summaryrefslogtreecommitdiffstats
path: root/essays/post_formalism_memories.tex
diff options
context:
space:
mode:
authorp <grr@lo2.org>2024-11-27 23:07:58 -0500
committerp <grr@lo2.org>2024-11-27 23:07:58 -0500
commit614bc606467643792652386aa71fe6f006f06282 (patch)
treedc427a232cea66535b45511bf116e8ea294dda45 /essays/post_formalism_memories.tex
parent01045ca62b4b4f6a635b156365f2cd3bd2d8460a (diff)
downloadblueprint-614bc606467643792652386aa71fe6f006f06282.tar.gz
mathematical studies up to innperseqs diagram
Diffstat (limited to 'essays/post_formalism_memories.tex')
-rw-r--r--essays/post_formalism_memories.tex717
1 files changed, 0 insertions, 717 deletions
diff --git a/essays/post_formalism_memories.tex b/essays/post_formalism_memories.tex
deleted file mode 100644
index 0c867a2..0000000
--- a/essays/post_formalism_memories.tex
+++ /dev/null
@@ -1,717 +0,0 @@
-\newcommand{\midheading}[1]{
- { \vskip 1em \centering \large \textsc{#1} \par \vskip 1em }}
-
-
-\chapter{Post-Formalism in Constructed Memories}
-
-\section{Post-Formalist Mathematics}
-
-\fancyhead{} \fancyfoot{} \fancyfoot[LE,RO]{\thepage}
-\fancyhead[LE]{\textsc{Post-Formalism in Constructed Memories}} \fancyhead[RO]{\textit{Post-Formalist Mathematics}}
-
-Over the last hundred years, a philosophy of pure mathematics has
-grown up which I prefer to call \enquote{formalism.} As Willard Quine says in the
-fourth section of his essay "Carnap and Logical Truth,' formalism was
-inspired by a series of developments which began with non-Euclidian
-geometry. Quine himself is opposed to formalism, but the formalists have
-found encouragement in Quine's own book, \booktitle{Mathematical Logic}. The best
-presentation of the formalist position can be found in Rudolph Carnap's
-\booktitle{The Logical Syntax of Language}. As a motivation to the reader, and
-as a heuristic aid, I will relate my study to these two standard books. (It will
-heip if the reader is thoroughly familiar with them.) it is not important
-whether Carnap, or Quine, or formalism---or my interpretation of them---is
-\enquote{correct,} for this essay is neither history nor philosophy. I am using history
-as a bridge, to give the reader access to some extreme mathematical
-innovations.
-
-The formalist position goes as follows. Pure mathematics is the
-manipulation of the meaningless and arbitrary, but typographically
-well-defined ink-shapes on paper
-`$w$,' `$x$,' `$y$,' `$z$,'
-`\texttt{'},'
-`$($,' `$)$,'
-`$\downarrow$,' and `$\in$.'
-These shapes are manipulated according to arbitrary but well-defined
-mechanical rules. Actually, the rules mimic the structure of primitive
-systems such as Euclid's geometry. There are formation rules, mechanical
-definitions of which concatenations of shapes are \enquote{\term{sentences}.} One sentence
-is `$((x) (x\in x) \downarrow (x) (x\in x))$.' There are transformation rules, rules for the
-mechanical derivation of sentences from other sentences. The best known
-transformation rule is the rule that $\psi$ may be concluded from $\varphi$ and
-$\ulcorner \varphi \supset \psi \urcorner$;
-where `$\supset$' is the truth-functional conditional. For later convenience, I will
-say that $\varphi$ and $\ulcorner \varphi \supset \psi \urcorner$ are \enquote{\term{impliors},}
-and that $\psi$ is the \enquote{\term{implicand}.}
-Some sentences are designated as \enquote{\term{axioms}.} A \enquote{\term{proof}} is a series of
-sentences such that each is an axiom or an implicand of preceding sentences.
-The last sentence in a proof is a \enquote{\term{theorem}.}
-
-This account is ultra-simplified and non-rigorous, but it is adequate for
-my purposes. (The reader may have noticed a terminological issue here. For
-Quine, an implication is merely a logically true conditional. The rules which
-are used to go from some statements to others, and to assemble proofs, are
-rules of inference. The relevant rule of inference is the \term{modus ponens};\editornote{i.e., "$P$ implies $Q$. $P$ is true. Therefore, $Q$ must also be true."} $\psi$ is
-the ponential of $\varphi$ and $\ulcorner \varphi \supset \psi \urcorner$. What I
-am doing is to use a terminology of
-implication to talk about rules of inference and ponentials. The reason is
-that the use of Quine's terminology would result in extremely awkward
-formulations. What I will be doing is sufficiently transparent that it can be
-translated into Quine's terminology if necessary. My results will be
-unaffected.) The decisive feature of the arbitrary game called \enquote{mathematics}
-is as follows. A sentence-series can be mechanically checked to determine
-whether it is a proof. But there is no mechanical method for deciding
-whether a sentence is a theorem. Theorems, or rather their proofs, have to be
-puzzled out, to be discovered. in this feature lies the dynamism, the
-excitement of traditional mathematics. Traditional mathematical ability is
-the ability to make inferential discoveries.
-
-A variety of branches of mathematics can be specialized out from the
-basic system. Depending on the choices of axioms, systems can be
-constructed which are internally consistent, but conflict with each other. A
-system can be \enquote{interpreted,} or given a meaning within the language of a
-science such as physics. So interpreted, it may have scientific value, or it may
-not. But as pure mathematics, all the systems have the same arbitrary status.
-
-By \enquote{formalist mathematics} I will mean the present mathematical
-systems which are presented along the above lines. Actually, as many authors
-have observed, the success of the non-Euclidian \enquote{imaginary} geometries
-made recognition of the game-like character of mathematics inevitable.
-Formalism is potentially the greatest break with tradition in the history of
-mathematics. In the \essaytitle{Foreward} to \booktitle{The Logical Syntax of Language}, Carnap
-brilliantly points out that mathematical innovation is still hindered by the
-widespread opinion that deviations from mathematical tradition must be
-justified---that is, proved to be \enquote{correct} and to be a faithful rendering of
-\enquote{the true logic.} According to Carnap, we are free to choose the rules of a
-mathematical system arbitrarily. The striving after correctness must cease, so
-that mathematics will no longer be hindered. \enquote{\emph{Before us lies the boundless
-ocean of unlimited possibilities.}} In other words, Carnap, the most reputable
-of academicians, says you can do anything in mathematics. Do not worry
-whether whether your arbitrary game corresponds to truth, tradition, or
-reality: it is still legitimate mathematics. Despite this wonderful \uline{Principle of
-Tolerance} in mathematics, Carnap never ventured beyond the old
-ink-on-paper, axiomatic-deductive structures. I, however, have taken Carnap
-at his word. The result is my \enquote{post-formalist mathematics.} I want to stress
-that my innovations have been legitimized in advance by one of the most
-reputable academic figures of the twentieth century.
-
-Early in 1961, I constructed some systems which went beyond
-formalist mathematics in two respects.
-\begin{enumerate}[label=\arabic*.,nosep,itemsep=0.5em]
- \item My sentential elements are physically different from the little ink-shapes on paper used in all formalist systems. My sentences are physically different from concatenations of ink-shapes. My transformation rules have nothing to do with operations on ink-shapes.
-
-\item My systems do not necessarily follow the axiomatic-deductive,
-sen\-ten\-ce-implication-axiom-proof-theorem structure.
-\end{enumerate}
-\vskip 0.5em
-
- Both of these
-possibilities, by the way, are mentioned by Carnap in \essaytitle{Languages as
-Calculi.}\editornote{Also in \booktitle{The Logical Syntax of Language}.} A \enquote{post-formalist system,} then, is a formalist system which differs
-physically from an ink-on-paper system, or which lacks the
-axiomatic-deductive structure.
-
-As a basis for the analysis of post-formalist systems, a list of structural
-properties of formalist systems is desirable. Here is such a list. By
-\enquote{implication} I will mean simple, direct implication, unless I say otherwise.
-\vskip 0.5em
-\begin{enumerate}[nosep, itemsep=0.5em]
-\item A sentence can be repeated at will.
-
-\item The rule of implication refers to elements of sentences: sentences
-are structurally composite.
-
-\item A sentence can imply itself.
-
-\item The repeat of an implior can imply the repeat of an implicand: an
-implication can be repeated.
-
-\item Different impliors can imply different implicands.
-
-\item Given two or three sentences, it is possible to recognize
-mechanically whether one or two directly imply the third.
-
-\item No axiom is implied by other, different axioms.
-
-\item The definition of \enquote{proof} is the standard definition, in terms of
-implication, given early in this essay.
-
-\item Given the axioms and some other sentence, it is not possible to
-recognize mechanically whether the sentence is a theorem.
-Compound indirect implication is a puzzle.
-\end{enumerate}
-\vskip 0.5em
-
-Now for the first post-formalist system.
-
-\midheading{\sysname{Illusions}}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-A \term{sentence} is the page (page \pageref{illusions}, with figure \ref{illusions} on it) so long as the
-apparent, perceived ratio of the length of the vertical line to that
-of the horizontal line (the statement's \enquote{associated ratio}) does not
-change. (Two sentences are the \enquote{same} if end only if their
-associated ratios are the same.)
-
-A sentence $Y$ is \term{implied by} a sentence $X$ if and only if $Y$ is the same as $X$,
-or else $Y$ is, of all the sentences one ever sees, the sentence having
-the associated ratio next smaller than that of $X$.
-
-Take as the \term{axiom} the first sentence one sees.
-
-\emph{Explanation}: The figure is an optical illusion such that the vertical line
-normally appears longer than the horizontal line, even though their
-lengths are equal. One can correct one's perception, come to see
-the vertical line as shorter relative to the horizontal line, decrease
-the associated ratio, by measuring the lines with a ruler to convince
-oneself that the vertical line is not longer than the other, and then
-trying to see the lines as equal in length; constructing similar
-figures with a variety of real (measured) ratios and practicing
-judging these ratios; and so forth.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-\begin{figure}[p]
- {\centering \includegraphics[width=4in]{img/illusions} \par}
- \caption{The sentence for \sysname{Illusions}.}
- \label{illusions}
-\end{figure}
-
-\sysname{Illusions} has Properties 1, 3--5, and 7--8. Purely to clarify this fact, the
-following sequence of integers is presented as a model of the order in which
-associated ratios might appear in reality. (The sequence is otherwise totally
-inadequate as a model of \sysname{Illusions.}) $4\medspace2\medspace1$; $4\medspace2$; $5\medspace4\medspace2\medspace1$; $4\medspace3\medspace1$. The
-implication structure would then be as shown in figure \ref{illusionstructure}.
-
-\begin{figure}
- {\centering \includegraphics[width=4.5in]{img/illusionstructure} \par}
- \caption{Example implication structure for \sysname{Illusions}.}
- \label{illusionstructure}
-\end{figure}
-
-The axiom would be 4, and 5 could not appear in a proof. \sysname{Illusions} has
-Property 1 on the basis that one can control the associated ratio. Turning to
-Property 4, it is normally the case that when an implication is repeated, a
-given occurrence of one of the sentences involved is unique to a specific
-occurrence of the implication. In \sysname{Illusions,} however, if two equal
-sentences are next smaller than $X$, the occurrence of $X$ does not uniquely
-belong to either of the two occurrences of the implication. Compare figure \ref{thestructure},
-where the occurrence of `$t$' is not unique to either occurrence of `$the$'.
-Subject to this explanation, \sysname{Illusions} has Property 4. \sysname{Illusions} has
-Property 8, but it goes without saying that the type of implication is not
-\term{modus ponens}. Properties 3, 5, and 7 need no comment. As for Property 2,
-the rule of implication refers to a property of sentences, rather than to
-elements of sentences. The interesting feature of \sysname{Illusions} is that it
-reverses the situation defined by Properties 6 and 9. Compound indirect
-implication is about the same as simple implication. The only difference is
-the difference between being smaller and being next smaller. And there is
-only one axiom (per person).
-
-\begin{figure}
- {\centering \setlength\tabcolsep{0.25em}
- \begin{tabular}{c c c} t & h & e \\ h & & \\ e & & \end{tabular} \par}
- \caption{Structure with shared node.}
- \label{thestructure}
-\end{figure}
-
-
-Simple direct implication, however, is subjective and illusive. It
-essentially involves changing one's perceptions of an illusion. The change of
-associated ratios is subjective, elusive, and certainly not numerically
-measurable. Then, the order in which one sees sentences won't always be
-their order in the implications and proofs. And even though one is exposed
-to all the sentences, one may have difficulty distinguishing and remembering
-them in consciousness. If I see the normal illusion, then manage to get
-myself to see the lines as being of equal length, I know I have seen a
-theorem. What is difficult is grasping the steps in between, the simple direct
-implications. If the brain contains a permanent impression of every sensation
-it has received, then the implications objectively exist; but they may not be
-thinkable without neurological techniques for getting at the impressions. In
-any case, \enquote{proof} is well-defined in some sense---but proofs may not be
-thinkable. \sysname{Illusions} is, after all, not so much shakier in this respect than
-even simple arithmetic, which contains undecidable sentences and
-indefinable terms.
-
-In \booktitle{The Logical Syntax of Language}, Carnap distinguishes pure syntax
-and descriptive syntax; and says that pure syntax should be independent of
-notation, and that every system should be isomorphic to some ink-on-paper
-system. In so doing, Carnap violates his own \uline{Principle of Tolerance}. Consider
-the following trivial formalist system.
-
-\midheading{\enquote{Order}}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-A \term{sentence} is a member of a finite set of integers.
-
-Sentence $Y$ is \term{implied by} sentence $X$ if and only if $Y=X$, or else of all the
-sentences, $Y$ is the one next smaller than $X$.
-
-Take as the \term{axiom} the largest sentence.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-Is the pure syntax of \sysname{Illusions} isomorphic to \sysname{Order}? The preceding
-paragraph proved that it is not. The implication structure of \sysname{Order} is
-mechanical to the point of idiocy, while the implication structure of
-\sysname{Illusions} is, as I pointed out, elusive. Figure \ref{orderstruc}
-where loops indicate multiple occurances of the same sentence, could
-adequately represent a proof in \enquote{Order,} but could not remotely represent
-one in \sysname{Illusions.} The essence of \sysname{Illusions} is that it is coupled to the
-reader's subjectivity. For an ink-on-paper system even to be comparable to
-\sysname{Illusions,} the subjectivity would have to be moved out of the reader and
-onto the paper. This is utterly impossible.
-
-\begin{figure}
- {\centering \includegraphics[width=4.5in]{img/orderstructure} \par}
- \caption{Implication structure of \sysname{Order}.}
- \label{orderstruc}
-\end{figure}
-
-Here is the next system.
-
-\midheading{\sysname{Innperseqs}}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-\emph{Explanation}: Consider the rainbow halo which appears to surround a small
-bright light when one looks at it through fogged glass (such as
-eyeglasses which have been breathed on). The halo consists of
-concentric circular bands of color. As the fog evaporates, the halo
-uniformly contracts toward the light. The halo has a vague outer
-ring, which contracts as the halo does. Of concern here is what
-happens on one contracting radius of the halo, and specifically
-what happens on the segment of that radius lying in the vague
-outer ring: the outer segment.
-
-A \term{sentence} (or \term{halopoint}) is the changing halo color at a fixed point, in
-space, in the halo; until the halo contracts past the point.
-
-Several sentences \term{imply} another sentence if and only if, at some instant,
-the several sentences are on an outer segment, and the other
-sentence is the inner endpoint of that outer segment.
-
-An \term{axiom} is a sentence which is in the initial vague outer ring (before it
-contracts), and which is not an inner endpoint.
-
-An \term{innperseq} is a sequence of sequences of sentences on one radius
-satisfying the following conditions.
- \begin{enumerate}
- \item The members of the first sequence are axioms,
- \item For each of the other sequences, the first member is implied by the non-first members of the preceding sequence; and the remaining members (if any) are axioms or first members of preceding sequences.
- \item All first members, of sequences other than the last two, appear as non-first members.
- \item No sentence appears as a non-first member more than once.
- \item The last sequence has one member.
- \end{enumerate}
-\end{sysrules}
-
-\newcommand{\innprow}[4]{
- \parbox{2.25in}{
- \parbox{0.35in}{\includegraphics[scale=0.25]{img/time#1}}
- \parbox{0.5in}{#2:}
- \parbox{1.25in}{
- \parbox{1.25in}{#3}
-
- \parbox{1.25in}{#4}}}\vskip 0.5em}
-
-\begin{figure}
-{\centering
- \parbox{0.15in}{\rotatebox[origin=c]{90}{\
- {\footnotesize Successive bands represent the vague outer ring at successive times as it fades in toward the small bright light.}}}\begin{minipage}{1.5in}
- \imgw{1.3in}{img/innperseqs}\vskip 0.1em {\centering\small small bright light \par}
- \end{minipage}\begin{minipage}{2in}
-\enquote{Sentences} at
-\vskip 1em
-
- \innprow{1}{$time_1$}{$a_1 a_2 a_3 a_4 a_5 a_6 a_7 b$}{$a_1,a_2 \rightarrow\ b$}
-
- \innprow{2}{$time_2$}{$a_2 a_3 a_4 a_5 a_6 a_7 b c$}{$a_3 \rightarrow\ c$}
-
- \innprow{3}{$time_3$}{$a_4 a_5 a_6 a_7 b c d$}{$a_4,a_5 \rightarrow\ d$}
-
- \innprow{4}{$time_4$}{$a_6 a_7 b c d e$}{$a_6,b \rightarrow\ e$}
-
- \innprow{5}{$time_5$}{$a_7 b c d e f$}{$a_7,c \rightarrow\ f$}
-
- \innprow{6}{$time_6$}{$c d e f g$}{$d,e \rightarrow\ g$}
-
- \vskip 2em
-
-\enquote{Axioms} \\
- \hskip 1em $a_1 a_2 a_3 a_4 a_5 a_6 a_7$
-
- \vskip 2em
-
-Innperseq \\
-$(a_3,a_2,a_1)$ \\
-$(b,a_3)$ \\
-$(c,a_5,a_4)$ \\
-$(d,b,a_6)$ \\
-$(e,c,a_7)$ \\
-$(f,e,d)$ \\
-$(g)$
- \end{minipage}\par}
- \vskip 1em
- \caption{Example instance of \sysname{Innperseqs.}}
- \label{innperdiag}
-\end{figure}
-
-In diagram \ref{innperdiag}, different positions of the vague outer
-ring at different times are suggested by different shadings. The
-outer segment moves \enquote{down the page.} The figure is by no means
-an innperseq, but is supposed to help explain the definition.
-In \sysname{Innperseqs,} a conventional proof would be redundant unless all
-the statements were on the same radius. And even if the weakest axiom were
-chosen (the initial outer endpoint), this axiom would imply the initial inner
-endpoint, and from there the theorem could be reached immediately. In
-other words, to use the standard definition of \enquote{\term{proof}} in \sysname{Innperseqs}
-would result in an uninteresting derivation structure. Thus, a more
-interesting derivation structure is defined, the \enquote{\term{innperseq.}} The interest of
-an \enquote{\term{innperseq}} is to be as elaborate as the many restrictions in its definition
-will allow. Proofs are either disregarded in \sysname{Innperseqs}; or else they are
-identified with innperseqs, and lack Property 8. \sysname{Innperseqs} makes the
-break with the proof-theorem structure of formalist mathematics.
-
-Turning to simple implication, an implicand can have many impliors;
-and there is an infinity of axioms, specified by a general condition. The
-system has Property 1 in the sense that a sentence can exist at different
-times and be a member of different implications. It has Property 4 in the
-sense that the sentences in a specific implication can exist at different times,
-and the implication holds as long as the sentences exist. It has Property 3 in
-that an inner endpoint implies itself. The system also has Properties 5 and 7;
-and lacks Property 2. But, as before, Properties 6 and 9 are another matter.
-Given several sentences, it is certainly possible to tell mechanically whether
-one is implied by the others. But when are you given sentences? If one can
-think the sentences, then relating them is easy---but it is difficult to think the
-sentences in the first place, even though they objectively exist. The diagram
-suggests what to look for, but the actual thinking, the actual sentences are
-another matter. As for Property 9, when \term{theorems} are identified with last
-members of innperseqs, I hesitate to say whether a derivation of a given
-sentence can be constructed mechanically. If a sentence is nearer the center
-than the axioms are, an innperseq can be constructed for it. Or can it? The
-answer is contingent. \sysname{Innperseqs} is indeterminate because of the difficulty
-of thinking the sentences, a difficulty which is defined into the system. It is
-the mathematician's capabilities at a particular instant which delimit the
-indeterminacies. Precisely because of the difficulty of thinking sentences, I
-will give several subvariants of the system.
-
-\midheading{Indeterminacy}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-A \enquote{\term{totally determinate innperseq}} is an innperseq in which one thinks all the
-sentences.
-
-An \enquote{\term{implior-indeterminate innperseq}} is an innperseq in which one thinks
-only each implicand and the outer segment it terminates.
-
-A \enquote{\term{sententially indeterminate innperseq}} is an innperseq in which one thinks
-only the outer segment, and its inner endpoint, as it progresses inward.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-
-Let us return to the matter of pure and descriptive syntax. The interest
-of \sysname{Illusions} and \sysname{Innperseqs} is precisely that their abstract structure
-cannot be separated from their physical and psychological character, and
-thus that they are not isomorphic to any conventional ink-on-paper system. I
-am trying to break through to unheard of, and hopefully significant, modes
-of implication; to define implication structures (and derivation structures)
-beyond the reach of past mathematics.
-
-\clearpage
-\section{Constructed Memory Systems}
-\fancyhead[LE]{\textsc{Post-Formalism in Constructed Memories}} \fancyhead[RO]{\textit{2. Constructed Memory Systems}}
-
-In order to understand this section, it is necessary to be thoroughly
-familiar with \essaytitle{Studies in Constructed Memories,} the essay following this
-one. (I have not combined the two essays because their approaches are too
-different.) I will define post-formalist systems in constructed memories,
-beginning with a system in an M*-Memory.\editornote{The term M*-Memory is defined on page \pageref{mstardef}.}
-
-\midheading{\enquote{Dream Amalgams}}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-A \term{sentence} is a possible method, an $A_{a_i}$. with respect to an M*-Memory.
-The sentence $A_{a_p}$ \enquote{\term{implies}} the sentence $A_{a_q}$ if and only if the $a_q$th
-M*-assertion is actually thought; and either $A_{a_q} = A_{a_p}$, or else there is
-cross-method contact of a mental state in $A_{a_q}$ with a state in $A_{a_p}$.
-
-The \term{axioms} must be chosen from sentences which satisfy two conditions.
-The mental states in the sentences must have cross-method contact
-with mental states in other sentences. And the M*-assertions
-corresponding to the sentences must not be thought.
-
-\emph{Explanation}: As \essaytitle{Studies in Constructed Memories} says, there can be
-cross-method contact of states, because a normal dream can
-combine totally different episodes in the dreamer's life into an
-amalgam.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-\sysname{Dream Amalgams} has Properties 1--5. For the first time, sentences are
-structurally composite, with mental states being the relevant sentential
-elements. Implication has an unusual character. The traditional type of
-implication, modus ponens, is \enquote{directed,} because the conditional is
-directed. Even if $\ulcorner\varphi\supset\phi\urcorner$ is true
-$\ulcorner\phi\supset\varphi\urcorner$ may not be. Now implication is also
-directed in \sysname{Dream Amalgams,} but for a very different reason.
-Cross-method contact, unlike the conditional, has a symmetric character.
-What prevents implication from being necessarily symmetrical is that the
-implicand's M*-assertion actually has to be thought, while the implior's
-M*-assertion does not. Thus, implication is both subjective and mechanical,
-it is subjective, in that it is a matter of volition which method is remembered
-to have actually: been used. It is mechanical, in that when one is
-remembering, one is automatically aware of the cross-method contacts of
-states in $A_{a_q}$. The conditions on the axioms ensure that they will have
-implications without losing Property 7.
-
-As for compound implication in \sysname{Dream Amalgams,} the organism
-with the M*-Memory can't be aware of it at all; because it can't be aware
-that at different times it remembered different methods to be the one
-actually used. (In fact, the organism cannot be aware that the system has
-Property 5, for the same reason.) On the other hand, to an outside observer
-of the M*-Memory, indirect implication is not only thinkable but
-mechanical. It is not superfluous because cross-method contact of mental
-states is not necessarily transitive. The outside observer can decide whether a
-sentence is a theorem by the following mechanical procedure. Check
-whether the sentence's M*-assertion has acually been thought; if so, check all
-sentences which imply it to see if any are axioms; if not, check all the
-sentences which imply the sentences which imply it to see if any are axioms;
-etc. The number of possible methods is given as finite, so the procedure is
-certain to terminate. Again, an unprecedented mode of implication has been
-defined.
-
-When a post-formalist system is defined in a constructed memory, the
-discussion and analysis of the system become a consequence of constructed
-memory theory and an extension of it. Constructed memory theory, which
-is quite unusual but still more or less employs deductive inference, is used to
-study post-formalist modes of inference which are anything but deductive.
-
-To aid in understanding the next system, which involves infalls in a
-$D$-Memory, here is an
-
-{ \vskip 1.5em \centering \large \framebox[1.1\width]{\enquote{Exercise to be Read Aloud}} \par\vskip 1.5em}
-
-(Read according to a timer, reading the first word at 0' 0", and prolonging
-and spacing words so that each sentence ends at the time in parentheses after
-it. Do not pause netween sentences.)
-\vskip 1em
-\begin{tabular}{ r p{2.5in} }
- ($event_1$) & All men are mortal. (17") \\
-
- ($Sentence_1=event_2$) & The first utterance lasted 17" and ended at 17"; and lasted 15" and ended 1" ago. (59") \\
-
- ($S_2=event_3$) & The second utterance lasted 42" and ended at 59": and lasted 50" and ended 2" ago. (1' 31") \\
-
- ($S_3=event_4$) & The third utterance lasted 32" and ended at 1' 31"; and lasted 40" and ended 1" ago. (2' 16") \\
-\end{tabular}
-\vskip 1em
-
-Since '32' in $S_3$ is greater than '2' in $S_2$, $S_2$ must say that $S_1$ ($=event_2$)
-ended 30" after $S_2$ began, or something equally unclear. The duration of $S_2$
-is greater than the distance into the past to which it refers. This situation is
-not a real infall, but it should give the reader some intuitive notion of an
-infall.
-
-{
- \clearpage %TODO shitty hacky way to get this unbroken
-\midheading{\enquote{Infalls}}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
- A \term{sentence} is a D-sentence, in a D-Memory such that $event_{j+1}$ is the first
-thinking of the $j$th D-sentence, for all $j$.
-
-Two sentences \enquote{imply} another if and only if all three are the same; or else
-the three are adjacent (and can be written $S_{j+1},S_j,S_{j-1}$), and are such
-that $\delta_j=x_{j+1}-x_j> z_j,$ $S^D_{j-1}$ is the implicand. (The function of $S_{j+1}$ is to
-give the duration $\delta_j=x_{j+1}-x_j$ of $S_j$. $S_j$ states that $event_j$, the first
-thinking of $S^{D}_{j-1}$, ended at a distance $z_j$ into the past, where $z_j$ is smaller
- than $S^D_j$'s own duration. Diagram \ref{infallsdiag} indicates the relations.)
-\end{sysrules}
-}
-
-\begin{figure}
- \centering
- \includegraphics[width=4in]{img/infallsdiag}
- \caption{Implication structure of example $D$-Memory infalls.}
- \label{infallsdiag}
-\end{figure}
-
-In this variety of D-Memory, the organism continuously thinks successive
-D-sentences, which are all different, just as the reader of the above exercise
-continuously reads successive and different sentences. Thus, the possibility
-of repeating a sentence depends on the possibility of thinking it while one is
-thinking another sentence---a possibility which may be far-fetched, but which
-is not explicitly excluded by the definition of a \enquote{D-Memory.} If the
-possibility is granted, then \sysname{Infalls} has Properties 1--5. Direct implication is
-completely mechanical; it is subjective only in that the involuntary
-determination of the $z_j$ and other aspects of the memory is a \enquote{subjective}
-process of the organism. Compound implication is also mechanical to an
-outside observer of the memory, but if the organism itself is to be aware of
-it, it has to perform fantastic feats of multiple thinking.
-
-\sysname{Dream Amalgams} and \sysname{Infalls} are systems constructed with
-imaginary elements, systems whose \enquote{notation} is drawn from an imaginary
-object or system. Such systems have no descriptive syntax. Imaginary objects
-were introduced into mathematics, or at least into geometry, by Nicholas
-Lobachevski, and now I am using them as a notation. For these systems to
-be nonisomorphic to any ink-on-paper systems, the mathematician must be
-the organism with the M*-Memory or the D-Memory. But this means that
-in this case, the mathematics which is nonisomorphic to any ink-on-paper
-system can be performed only in an imaginary mind.
-
-Now for a different approach. Carnap said that we are free to choose
-the rules of a system arbitrarily. Let us take Carnap literally. I want to
-construct more systems in constructed memories---so why not construct the
-system by a procedure which ensures that constructed memories are
-involved, but which is otherwise arbitrary? Why not suspend the striving
-after \enquote{interesting} systems, that last vestige of the striving after
-\enquote{correctness,} and see what happens? Why not construct the rules of a
-system by a chance procedure?
-
-To construct a system, we have to fill in the blanks in the following rule
-schema in such a way that grammatically correct sentences result.
-
-\newcommand{\blankspace}{\_\_\_\_\_\_\_\_\_\_}
-
-\midheading{Rule Schema}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-A \term{sentence} is a(n) \blankspace.
-
-Two sentences \term{imply} a third if and only if the two sentences \blankspace\ the third.
-
-An \term{axiom} is a sentence that \blankspace.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-
-I now spread the pages of \essaytitle{Studies in Constructed Memories} on the floor.
-With eyes closed, I hold a penny over them and drop it. I open my eyes and
-copy down the expressions the penny covers. By repeating this routine, I
-obtain a haphazard series of expressions concerning constructed memories. It
-is with this series that I will fill in the blanks in the rule schema. In the next
-stage, I fill the first (second, third) blank with the ceries of expressions
-preceding the-first (second, third) period in the entire series.
-
-\midheading{\sysname{Haphazard System}}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
- A \term{sentence} is a the duration $D$-sentences $\triangle\ (\mathparagraph^m)$ conclude these
-\enquote{$\Phi^*$-Reflec\-tion,} or the future Assumption voluntarily force of
-conviction for conclusion the Situation or by ongoing that this
-system? be given telling between the Situation 1.
-
-Two sentences \term{imply} a third if and only if the two sentences is\slash was
-contained not have to the acceptance that a certain and malleable
-study what an event involves material specifically mathematics:
-construct accompanies the rest, extra-linguistically image organism
-can fantasy not remembering $\Phi^*$-Memory, the future interval defined
-in dream the third.
-
-An \term{axiom} is a sentence that internally D-sentences, just as the
-\enquote{$\Phi^*$-Memory} sentences $A_{a_1}$ is $A_{a_2}$.
-
-In the final stage, I cancel the smallest number of words I have to in
-order to make the rules grammatical.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-\midheading{\sysname{Fantasied Amnesia}}
-
-\begin{sysrules}
-A \term{sentence} is a duration or the future force of conviction for the Situation
-or this system given Situation 1.
-
-Two sentences \term{imply} a third if and only if the two sentences have the
-acceptance that a certain and malleable study extra-linguistically can
-fantasy not remembering the future interval defined in the third.
-
-An \term{axiom} is a sentence that internally just sentences $A_{a_2}$.
-\end{sysrules}
-
-It becomes clear in thinking about \sysname{Fantasied Amnesia} that its
-metametamathematics is dual. Describing the construction of the rules, the
-metamathematics, by a systematic performance, is one thing. Taking the
-finished metamathematics at face value, independently of its origin, and
-studying it in the usual manner, is another. Let us take \sysname{Fantasied Amnesia}
-at face value. As one becomes used to its rules, they become somewhat more
-meaningful. I will say that an \enquote{interpretation} of a haphazard system is an
-explanation of its rules that makes some sense out of what may seem
-senseless. \enquote{Interpreting} is somewhat like finding the conditions for the
-existence of a constructed memory which seemingly cannot exist. The first
-rule of \sysname{Fantasied Amnesia} is a disjunction of three substantives. The
-\enquote{Situation} referred to in the second substantive expression is either
-Situation 1 or else an unspecified situation. The third substantive expression
-apparently means \enquote{this system, assuming Situation 1,} and refers to
-\sysname{Fantasied Amnesia} itself. The definition of \enquote{sentence} is thus meaningful,
-but very bizarre. The second rule speaks of \enquote{the acceptance} as if it were a
-written assent. The rule then speaks of a \enquote{malleable study} as \enquote{fantasying}
-something. This construction is quite weird, but let us try to accept it. The
-third rule speaks of a sentence that \enquote{sentences} (in the legal sense) a possible
-method. So much for the meaning of the rules.
-
-Turning to the nine properties of formalist systems, the reference to
-\enquote{the future interval} in the implication rule of \sysname{Fantasied Amnesia}
-indicates that the system has Property 2; and the system can perfectly well
-have Property 8. It does not have Property 6 in any known sense. Certainly
-it does have Property 9. it just might have Property 1. But as for the other
-four properties, it seems out of the question to decide whether \sysname{Fantasied
-Amnesia} has them. For whatever it is worth, \sysname{Fantasied Amnesia} is on
-balance incomparable to formalist systems.
-
-My transformation rule schema has the form of a biconditional, in
-which the right-hand clause is the operative one. If a transformation rule were to
-vary, in such a way that it could be replaced by a constant rule whose right-hand
-clause was the disjunction of the various right clauses for the variable rule,
-then the latter would vary \enquote{trivially.} I will say that a system whose
-transformation rule can vary non-trivially is a \enquote{heterodeterminate} system.
-Since I have constructed a haphazard metamathematics, why not a
-heterodeterminate metamathematics? Consider a mathematician with an
-$M$-Memory, such that each $A_{a_i}$. is the consistent use of a different
-transformation rule, a different definition of \enquote{imply,} for the mathematics
-in which the mathematician is discovering theorems. The consistent use of a
-transformation rule is after all a method---a method for finding the
-commitments premisses make, and for basing conclusions in premisses. When
-the mathematician goes to remember which rule of inference he has actually
-been using, he \enquote{chooses} which of the possible methods is remembered to
-have actually been used. This situation amounts to a heterodeterminate
-system. In fact, the metamathematics cannot even be written out this time; I
-can only describe it metametamathematically in terms of an imaginary
-memory.
-
-We are now in the realm of mathematical systems which cannot be
-written out, but can only be described metametamathematically. I will
-present a final system of this sort. It is entitled \sysname{System Such That No One
-Knows What's Going On.} One just has to guess whether this system exists,
-and if it does what it is like.\editornote{The appendix contains a presentation of this work.} The preceding remark is the
-metametamathematical description, or definition, of the system.
-
-\section{Epilogue}
-\fancyhead[LE]{\textsc{Post-Formalism in Constructed Memories}} \fancyhead[RO]{\textit{3. Epilogue}}
-
-Ever since Carnap's Principle of Tolerance opened the floodgates to
-arbitrariness in mathematics, we have been faced with the prospect of a
-mathematics which is indistinguishable from art-for-art's-sake, or
-amusement-for-amusement's-sake. But there is one characteristic which saves
-mathematics from this fate. Mathematics originated by abstraction from
-primitive technology, and is indispensable to science and technology---in
-short, mathematics has scientific applications. The experience of group
-theory has proved, I hope once and for all, the bankruptcy of that narrow
-practicality which would limit mathematics to what can currently be applied
-in science. But now that mathematics is wide open, and anything goes, we
-should be aware more than ever that scientific applicability is the only
-objective value that mathematics has. I would not have set down constructed
-memory theory and the post-formalist systems if I did not believe that they
-could be applied. When and how they will be is another matter.
-
-And what about the \enquote{validity} of formalism? The rise of the formalist
-position is certainly understandable. The formalists had a commendable,
-rationalistic desire to eliminate the metaphysical problems associated with
-mathematics. Moreover, formalism helped stimulate the development of the
-logic needed in computer technology (and also to stimulate this paper). In
-spite of the productiveness of the formalist position, however, it now seems
-beyond dispute that formalism has failed to achieve its original goals. (My
-pure philosophical writings are the last word on this issue.) Perhaps the main
-lesson to be learned from the history of formalism is that an idea does not
-have to be \enquote{true} to be productive.
-
-
-\section*{Note}
-Early versions of \sysname{Illusions} and \sysname{Innperseqs} appeared in my essay
-\essaytitle{Concept Art,} published in \booktitle{An Anthology}, ed. La Monte Young, New
-York, 1963. An early, July 1961 version of \sysname{System Such That No One
-Knows What's Going On} appeared in \journaltitle{dimension 14}, Ann Arbor, 1963,
-published by the University of Michigan College of Architecture and Design.
-