-selfish and self-sacrificing to believe
-that I must either agree with current fads or else contest them publicly. The
-genuinely selfish attitude is *hat it is sufficient for me to know what the
-superior approach is. I can ignore the false issues which fill the mass media; I
-do not have to participate in public opinion at all. The genuinely selfish
-attitude is that "it does not concern me." Genuine selfishness is living one's
-life on a level which does not communicate with the level of the mass media
-and public opinion.
-
-If we recognize that it is irrational to undertake a fundamental task in
-order to benefit society and gain social approval, then our very choice of
-fundamental tasks shouid be affected. The most visible fundamental tasks
-are those which the establishment is to some extent aware of, and which if
-accomplished would immediately be rewarded with social approval. (In the
-natural sciences, there literally may be a race to solve a well-known problem).
-But if our motives are genuinely self-serving, and have to do with the
-development of our potentiality for its own sake, then there is no reason to
-limit ourselves to widely understood problems. We can undertake to discover
-timeless results---permanent answers to questions which will be important
-indefinitely---without concerning ourselves with whether society can adopt
-the results institutionally. We can pose problems of which neither the
-establishment, the media, nor public opinion are aware. We can undertake
-tasks which draw on our unique abilities, so that our personal contribution is
-indispensable.
-
-There is a difficulty which we have postponed mentioning. The
-individual is always compelled to engage in some socially approved activity
-in order to obtain the means of subsistence. We cannot assume that the
-individual will have an inherited source of income. In order to pursue a
-fundamental task, he will have to pursue a legitimate occupation at the same
-time. It may be extremely difficult to lead such a double life, because to do
-so requires precisely the self-assurance. that comes from accomplishing the
-fundamental task. Leading a double life is not a game for the person who is
-unsure about his real abilities or his vocation. If the individual is capable of
-leading a double life, our suggestion is to obtain the means of subsistence by
-the most efficient swindle available. Do not hesitate to practice outward
-conformity in order to exploit the establishment for your own purposes.
-
-There remains the case of the individual who, like Galois, is not
-prepared to lead a double life. His problem is one of destitution. However,
-he is different from an ordinary pauper. By assumption, he is more talented
-than the members of the establishment; he does not belong to the
-establishment because he is overqualified for it. Given that he is more
-talented than members of the establishment, and that his survival is
-threatened, a collateral fundamental task emerges, the task of immediately
-transmuting his talent into power to handle the establishment on his own
-terms. To perceive this task is a major resuit of this essay. The task cannot be
-defined accurately without a perfect understanding of the difference
-between fundamental tasks and the serve-society-and-get-famous fraud. We
-contend that Galois should have regarded the task of immediately
-transmuting his talent into power over the establishment as an inseparable
-collateral problem to his mathematical researches. From a common sense
-point of view, this collateral task will seem utterly impossible. However, we
-are talking about individuals whose vocation is to do the seemingly
-impossible. Thus, we conclude by leaving this unsolved fundamental problem
-for the reader to ponder.
-
-\chapter{Creep}
-
-
-When Helen Lefkowitz said I was "such a creep" at Interlochen in
-1956, her remark epitomized the feeling that females have always had about
-me. My attempts to understand why females rejected me and to decide what
-to do about it resulted in years of confusion. In 1961-1962, I tried to
-develop a theory of the creep problem. This theory took involuntary
-celibacy as the defining characteristic of the creep. Every society has its
-image of the ideal young adult, even though the symbols of growing up
-change from generation to generation. The creep is an involuntary celibate
-because he fails to develop the surface traits of adulthood--poise and
-sophistication; and because he is shy, unassertive, and lacks self-confidence
-in the presence of others. The creep is awkward and has an unstylish
-appearance. He seems sexless and childish. He is regarded by the ideal adults
-with condescending scorn, amusement, or pity.
-
-Because he seems weak and inferior in the company of others, and
-cannot maintain his self-respect, the creep is pressed into isolation. There,
-the creep doesn't have the pressure of other people's presence to make him
-feel inferior, to make him feel that he must be like them in order not te be
-inferior. The creep can develop the morale required to differ. The creep also
-tends to expand his fantasy life, so that it takes the place of the
-interpersonal life from which he has been excluded. The important
-consequence is that the creep is led to discover a number of positive
-personality values which cannot be achieved by the mature, married adult.
-During the period when I developed the creep theory, I was spending almost
-all of my time alone in my room, thinking and writing. This fact should
-make the positive creep values more understandable.
-
-\begin{enumerate}
-\item Because of his isolation, the creep has a qualitatively higher sense of
-identity. He has a sense of the boundaries of his personality, and a control of
-what goes on within those boundaries. In contrast, the mature adult, who
-spends all his time with his marriage partner or in groups of people, is a mere
-channel into which thoughts flow from outside; he lives in a state of
-conformist anonymity.
-
-\item The creep is emotionally autonomous, independent, or
-self-contained. He develops an elaborate world of feelings which remain
-within himself, or which are directed toward inanimate objects. The creep
-may cooperate with other people in work situations, but he does not develop
-emotional attachments to other people.
-
-\item Although the creep's intellectual abilities develop with education,
-the creep lives in a sexually neutral world and a child's world throughout his
-life. He is thus able to play like a child. He retains the child's capacity for
-make-believe. He retains the child's lyrical creativity in regard to
-self-originated, self-justifying activities.
-
-\item There is enormous room in the creep's life for the development of
-every aspect of the inner world or the inner life. The creep can devote
-himself to thought, fantasy, imagination, imaging, variegated mental states,
-dreams, internal emotions and feelings towards inanimate objects. The creep
-develops his inner world on his own power. His inner life originates with
-himself, and is controlled and intellectually consequential. The creep has no
-use for meditations whose content is supplied by religious traditions. Nor has
-he any use for those drug experiences which adolescents undertake to prove
-how grown-up they are, and whose content is supplied by fashion. The
-creep's development of his inner life is the summation of all the positive
-creep values.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-After describing these values, the creep theory returned to the problem
-of the creep's involuntary celibacy. For physical reasons, the creep remains a
-captive audience for the opposite sex, but his attempts to gain acceptance by
-the opposite sex always end in failure. On the other hand, the creep may
-well find the positive creep values so desirable that he will want to intensify
-them. The solution is for the creep to seek a medical procedure which will
-sexually neutralize him. He can then attain the full creep values, without the
-disability of an unresolved physical desire.
-
-Actually, the existence of the positive creep values proves that the
-creep is an authentic non-human who happens to be trapped in human social
-biology. The positive creep values imply a specification of a whole
-non-human: social biology which would be appropriate to those values.
-Finally, the creep theory mentioned that creeps often make good grades in
-school, and can thus do clerical work or other work useful to humans. This
-fact would be the basis for human acceptance of the creep.
-
-In the years after I presented the creep theory, a number of
-inadequacies became apparent in it. The principal one was that I managed to
-cast off the surface traits of the creep, but that when I did my problem
-became even more intractable. An entirely different analysis of the problem
-was required.
-
-My problem actually has to do with the enormous discrepancy between
-the ways I can relate to males and the ways I can relate to females. The
-essence of the problem has to do with the social values of females, which are
-completely different from my own. The principal occupation of my life has
-been certain self-originated activities which are embodied in "writings." Now
-most males have the same social values that I find in all females. But there
-have always been a few males with exceptional values; and my activities have
-developed through exchanges of ideas with these males. These exchanges
-have come about spontaneously and naturally. In contrast, I have never had
-such an exchange of ideas with females, for the following reasons. Females
-have nothing to say that applies to my activities. They cannot understand
-that such activities are possible. Or they are a part of the "masses" who
-oppose and have tried to discourage my activities.
-
-The great divergence between myself and females comes in the area
-where each individual is responsible for what he or she is; the area in which
-one must choose oneself and the principles with which one will be identified.
-This area is certainly not a matter of intelligence or academic degrees.
-Further, the fact that society has denied many opportunities to females at
-one time or another is not involved here. (My occupation has no formal
-prerequisites, no institutional barriers to entry. One enters it by defining
-oneself as being in it. Yet no female has chosen to enter it. Or consider such
-figures as Galileo and Galois. By the standards of their contemporaries, these
-individuals were engaged in utterly ridiculous, antisocial pursuits. Society
-does not give anybody the "opportunity" to engage in such pursuits. Society
-tries to prevent everybody from being a Galileo or Galois. To be a Galileo is
-really a matter of choosing sides, of choosing to take a certain stand.)
-
-Let me be specific about my own experiences. When I distributed the
-prospectus for \journaltitle{The Journal of Indeterminate Mathematical Investigations} to
-graduate students at the Courant Institute in the fall of 1967, the most
-negative reactions came from the females. The mere fact that I wanted to
-invent a mathematics outside of academic mathematics was in and of itself
-offensive and revolting to them. Since the academic status of these females
-was considerably higher than my own, the disagreement could only be
-considered one of values.
-
-The field of art provides an even better example, because there are
-many females in this field. In the summer of 1969 I attended a meeting of
-the women's group of the Art Workers Coalition in New York. Many of the
-women there had seen my Down With Art pamphlet. Ail the females who
-have seen this pamphlet have reacted negatively, and it is quite clear what
-their attitude is. They believe that they are courageously defending modern
-art against a philistine. They consider me to be a crank who needs a "modern
-museum art appreciation course." The more they are pressed, the more
-proudiy do they defend "Great Art." Now the objective validity of my
-opposition to art is absolutely beyond question. To defend modern art is
-precisely what a hopeless mediocrity would consider courageous. Again, it is
-clear that the opposition between myself and females is in the area where
-one must choose one's values.
-
-I have found that what I really have to do to make a favorable
-impression on females is to conceal or suspend my activities----the most
-important part of my life; and to adopt a facade of conformity. Thus, I
-perceive females as persons who cannot function in my occupation. I
-perceive them as being like an employment agency, like an institution to
-which you have to present a conformist facade. Females can he counted on to
-represent the most "social, human" point of view, a point of view which, as I
-have explained, is distant from my own. (In March 1970, at the Institute for
-Advanced Study, the mathematician Dennis Johnson said to me that he
-would murder his own mother, and murder all his friends, if by doing so he
-could get the aliens to take him to another star and show him a higher
-civilization. My own position is the same as Johnson's.)
-
-It follows that my perception of sex is totally different from that of
-others. The depictions of sex in the mass media are completely at variance
-with my own experience. I object to pornography in particular because it is
-like deceptive advertising for sex; it creates the impression that the physical
-aspect of sex can be separated from human personalities and social
-interaction. Actually, if most people can separate sex from personality, it is
-because they are so average that their values are the same as everybody else's.
-In my case, although I am a captive audience for females for physical
-reasons, the disparity between my values and theirs overrides the physical
-attraction I feel for them. It is hard enough to present a facade of
-conformity in order to deal with an employment agency, but the thought of
-having to maintain such a facade in a more intimate relationship is
-completely demoralizing.
-
-What conclusions can be drawn by comparing the creep theory with my
-later experience? First, some individuals who are unquestionably creeps as
-far as the surface traits are concerned simply may not be led to the deeper
-values I described. They may not have the talent to get anything positive out
-of their involuntary situation; or their aspirations may be so conformist that
-they do not see their involuntary situation as a positive opportunity. Many
-creeps are female, but all the evidence indicates that they have the same
-values I have attributed to other females---values which are hard to reconcile
-with the deeper creep values.
-
-As for the positive creep values, I may have had them even before I
-began to care about whether females accepted me. For me, these values may
-have been the cause, not the effect, of surface creepiness. They are closely
-related to the values that underlie my activities. It is not necessary to appear
-strangely dressed, childish, unassertive, awkward, and lacking in confidence
-in order to achieve the positive creep values. (I probably emphasized surface
-creep traits during my youth in order to dissociate myself from conformist
-opinion at a time when I hadn't yet had the chance to make a full
-substantive critique of it.) Even sex, in and of itself, might not be
-incompatible with the creep inner life; what makes it incompatible is the
-female personality and female social values, which in real life cannot be
-separated from sex and are the predominant aspect of it.
-
-Having cast off the surface traits of the creep, I can now see that
-whether I make a favorable impression on females really depends on whether
-I conceal my occupation. Celibacy is an effect of my occupation; it does not
-have the role of a primary cause that the creep theory attributed to it.
-However, it does have consequences of its own. In the context of the entire
-situation I have described, it constitutes an absolute dividing line between
-myself and humanity. It does seem to be closely related to the deeper creep
-values, especially the one of living in a child's world.
-
-As for the sexual neutralization advocated in the creep theory, to find a
-procedure which actually achieves the stated objective without having all
-sorts of unacceptable side effects would be an enormous undertaking. It is
-not feasible as a minor operation developed for a single person. Further, as
-the human species comes to have vast technological capabilities, many
-special interest groups will want to tinker with human social biology, each in
-a different way, for political reasons. I am no longer interested in petty
-tinkering with human biology. As I make it clear in other writings, I am in
-favor of building entities which are actially superior to humans, and which
-avoid the whole fabric of human biosocial defects, not just one or two of
-them.
-
-\clearpage
-{
-
-
-2/22/1963
-Henry Flynt and Jack Smith demonstrate against Lincoln Center, February 22, 1963
-(photo by Tony Conrad)
-}
-\clearpage
-
-
-\chapter{The Three Levels of Politics}
-
-
-Political activity and its results can occur on three levels. The first level
-is the personal one. An individual may vote to re-elect a local politician
-because of patronage he has received, for example. On this level the
-individual's motivation is narrow, immediate self-interest. Often the action
-has a defensive character; the individual is trying to hold on to something he
-already possesses.
-
-The second level may be called the historical level. It is exemplified by
-the Civil War in the United States. Certain political movements result in
-largescale, irreversible social change. The Civil War set in motion the
-industrialization of the United States, as well as abolishing slavery. In 1860,
-slavery was viewed by large numbers of Americans as a legitimate institution.
-One hundred years later, even American conservatives did not often defend
-it. To re-establish a plantation economy in the South today would be out of
-the question. These observations prove that on the second level, society
-really does change. On this level, political action does make a difference.
-
-However, there is a further aspect to the Civil War which indicates that
-politics does not make the difference people think it makes. According to
-the ideology of the abolitionists, the accomplishment of the Civil War would
-be to raise the slaves to a position of equality with whites. In fact, nothing of
-the sort happened. The real accomplishment of the Civil War was to
-transform the United States into an industria! capitalist society (and to
-abolish an institution which was incompatible with the capitalists' need for a
-free labor market). By the time the Northern businessmen brought
-Reconstruction to an end, it was clear that the position of blacks in
-American society was where it had always been: at the bottom. The Civil
-War changed American society, but is did not make the society any more
-utopian. On the contrary, it brought into prominence still another violent
-social conflict---the conflict between labor and capital.
-
-The third level of politics has to do with the utopian aspect of modern
-political ideologies, the aspect which calls not only for society to change, but
-to change for the better. Typical third-level political goals are the abolition
-of war, the abolition of the oligarchic structure of society, and the abolition
-of economic institutions which value human lives in terms of money. in all
-of human history, society has never changed on this third level.
-
-The successful Communist revolutionists of the twentieth century (in
-the underdeveloped countries) have repeatedly claimed to have accomplished
-third-level change in their societies. However, these claims of third-level
-change have always turned out to be illusions which cover a recapitulation of
-capitalist development. Communist revolutions are typical examples of real
-second-level change which is accomplished under the cover of claims of
-third-level change, claims which are pure and simple frauds.
-
-By introducing the concept of levels of politics, we can resolve the
-apparent paradox that society certainly changes, but that it really does not
-change. It is important to understand that empirical evidence on the
-question of the levels of politics can only be drawn from the past, the
-present, and the immediate future (five to ten years). Recent technological
-developments have brought into question the very existence of the human
-species. In addition, technology is developing much faster than society is. It
-is meaningless to discuss the issue of second versus third-level social change
-with reference to the more distant future, because there may not be any
-human society in the more distant future.
-
-This essay is concerned with the politics of the third level. The first and
-second levels are certainly rea! enough, but we are not the least interested in
-them. As we have just said, we make the restriction that any empirical
-analysis of the third level must refer to the past, the present, or the
-immediate future. Our purpose is to present a substitute for the politics of
-the third level.
-
-There are a number of present-day political tendencies which hold out
-the promise of third-level social change. These tendencies are all descended
-from the leftist working-class movements of nineteenth century Europe,
-most of them by way of the early Soviet regime. The promises of third-level
-change held out by these tendencies are nothing but cheap illusions. What is
-more, a careful examination of leftist ideologies in relation to the historical
-record will show that the promises of third-level change are extremely vague
-and without substance. Beneath the surface of vague promises, leftist
-ideologies do not even favor third-level change; they are opposed to it.
-
-One example will serve to demonstrate this contention. In my capacity
-as a professional economist, I have become familiar with the official
-economic policies---the doctrines of the professional economists---of the
-various socialist governments and leftist movements throughout the world. It
-should be mentioned that most of the followers of leftism are not familiar
-with these technical economic policies; they are aware only of vague,
-meaningless promises of future bliss coming from leftist political
-speechmakers. When we turn to technical economic realities, we find that
-virtually every leftist tendency in the world today accepts economic
-principles which in the parlance of the layman are referred to as
-"capitalism." The most important principle is stated by Ernest Mandel: "the
-economy continues to be fundamentally a money economy, with the
-satisfaction of the bulk of people's needs depending on the number of
-currency tokens a person possesses." When it comes to the realities of
-technical economics, virtually every leftist in the world accepts this
-principle. So far as the third level is concerned, there is no such thing as a
-non-capitalist polical tendency, and there is no point in hoping for one. A
-similar conclusion holds for virtually every aspect of third-level politics.
-Leftists claim that Communism eliminates the causes of war; while at the
-same time war breaks out beween China and the Soviet Union.
-
-We propose to draw a far-reaching conclusion from these
-considerations. Returning to the example of first-level politics, it is rational
-for the patronage-seeker to be in favor of the election of one focal politican
-and against the election of his opponent. This is a matter which is within the
-scope of human responsibility, and with respect to which individual action
-can make a difference. But it is not rationa! to be either for against
-"capitalism," to be either for or against war. As we have seen, "capitalism"
-and war are permanent aspects of human society, and no political tendency
-genuinely opposes them. {t is meaningless to treat them as if they were
-within the scope of human responsibility in the sense that the election of a
-local politician is. in other words, the third-level aspects of society are not
-partial, limited aspects which can be eliminated by conscious human action
-while the bulk of human life is retained. The only way you can meaningfully
-be against the third-level aspects of human society is by adopting a different
-attitude to the human species as such.
-
-This attitude is the one you would adopt if you were suddenly thrown
-into a society of apes---apes which perpetually preyed within their own
-ecological niche. It is clear that if you proposed to be "against" such a
-situation, and to do something about it, then politics as it is normally
-conceived would be out of the question. To anticipate our later discussion,
-the first thing you must do is to protect yourself against society. The way to
-do this is to create an invisible enclave for yourself within the Establishment.
-Having such an enclave certainly does not imply loyalty to the
-Establishment. On the contrary, there is no reason why you should be toyal
-to any faction among the apes. You only pretend to be loyal to one faction
-or another when it is necessary for self-defense. If there is a change of regime
-in the country where you are living, you either leave or join the winning side.
-Transfer your invisible enclave to whatever Establishment is available. But all
-this is an external, defensive tactic which has nothing to do with the primary
-goals of our strategy.
-
-We will finish our critique of third-level politics, and then continue the
-description of the substitute which we propose. In addition to making vague
-promises of third-level change, leftism encourages indignation at social
-conditions which are beyond anyone's power to affect. Leftism attributes
-great ethical merit to such indignation and morally condemns anyone who
-does not share it. But this attitude is totally irrational and dishonest. In
-philosophy and mathematics, it is possible for a proposition to be valid even
-though it has no chance of institutional acceptance. But in social, economic,
-and political matters, attitudes which have policy implications are nonsense
-unless the policies are actually implemented. Institutional acceptance is the
-only arena of validation of a social doctrine. It is absurd to attribute ethical
-merit to a longing for the impossible. Indignation at a social condition which
-is beyond anyone's power to affect is meaningless. (Indeed, to the extent
-that such indignation diverts social energy into a dead end, it is
-"counter-revolutionary.") To be more radical in social matters than society
-can possibly be is not virtuous; it is idiotic.
-
-Although third-level politics is a fraud, it is the contention of this essay
-that there exists a rational substitute for it. Once you perceive that you exist
-in a society of apes who attack their own ecological niche, there are rational
-goals which you can adopt for your life that correspond to third-level change
-even though they have nothing to do with leftism. The preliminary step, as
-we have said, is to create an invisible enclave for yourself within. the
-Establishment. The remainder of the strategy is in two parts which are in
-fact closely related.
-
-The first part is based on a consideration of the effects which such
-figures as Galileo, Galois, Abel, Lobachevski, and Mendel have had on
-society. These men devoted themselves to researches which seemed to be
-purely abstract, without any relevance to the practical world. Yet, through
-long, tortuous chains of events, their researches have had disruptive effects
-on society which go far beyond the effects of most political movements. The
-reason has to do with the peculiar role which technology has in human
-society. Society's attitude in relation to technology is like that of a child
-who cannot refrain from playing with matches. We find that
-the abstract researches of the men being considered accomplished a dual
-result. On the one hand, they represented inner escape, the achievement of a
-private utopia now. Of course, the general public will not understand this;
-only the few who are capable of participating in such activities will
-appreciate the extent to which they can constitute inner escape. On the
-other hand, they have had profoundly disruptive effects on society, effects
-which still have not run their course.
-
-Thus, the first part of our strategy is to follow the example of these
-individuals. Of course, we do not stay within the bounds of present-day
-academic research, any more than Galileo or Mendel did in their time. What
-we have in mind is activities in the intellectual modality represented by the
-rest of this book.
-
-It should be clear that such activities do represent a private utopia, and are at
-the same time the seeds of disruptive future technologies which lead directly
-to the second part of our strategy.
-
-It is important to realize that by speaking of inner escape we do not
-mean fashionable drug use, or Eastern religions, or occultism. These
-threadbare superstitions are embraced by the cosmopolitan middle
-classes---intellectually spineless fools who are always grasping for spiritual
-comfort. Superstitious fads are escapism in the worst sense, as they only
-serve to further muddle the heads of the fools who embrace them. In
-contrast, the inner escape which we propose is origina! and consequential,
-leading to an increase in man's manipulative power over the world. It has
-nothing to do with irrationality or superstition.
-
-The second part of our strategy is predicated on the following states of
-affairs. First, it is the human species as such which is the obstacle to
-third-level political change. Secondly, technology is developing far more
-rapidly than society is, and no feature of the natural world need any longer
-be taken for granted. Society cannot help but foster technology in the
-pursuit of military and economic supremacy, and this includes technology
-which can contribute to the making of artificial superhuman beings. Every
-fundamental advance in logic, physics, neurophysiology, and
-neurocybernetics obviously leads in this direction. Thus, the second part of
-the strategy is to participate in the making of artificial superhumans,
-possibly by infiltrating the military-scientific establishment and diverting
-research in the appropriate direction.
-
-{ \itshape
-Note: This essay provides a specific, practical strategy for the present
-environment. It also shows that certain types of opposition to the status quo
-are meaningless. Subversion Theory, on the other hand, was a general theory
-which was not limited to any one environment, but also which failed to
-provide a specific strategy for the present environment. \par }
-
+\input{essays/social_recognition.tex}
+\input{essays/creep.tex}
+\input{essays/three_levels_of_politics.tex}
\part{Science (Logic)}
-
-\chapter{The Logic of Admissible Contradictions (Work in Progress)}
-
-\section{Chapter III. A Provisional Axiomatic Treatment}
-
-
-In the first and second chapters, we developed our intuitions
-concerning perceptions of the logically impossible in as much detail as we
-could. We decided, on intuitive grounds, which contradictions were
-admissible and which were not. As we proceeded, it began to appear that the
-results suggested by intuition were cases of a few general principles. In this
-chapter, we will adopt these principles as postulates. The restatement of our
-theory does not render the preceding chapters unnecessary. Only by
-beginning with an exhaustive, intuitive discussion of perceptual illusions
-could we convey the substance underlying the notations which we call
-admissble contradictions, and motivate the unusual collection of postulates
-which we will adopt.
-
-All properties will be thought of as "parameters," such as time,
-location, color, density, acidity, etc. Different parameters will be represented
-by the letters x, y, z, .... Different values of one parameter, say x, will be
-represented by $x_1$, $x_2$, .... Each parameter has a domain, the set of all values
-it can assume. An ensembie ($x_0$, $y_0$, $z_0$, ...) will stand for the single possible
-phenomenon which has x-value $x_0$, y-value $y_0$, etc. Several remarks are in
-order. My ensembles are a highly refined version of Rudolph Carnap's
-intensions or intension sets (sets of all possible entities having a given
-property). The number of parameters, or properties, must be supposed to be
-indefinitely large. By giving a possible phenomenon fixed values for every
-parameter, I assure that there will be only one such possible phenomenon. In
-other words, my intension sets are all singletons. Another point is that if we
-specify some of the parameters and specify their ranges, we limit the
-phenomena which can be represented by our "ensembles." If our first
-parameter is time and its range is $R$, and our second parameter is spatial
-location and its range is $R^2$, then we are limited to phenomena which are
-point phenomena in space and time. If we have a parameter for speed of
-motion, the motion will have to be infinitesimal. We cannot have a
-parameter for weight at all; we can only have one for density. The physicist
-encounters similar conceptual problems, and does noi find them
-insurmountable.
-
-Let ($x_1$, $y$, $z$, ...), ($x_2$, $y$, $z$, ...), etc. stand for possible phenomena
-which all differ from each other in respect to parameter x but are identical in
-respect to every other parameter $y$, $z$, ... . (If the ensembles were intension
-sets, they would be disjoint precisely because $x$ takes a different value in
-each.) A "simple contradiction family" of ensembles is the family [($x_1$,$y$,$z$,
-...), ($x_2$, $y$, $z$, ...), ...]. The family may have any number of ensembles. It
-actually represents many families, because $y$, $z$, ... are allowed to vary; but
-each of these parameters must assume the same value in all ensembles in any
-one family. $x$, on the other hand, takes different values in each ensemble in
-any one family, values which may be fixed. A parameter which has the same
-value throughout any one family will be referred to as a consistency
-parameter. A parameter which has a different value in each ensemble in a
-given family will be referred to as a contradiction parameter.
-"Contradiction" will be shortened to "con." A simple con family is then a
-family with one con parameter. The consistency parameters may be dropped
-from the notation, but the reader must remember that they are implicitly
-present, and must remember how they function.
-
-A con parameter, instead of being fixed in every ensemble, may be
-restricted to a different subset of its domain in every ensemble. The subsets
-must be mutually disjoint for the con family to be well-defined. The con
-family then represents many families in another dimension, because it
-represents every family which can be formed by choosing a con parameter
-value from the first subset, one from the second subset, etc.
-
-Con families can be defined which have more than one con parameter,
-i.e. more than one parameter satisfying all the conditions we put on x. Such
-con families are not "simple." Let the cardinality of a con family be
-indicated by a number prefixed to "family," and let the number of con
-parameters be indicated by a number prefixed to "con." Remembering that
-consistency parameters are understood, a 2-con $\infty$-family would appear as
-[($x_1$, $y_1$). ($x_2$, $y_2$), ...].
-
-A "contradiction" or "$\varphi$-object" is not explicitly defined, but it is
-notated by putting "$\varphi$" in front of a con family. The characteristics of $\varphi$-objects,
-or cons, are established by introducing additional postulates in the
-theory.
-
-In this theory, every con is either "admissible" or "not admissible."
-"Admissible" will be shortened to "am." The initial amcons of the theory
-are introduced by postulate. Essentially, what is postulated is that cons with
-a certain con parameter are am. (The cons directly postulated to be am are
-on 1-con families.) However, the postulate will specify other requirements for
-admissibility besides having the given con parameter. The requisite
-cardinality of the con family will be specified. Also, the subsets will be
-specified to which the con parameter must be restricted in each ensemble in
-the con. A con must satisfy all postulated requirements before it is admitted
-by the postulate.
-
-The task of the theory is to determine whether the admissibility of the
-cons postulated to be am implies the admissibility of any other cons. The
-method we have developed for solving such problems will be expressed as a
-collection of posiulates for our theory.
-
-\postulate{1} Given $\varphi[(x\in A),(x\in B),\ldots]$ am, where $x\in A$, $x\in B$, ... are the
-restrictions on the con parameter, and given $A_1\subset A$, $B_1\subset B$, ..., where $A_1,B_1,...\neq\emptyset$, then
-$\varphi[(x\in A_1),(x\in B_1),...]$ is am. This postulate is obviously
-equivalent to the postulate that $\varphi[(x\in A\cap C),(x\in B\cap C),...]$ is am, where $C$ is
-a subset of $x$'s domain end the intersections are non-empty. (Proof: Choose
-$C=A_1\cup B_1\cup\ldots$ .)
-
-\postulate{2} If $x$ and $y$ are simple amcon parameters, then a con with con
-parameters $x$ and $y$ is am if it satisfies the postulated requirements
-concerning amcons on $x$ and the postulated requirements concerning amcons
-on $y$.
-
-The effect of all our assumptions up to now is to make parameters
-totally independent. They do not interact with each other at all.
-
-We will now introduce some specific amcons by postulate. If $s$ is speed,
-consideration of the waterfall illusion suggests that we postulate
-$\varphi[(s>O),(s=O)]$ to be am. (But with this postulate, we have come a long way from
-the literary description of the waterfall illusion!) Note the implicit
-requirements that the con family must be a 2-family, and that $s$ must be
-selected from $[O]$ in one ensemble and from ${s:s>O}$ in the other ensemble.
-
-If $t$ is time, $t\in R$, consideration of the phrase "b years ago," which is an
-amcon in the natural language, suggests that we postulate $\varphi[(t):a-b\leq t\leq v-b \&a\leq v]$ to be am,
-where $a$ is a fixed time expressed in years A.D., $b$ is a fixed
-number of years, and $v$ is a variable---the time of the present instant in years
-A.D. The implicit requirements are that the con family must have the
-cardinality of the continuum, and that every value of $t$ from $a-b$ to $v-b$ must
-appear in an ensemble, where $v$ is a variable. Ensembles are thus continually
-added to the con family. Note that there is the non-trivial possibility of using
-this postulate more than once. We could admit a con for $a=1964$, $b=\sfrac{1}{2}$
-then admit another for $a=1963$, $b=2$, and admit still another for $a=1963$,
-$b=1$; etc.
-
-Let $p$ be spatial location, $p\in R^2$. Let $P_i$ be a non-empty, bounded,
-connected subset of $R^2$. Restriction subsets will be selected from the $P_i$.
-Specifically, let $P_1\cap P_2=\emptyset$. Consideration of a certain dreamed illusion
-suggests that we admit $\varphi[(p\in P_1),(p\in P_2)]$. The implicit requirements are
-obvious. But in this case, there are more requirements in the postulate of
-admissibility. May we apply the postulate twice? May we admit first
-$\varphi[(p\in P_1),(p\in P_2)]$ and then $\varphi[(p\in P_3),(p\in P_4)]$, where $P_3$ and $P_4$ are arbitrary
-$P_i$'s different from $P_1$ and $P_2$? The answer is no. We may admit
-$\varphi[(p\in P_1),(p\in P_2)]$ for arbitrary $P_1$ and $P_2$, $P_1\cap P_2=\emptyset$, but having made this "initial
-choice," the postulate cannot be reused for arbitrary $P_3$ and $P_4$. A second
-con $\varphi[(p\in P_3),(p\in P_4)]$, $P_3\cap P_4=\emptyset$, may be postulated to be am only if
-$P_1\cup P_3$,$P_2\cup P_3$,$P_1\cup P_4$, and $P_2\cup P_4$ are not connected. In other words, you
-may postulate many cons of the form $\varphi[(p\in P_i),(p\in P_j)]$ to be am, but
-your first choice strongly circumscribes your second choice, etc.
-
-We will now consider certain results in the logic of amcons which were
-established by extensive elucidation of our intuitions. The issue is whether
-our present axiomization produces the same results. We will express the
-results in our latest notation as far as possible. Two more definitions are
-necessary. The parameter $\theta$ is the angle of motion of an infinitesimally
-moving phenomenon, measured in degrees with respect to some chosen axis.
-Then, recalling the set $P_1$, choose $P_5$ and $P_6$ so that $P_1=P_5\cup P_6$ and
-$P_5\cap P_6=\emptyset$.
-
-The results by which we will judge our axiomization are as follows.
-
-\begin{enumerate} % TODO with colons?
-
- \item $\varphi[S, C_1\cup C_2]$ can be inferred to be am.
-
-Our present notation cannot express this result, because it does not
-distinguish between different types of uniform motion throughout a finite
-region, \ie the types $M$, $C_1$, $C_2$, $D_1$, and $D_2$. Instead, we have infinitesimal
-motion, which is involved in all the latter types of motion. Questions such as
-"whether the admissibility of $\varphi[M,S]$ implies the admissibility of $\varphi[C_1,S]$"
-drop out. The reason for the omission in the present theory is our choice of
-parameters and domains, which we discussed earlier. Our present version is
-thus not exhaustive. However, the deficiency is not intrinsic to our method;
-and it does not represent any outright falsification of our intuitions. Thus,
-we pass over the deficiency.
-
-\item $\varphi[(p\in P_1,s_0),(p\in P_2,S_0)]$ and other such cons can be inferred to be am.
-With our new, powerful approach, this result is trivial. It is guaranteed by
-what we said about consistency parameters.
-
-\item There is no way to infer that $\varphi[C_1,C_2]$ is am; and no way to infer that
-$\varphi[(45^\circ,s_0\greater O),(60^\circ,s=s_0)]$ is am.
-
-The first part of the result drops out. The second part is trivial with our new
-method as long as we do not postulate that cons on $\theta$ are am.
-
-\item $\varphi[(p\in P_2),(p\in P_5)]$ can be inferred to be am.
-
-Yes, by Postulate 1.
-
-\item $\varphi[(s>O, p\in P_1),(s=O, p\in P_2)]$ and $\varphi[(s>O, p\in P_2),(s=O, p\in P_1)]$ can
-be inferred to be am.
-
-Yes, by Postulate 2. These two amcons are distinct. The question of whether
-they should be considered equivalent is closely related to the degree to
-which con parameters are independent of each other.
-
-\item There is no way to infer that $\varphi[(p\in P_5),(p\in P_6)]$ or $\varphi[(p\in P_1),(p\in P_3)]$
-is am. Our special requirement in the postulate of admissibility for
-$\varphi[(p\in P_1),(p\in P_2)]$ guarantees this result.
-\end{enumerate}
-
-The reason for desiring this last result requires some discussion. In
-heuristic terms, we wish to avoid admitting both location in New York in
-Greensboro and location in Manhattan and Brooklyn. We also wish to avoid
-admitting location in New York in Greensboro and location in New York in
-Boston. If we admitted either of these combinations, then the intuitive
-rationale of the notions would indicate that we had admitted triple location.
-While we have a dreamed illusion which justifies the concept of double
-location, we have no intuitive justification whatever for the concept of triple
-location. It must be clear that admission of either of the combinations
-mentioned would not imply the admissibility of a con on a 3-family with
-con parameter p by the postulates of our theory. Our theory is formally safe
-from this implication. However, the intuitive meaning of either combination
-would make them proxies for the con on the 3-family.
-
-A closely related consideration is that in the preceding chapter, it
-appeared that the admission of $\varphi[(p\in P_1),(p\in P_2)]$ and $\varphi[(p\in P_5),(p\in P_6)]$
-would tend to require the admission of the object $\varphi[(p\in P_2),\varphi[(p\in P_5),(p\in P_6)]]$
-(a Type 1 chain). Further, it this implication held, then by the same
-rationale the admission of $\varphi[(p\in P_1),(p\in P_2)]$ and $\varphi[(s>O,p_0\in P_1),(s=O,p=p_0)]$,
- both of which are am, would require the admission of the object
-$\varphi[(p\in P_2), \varphi[(s>O,p_0\in P_1),(s=O, p=p_0)]]$.
-We may now say, however,
-that the postulates of our theory emphatically do not require us to accept
-these implications. If there is an intuitively valid notion underlying the chain
-on s and p, it reduces to the amcons introduced in result 5. As for the chain
-on p alone, we repeat that simultaneous admission of the two cons
-mentioned would tend to justify some triple location concept. However, we
-do not have to recognize that concept as being the chain. It seems that our
-present approach allows us to forget about chains for now.
-
-Our conclusion is that the formal approach of this chapter is in good
-agreement with our intuitively established results.
-
-\section*{Note on the overall significance of the logic of amcons:}
-
-When traditional logicians said that something was logically impossible,
-they meant to imply that it was impossible to imagine or visualize. But this
-implication was empirically false. The realm of the logically possible is not
-the entire realm of connotative thought; it is just the realm of normal
-perceptual routines. When the mind is temporarily freed from normal
-perceptual routines---especially in perceptual illusions, but also in dreams and
-even in the use of certain "illogical" natural language phrases---it can imagine
-and visualize the "logically impossible." Every text on perceptual
-psychology mentions this fact, but logicians have never noticed its immense
-significance. The logically impossible is not a blank; it is a whole layer of
-meaning and concepts which can be superimposed on conventional logic, but
-not reduced or assimilated to it. The logician of the future may use a drug or
-some other method to free himself from normal perceptual routines for a
-sustained period of time, so he can freely think the logically impossible. He
-will then perform rigorous deductions and computations in the logic of
-amcons.
-
-\chapter{Subjective Propositional Vibration (Work in Progress)}
-
-Up until the present, the scientific study of language has treated
-language as if it were reducible to the mechanical manipulation of counters
-on a board. Scientists have avoided recognizing that language has a mental
-aspect, especially an aspect such as the 'understood meaning" of a linguistic
-expression. This paper, on the other hand, will present linguistic constructs
-which inescapably involve a mental aspect that is objectifiable and can be
-subjected to precise analysis in terms of perceptual psychology. These
-constructs are not derivable from the models of the existing linguistic
-sciences. In fact, the existing linguistic sciences overlook the possibility of
-such constructs.
-
-Consider the ambiguous schema '$A\supset B\&C$', expressed in words as '$C$ and
-$B$ if $A$'. An example is
-
-\begin{equation}
- \label{firstvib}
- \parbox{4in}{Jack will soon leave and Bill will laugh if Don speaks.}
-\end{equation}
-
-In order to get sense out of this utterance, the reader has to supply it with a
-comma. That is, in the jargon of logic, he has to supply it with grouping. Let
-us make the convention that in order to read the utterance, you must
-mentally supply grouping to it, or "bracket" it. If you construe the schema
-as '$A\supset (B\&C)$', you will be said to bracket the conjunction. If you construe
-the schema as '$(A\supset B)\&C$', you will be said to bracket the conditional. There
-is an immediate syntactical issue. If you are asked to copy \ref{firstvib}, do you write
-"Jack will soon leave and Bill will laugh if Don speaks"; or do you write
-"Jack will soon leave, and Bill will laugh if Don speaks" if that is the way
-you are reading \ref{firstvib} at the moment? A distinction has to be made between
-reading the proposition, which involves bracketing; and viewing the
-proposition, which involves reacting to the ink-marks solely as a pattern.
-Thus, any statement about an ambiguous grouping proposition must specify
-whether the reference is to the proposition as read or as viewed.
-
-Some additional conventions are necessary. With respect to \ref{firstvib}, we
-distinguish two possibilities: you are reading it, or you are not looking at it
-(or are only viewing it). Thus, a "single reading" of \ref{firstvib} refers to an event
-which separates two consecutive periods of not looking at \ref{firstvib} (or only
-viewing it). During a single reading, you may switch between bracketing the
-conjunction and bracketing the conditional. These switches demarcate a
-series of "states" of the reading, which alternately correspond to "Jack will
-soon leave, and Bill will laugh if Don speaks" or "Jack will soon leave and Bill
-will laugh, if Don speaks". Note that a state is like a complete proposition.
-We stipulate that inasmuch as \ref{firstvib} is read at all, it is the present meaning or
-state that counts---if you are asked what the proposition says, whether it is
-true, \etc
-
-Another convention is that the logical status of
-\begin{quotation}
-(Jack will soon leave and Bill will laugh if Don speaks) if and only if (Jack
-will soon leave and Bill will laugh if Don speaks)
-\end{quotation}
-is not that of a normal tautology, even though the biconditional when
-viewed has the form '$A\equiv A$'. The two ambiguous components will not
-necessarily be bracketed the same way in a state.
-
-We now turn to an example which is more substantial than \ref{firstvib}.
-
-Consider
-
-\begin{quotation}
-Your mother is a whore and you are now bracketing the conditional in (2) if
-you are now bracketing the conjunction in (2). (2)
-\end{quotation}
-
-If you read this proposition, then depending on how you bracket it, the
-reading will either be internally false or else will call your mother a whore. In
-general, ambiguous grouping propositions are constructs in which the mental
-aspect plays a fairly explicit role in the language. We have included (2) to
-show that the contents of these propositions can provide more complications
-than would be suggested by \ref{firstvib}.
-
-There is another way of bringing out the mental aspect of language,
-however, which is incomparably more powerful than ambiguous grouping.
-We will turn to this approach immediately, and will devote the rest of the
-paper to it. The cubical frame \cubeframe\ is a simple reversible perspective figure
-which can either be seen oriented upward like \cubeup\ or oriented downward
-like \cubedown. Both positions are implicit in the same ink-on-paper image; it is
-the subjective psychological response of the perceiver which differentiates
-the positions. The perceiver can deliberately cause the perspective to reverse,
-or he can allow the perspective to reverse without resisting. The perspective
-can also reverse against his will. Thus, there are three possibilities: deliberate,
-indifferent, and involuntary reversal.
-
-Suppose that each of the positions is assigned a different meaning, and
-the figure is used as a notation. We will adopt the following definitions
-because they are convenient for our purposes at the moment.
-
-$$ \cubeframe \left\{\parbox{4in}{for '3' if it appears to be oriented like \cubeup \linebreak
-for '0' if it appears to be oriented like \cubedown}\right\} $$
-
-We may now write
-
-\begin{equation}
- \label{cubefour}
-1+\cubeframe = 4
-\end{equation}
-
-We must further agree that \ref{cubefour}, or any proposition containing such
-notation, is to be read to mean just what it seems to mean at any given
-instant. If, at the moment you read the proposition, the cube seems to be
-up, then the proposition means $1+3=4$; but if the cube seems to be down,
-the proposition means $1+O=4$. The proposition has an unambiguous
-meaning for the reader at any given instant, but the meaning may change in
-the next instant due to a subjective psychological change in the reader. The
-reader is to accept the proposition for what it is at any instant. The result is
-subjectively triggered propositional vibration, or SPV for short. The
-distinction between reading and viewing a proposition, which we already
-made in the case of ambiguous grouping, is even more important in the case
-of SPV. Reading now occurs only when perspective is imputed. In reading
-\ref{cubefour} you don't think about the ink graph any more than you think about the
-type face.
-
-in a definition such as that of '\cubeframe', '3' and 'O' will be called the
-assignments. A single reading is defined as before. During a single reading, \ref{cubefour}
-will vibrate some number of times. The series of states of the reading, which
-alternately correspond to '$1+3=4$' or '$1+O=4$', are demarcated by
-these vibrations. The portion of a state which can change when vibration
-occurs will be called a partial. It is the partials in a reading that correspond
-directly to the assignments in the definition.
-
-Additional conventions are necessary. Most of the cases we are
-concerned with can be covered by two extremely important rules. First, the
-ordinary theory of properties which have to do with the form of expressions
-as viewed is not applicable when SPV notation is present. Not only is a
-biconditional not a tautology just because its components are the same when
-viewed; it cannot be considered an ordinary tautology even if the one
-component's states have the same truth value, as in the case of '$1+\cubeframe\neq2$'.
-Secondly, and even more important, SPV notation has to be present
-explicitly or it is not present at all. SPV is not the idea of an expression with
-two meanings, which is commonplace in English; SPV is a double meaning
-which comes about by a perceptual experience and thus has very special
-properties. Thus, if a quantifier should be used in a proposition containing
-SPV notation, the "range" of the "variable" will be that of conventional
-logic. You cannot write '\cubeframe' for '$x$' in the statement matrix
-'$x=\cubeframe$'.
-
-We must now elucidate at considerable length the uniqué properties of
-SPV. When the reader sees an SPV figure, past perceptual training will cause
-him to impute one or the other orientation to it. This phenomenon is not a
-mere convention in the sense in which new terminology is a convention.
-There are already two clear-cut possibilities. Their reality is entirely mental;
-the external, ink-on-paper aspect does not change in any manner whatever.
-The change that can occur is completely and inherently subjective and
-mental. By mental effort, the reader can consciously control the orientation.
-If he does, involuntary vibrations will occur because of neural noise or
-attention lapses. The reader can also refrain from control and accept
-whatever appears. In this case, when the figure is used as a notation,
-vibrations may occur because of a preference for one meaning over the
-other. Thus, a deliberate vibration, an involuntary vibration, and an
-indifferent vibration are three distinct possibilities.
-
-What we have done is to give meanings to the two pre-existing
-perceptual possibilities. In order to read a proposition containing an SPV
-notation at all, one has to see the ink-on-paper figure, impute perspective to
-it, and recall the meaning of that perspective; rather than just seeing the
-figure and recalling its meaning. The imputation of perspective, which will
-happen anyway because of pre-existing perceptual training, has a function in
-the language we are developing analogous to the function of a letter of the
-alphabet in ordinary language. The imputation of perspective is an aspect of
-the notation, but it is entirely mental. Our language uses not only
-graphemes, but "psychemes" or "mentemes". One consequence is that the
-time structure of the vibration series has a distinct character; different in
-principle from external, mechanical randomization, or even changes which
-the reader would produce by pressing a button. Another consequence is that
-ambiguous notation in general is not equivalent to SPV. There can be mental
-changes of meaning with respect to any ambiguous notation, but in general
-there is no psycheme, no mental change of notation. It is the clear-cut,
-mental, involuntary change of notation which is the essence of SPV. Without
-psychemes, there can be no truly involuntary mental changes of meaning.
-
-In order to illustrate the preceding remarks, we will use an SPV
-notation defined as follows.
-
-\begin{equation*}
- \cubeframe \left\{\parbox{4in}{is an affirmative, read "definitely," if it appears to be oriented
- like \cubeup\linebreak
- is a negative, read "not," if it appears to be oriented like \cubedown}\right\}
-\end{equation*}
-
-The proposition which follows refers to the immediate past, not to all past
-time; that is, it refers to the preceding vibration.
-
-\begin{quotation}
-You have \cubeframe deliberately vibrated (4). (4)
-\end{quotation}
-
-
-This proposition refers to itself, and its truth depends on an aspect of the
-reader's subjectivity which accompanies the act of reading. However, the
-same can be said for the next proposition.
-
-\begin{quotation}
-The bat is made of wood, and you have just decided that the second
-word in (5) refers to a flying mammal. (5)
-\end{quotation}
-
-
-Further, the same can be said for (2). We must compare (5), (2), and (4) in
-order to establish that (4) represents an order of language entirely different
-from that represented by (5) and (2). (5) is a grammatical English sentence
-as it stands, although an abnormal one. The invariable, all-ink notation 'bat'
-has an equivocal referental structure: it may have either of two mutually
-exclusive denotations. In reading, the native speaker of English has to choose
-one denotation or the other; contexts in which the choice is difficult rarely
-occur. (2) is not automatically grammatical, because it lacks a comma. We
-have agreed on a conventional process by which the reader mentally supplies
-the comma. Thus, the proposition lacks an element and the reader must
-supply it by a deliberate act of thought. The comma is not, strictly speaking,
-a notation, because it is entirely voluntary. The reader might as well be
-supplying a denotation io an equivocal expression: (5) and (2) can be
-reduced to the same principle. As for (4), it cannot be mistaken for ordinary
-English. It has an equivocal "proto-notation," '\cubeframe'. You automatically
-impute perspective to the proto-notation before you react to it as language.
-Thus, a notation with a mental component comes into being involuntarily.
-This notation has an unequivocal denotation. However, deliberate,
-inditferent, and most important of all, involuntary mental changes in
-notation can occur.
-
-We now suggest that the reader actually read (5), (2), and (4), in that
-order. We expect that (5) can be read without noticeable effort, and that a
-fixed result will be arrived at {unless the reader switches in an attempt to
-find a true state). The reading of (2) involves mentally supplying the comma,
-which is easy, and comprehending the logical compound which . results,
-which is not as easy. Again, we expect that a fixed result will be arrived at
-(unless the reader vacillates between the insult and the internally false state).
-In order to read (4), center your sight on the SPV notation, with your
-peripheral vision taking in the rest of the sentence. A single reading should
-last at least half a minute. If the reader will seriously read (4), we expect that
-he will find the reading to be an experience of a totally different order from
-the reading of (5) and (2). It is like looking at certain confusing visual
-patterns, but with an entire dimension added by the incorporation of the
-pattern into language. The essence of the experience, as we have indicated, is
-that the original imputation of perspective is involuntary, and that the reader
-has to contend with involuntary changes in notation for which his own mind
-is responsible. We are relying on this experience to convince the reader
-empirically that (4) represents a new order of language to an extent to which
-(5) and (2) do not.
-
-To make our point even clearer, let us introduce an operation, called
-"collapsing," which may be applied to propositions containing SPV
-proto-notation. The operation consists in redefining the SPV figure in a given
-proposition so that its assignments are the states of the original proposition.
-Let us collapse (4). We redefine
-
-\begin{equation*}
- \cubeframe \left\{\parbox{4in}{for 'You have deliberately vibrated (4)' if it appears to be oriented
- like \cubeup\linebreak
- for 'You have not deliberately vibrated (4)' if it appears to be oriented
- like \cubedown}\right\}
-\end{equation*}
-
-(4) now becomes
-
-\begin{quotation}
-\cubeframe (4)
-\end{quotation}
-
-
-We emphasize that the reader must actually read (4), for the effect is
-indescribable. The reader should learn the assignments with flash cards if
-necessary.
-
-The claim we want to make for (4) is probably that it is the most
-clear-cut case yet constructed in which thought becomes an object for itself.
-Just looking at a reversible perspective figure which is not a linguistic
-utterance---an approach which perceptual psychologists have already
-tried---does not yield results which are significant with respect to "thought."
-In order to obtain a significant case, the apparent orientation or imputed
-perspective must be a proposition; it must be true or false. Then, (5) and (2)
-are not highly significant, because the mental act of supplying the missing
-element of the proposition is all a matter of your volition; and because the
-element supplied is essentially an "understood meaning." We already have an
-abundance of understood meanings, but scientists have been able to ignore
-them because they are not "objectifiable." In short, reversible perspective by
-itself is not "thought"; equivocation by itself has no mental aspect which is
-objectifiable. Only in reading (4) do we experience an "objectifiable aspect
-of thought." We have invented an instance of thought (as opposed to
-perception) which can be accomodated in the ontology of the perceptual
-psychologist.
+\input{essays/admissible_contradictions.tex}
+\input{essays/propositional_vibration.tex}
\end{document}
diff --git a/essays/down_with_art.tex b/essays/down_with_art.tex
index 176b9ff..23268a2 100644
--- a/essays/down_with_art.tex
+++ b/essays/down_with_art.tex
@@ -1,5 +1,5 @@
{
-\centering\specialheadersfont\Large
+\centering\sffamily
Down With Art \\
\par
}
diff --git a/essays/letters.tex b/essays/letters.tex
index 455a41b..fc5db5a 100644
--- a/essays/letters.tex
+++ b/essays/letters.tex
@@ -1,6 +1,6 @@
\chapter{Letters}
-\section{Letter from Terry Riley, Paris, to Henry Flynt, Cambridge,
+\section*{Letter from Terry Riley, Paris, to Henry Flynt, Cambridge,
Mass., dated 11/8/62}
One day a little boy got up and looked at his toys, appraised them and
@@ -39,7 +39,7 @@ will show us how to really enjoy ourselves. Whooopeeee
\clearpage
-\section{letter from Bob Morris to Henry Flynt, dated 8/13/62}
+\section*{Letter from Bob Morris to Henry Flynt, dated 8/13/62}
Dear Henry,
@@ -83,7 +83,7 @@ One accepts language, one accepts logic.
\signoff{Best regards,}
\signoff{Bob Morris}
-\section{}
+\section*{}
{
\raggedleft
@@ -153,7 +153,7 @@ touched on the Wednesday demonstrations. He spoke of George Maciunas'
congratulated Flynt on the clarity of the presentation and logicality of the
arguments. Photos were taken.
-\section{Statement of November 1963}
+\section*{Statement of November 1963}
Back in March 1963, I sent the first \textsc{FCTB Press Release}, about FCTB's
@@ -167,7 +167,7 @@ idiotic ones (although they got in '\textsc{No More Art/Culture?}', later on),
and added incidents; but the general outlines, and the phrases lifted verbatim
from the FCTB RELEASE, make the relationship clear.---Henry Fiynt
-\section{}
+\section*{}
{ \raggedleft 3/6/63 \par }
@@ -209,7 +209,7 @@ drudgery---send me a copy if you can.
\signoff{Best regards,}
\signoff{Bob Morris}
-\section{}
+\section*{}
{ \raggedleft 3/12/1963 \par }
Henry
@@ -268,7 +268,7 @@ people off---and let them wait for the next revision or explication.
\signoff{Walter DeMaria}
-\section{}
+\section*{}
Dear Henry, March 18, 1963
@@ -289,7 +289,7 @@ Yours,
Diane Wakoski
-\section{}
+\section*{}
"Dear Mr. Flynt...Since I may be depending on o-ganized culture for my
loot \& livelihood I can wish you only a limited success in your movement...